9.1 Introduction
Edmund Husserl’s work has been studied with regard to his phenomenology of the state, less so his phenomenology of law – probably because the scattered reflections on it did not seem to yield rich results.Footnote 1 However, A. Reinach, G. Husserl as well as A. Troller and others adopted phenomenological methods in their works on the philosophy of lawFootnote 2 which were particularly fruitful concerning the concept of time and law.
For legal phenomenologists, time is not a structure external to law, as it belongs to the social world and thus also to the realm of law.Footnote 3 Drawing on Edmund Husserl’s phenomenology, Adolf Reinach and Husserl’s son Gerhart emphasized the importance of time for the understanding of the nature of law. To reveal the temporality of law, both begin with a qualitative time based on the temporal dimensions of present, future and past. They then distinguished this time from an objective and external time series of ‘earlier-than/later-than’.Footnote 4 Duration or extended present thus becomes the central temporal event for this qualitative time. In this way, both legal phenomenologists opened up conceptual possibilities for the understanding of the temporality of law that is distinct from natural and other social times. However, while Gerhart Husserl was able to work with his father’s lectures on the ‘Phenomenology of Internal Time Consciousness’ published in 1928,Footnote 5 Reinach’s approaches were devised independently and, in many ways, represent pioneering work for the exploration of the temporality of law based on the earlier Realistic Phenomenology. Reinach’s early death, at the age of thirty-three, meant he only managed to deal with the temporality of law in a fragmentary way in his ‘Die apriorischen Grundlagen des bürgerlichen Rechtes’ (‘The Apriori Foundations of Civil Law’), determining it as an essential structural element of the special existence of law. Gerhart Husserl, on several occasions, analyzed questions of law and time from the perspective of transcendental phenomenology and even Heidegger’s ‘Fundamental Ontology’.Footnote 6 Even if the presented elements of a theory of time and law remain very abstract, both succeed in determining time – far more than space – as a basic dimension of law. Considering the procedural character of modern law as well as the necessary temporality and historicity of legal discourses, both Reinach and Husserl thus throw a new light on an essential aspect of the structure of law. This alone is reason enough to take a closer look at some of the key points in the writing of both.
9.2 Adolf Reinach’s Approaches to a Theory of Law and Time
Reinach accomplished for the structure of law what Rudolf Stammler worked on for its ethical content: the determination of an essential a priori.Footnote 7 Reinach focused on an ‘ontology of law’ or an ‘apriorische Gegenstandslehre’ (‘a priori theory of objects’). What, for Stammler, was the ‘correct law’ (‘Richtiges Recht’) in the sense of a ‘natural law with changing content’Footnote 8 or an unconditional ideal for all changing content of natural law.Footnote 9 was for Reinach the ‘social act’ of law.Footnote 10 Reinach took into account the changeability of the living conditions of law but maintained that the content of positive law has its origin in a priori structures of legal social acts.Footnote 11 While Stammler’s ideal form allows for changing natural law content as a measure of positive law, Reinach viewed every social act that produces positive law as having an a priori nature.Footnote 12 This essence is not normative for positive law but contains its substantial characteristics. At the same time, this essence gives the ontological foundation of contingent positive law. Reinach’s approach distinguishes him from both legal positivists and natural law theorists: He is not looking for essential normative foundations of positive law or of right principles in a moral sense of natural law theory but for the essence of concrete legal rules. Reinach saw the temporality between the timelessness of logical and mathematical objects on the one hand and the simple being in time of physical and psychological objects on the other as belonging to the a priori structures of law.
For Reinach, the neglected study of the specific temporal structure of legal objects by his contemporaries was a major reason for his phenomenological analysis of the a priori foundations of law.Footnote 13 Legal ontology is supposed to lead us to new kinds of objects, which differ in structure from nature, namely the objects of psychology and ideal things. While temporality is an important element of their structure,Footnote 14 Reinach did not elaborate on his phenomenology of the temporality of law systematically. It is almost like Augustine, whom Reinach quoted with a statement from the ‘Confessiones’: ‘If you do not ask me what it is, I believe that I know. But if you ask me, then I no longer know it’.Footnote 15 Augustine then developed his theory of time from this question. Reinach leaves us with many ideas regarding a phenomenology of time in his works,Footnote 16 although in them he criticizes sciences that are only concerned with proving the existence of certain phenomena ‘at some point of objective time’.Footnote 17 He deemed that just as it would be wrong to describe the essence of red in physical terms of wavelength oscillations, it is also wrong to base the temporality resulting from the essence of law on an objective time.Footnote 18 The mistake here lies in trying to explain a color by using something else, in this case, a limited metric like the wavelength of light. As such, Reinach’s phenomenology sought to avoid this problem by leading to the essence of the experienced phenomenon itself. To do this, he claimed that we have to ‘put ourselves in the place’ (‘hineinversetzen’) of law and its temporality and not try to explain it through something else.Footnote 19 Therefore, both the timelessness of the a priori foundations of law and the temporality of positive law tell us something important about Reinach’s view of the nature of law. Both aspects are grounded in the structures of this essence (‘Sein’/‘Being’) of law, which constitutes the legal a priori.
9.2.1 The Timelessness of the Legal A Priori
If one were to analyze law exclusively in terms of positivist legal theories, then, according to Reinach, one could only observe the constant changes in its enactment and expiration over time – where time means natural (astronomical or atomic) time.Footnote 20 One could neither demonstrate the generalizable structures of law nor do justice to legal temporality.Footnote 21 However, law does not neatly fall into a seemingly given and objective time and history but has its specific temporality which only becomes clear once its a priori structures are revealed.
Like the classical theories of law and time, Reinach also began with the timeless structures of law. However, unlike ancient and medieval metaphysics and their natural law theories,Footnote 22 he did not presuppose the existence of eternal laws. Nevertheless, Reinach shared their goal: the search for eternal truths that underlie the law:Footnote 23 ‘We are concerned with descending down to the ultimate elements of right, which that authority cannot “create”, and to the essential laws, to which it is indeed not bound but which have an eternal being which it cannot touch’.Footnote 24 Neither induction and abstraction from positive law nor new legal principles are sufficient to demonstrate the existence of prepositive legal principles as the latter exist independently and have timeless validity. Here, Reinach follows Edmund Husserl’s concept of the ‘material apriori’Footnote 25 in the early phase of his eidetic-realistic approach.Footnote 26 Any new period of history will likely negate these abstractions, and new legal principles will have to change with new moral convictions and economic developments. Law and jurisprudence gain their principles from the ‘constantly changing content from the content of the times’.Footnote 27 However, this does not mean that the a priori legal structures change with positive law. Rather, every sentence of positive law is necessarily preceded by an a priori structure: ‘[T]hese structures and relations subsist antecedent to law; they are not defined by reference to it’, as Duxbury puts it.Footnote 28
Like other German legal theorists at the end of the nineteenth century, Reinach wanted to base jurisprudence as a scientific discipline on principles that were timeless as in other sciences.Footnote 29 What stood in the way, in his view, was the positivist assumption that all law – in form and substance – was produced by social action and that no legal foundations can be found prior to this production: ‘We really do find what one has so emphatically denied: the positive law finds the legal concepts which enter into it; in absolutely no way does it produce them’.Footnote 30 Reinach argued that the foundations of law are not exhausted in their positive form and only positivism dwells on the laws of ought created by the legislator himself, while legal ontology goes back to the laws of being.Footnote 31 Furthermore, he noted that the search for nonpositive foundations of law does not have to resort to purely formal, logical or methodological principles nor does law find its independent foundation merely in eternal material principles alone, as the doctrine of natural law asserts. Rather, for him all law is based on structures which it does not create, but which it must presuppose. Reinach laid great stress on the assumption that there are principles of all positive law that ‘are independent of our grasp of them, just as are the laws of mathematics’.Footnote 32 These constitute the being or essence of law.Footnote 33 Thereby Reinach wanted to establish law as an independent sphere between physics or psychology and logic.Footnote 34 Ontology is supposed to give us insights into the essential structures of independent objects. It is to teach us about the essential foundations of law ‘which stand in themselves and are timelessly valid’.Footnote 35 Thus, unlike Immanuel Kant’s approach, Reinach held that the a priori foundations are not transcendental conditions of the possibility of knowledge, but of being itself.
The whole purpose of his ‘Apriori Foundations of Civil Law’ is to analyze these ‘essential laws’ with an ‘eternal being’.Footnote 36 Positive law can depart from them and even ignore them but is still based on them. They subsist in positive law and are already there when it formulates its propositions.Footnote 37 For Reinach, positive law is therefore neither cognitively nor normatively conditioned by the a priori structures but rather by social fact. Positive law can indeed deviate from such structures, although it can never change them. If the connection is true, then positive law is the embodiment of these a priori structures. The temporal legal acts then temporalize the timeless a priori structures: Whenever an event occurs at moment M, a certain consequence F (e.g., a claim) must occur. This ‘clear determination of temporal existence’ by the a priori legal structures creates a certainty of orientation.Footnote 38 The pure concepts of law are embedded in these structuresFootnote 39 and the search for them is also a legitimate concern of natural law doctrines.Footnote 40 These doctrines were wrong not to take into account the changeable conditions of life on which the validity of such permanent principles is based. Despite this critique of natural law, however, Reinach tried to avoid falling into the trap of positivist theories. While some natural law theories assume timeless or even variable but not arbitrarily changeable principles of good, correct positive law, the a priori structures necessarily underlie all law – morally good as well as bad. The a priori foundations of law do not denote a higher or better law but simply the essence of law as it is.Footnote 41
9.2.2 The Temporality of Law
As with his consideration of many other aspects of law, Reinach did not develop a full theory of its temporality. However, he emphasized the temporality of law as an important structure and gave many examples of it. The following traces these examples and brings them together within the framework of some common principles.
According to Reinach, when one looks at legal entities and structures from a phenomenological perspective, one can recognize a separate group of objects with their own mode of existence. These objects ‘do not belong to nature in the proper sense, which are neither physical nor psychical and which are at the same time different from all ideal objects in virtue of their temporality’.Footnote 42 Their temporality is a crucial factor in understanding the nature of legal objects. As such, the following begins by looking at Reinach’s notions of temporality and then presents his theoretical approaches to social and legal time.
9.2.2.1 Time and Space
Reinach developed a conception of the temporality of legal objects between the timelessness of the essential foundations of law and the temporality of natural objects. The a priori foundations of law have an atemporal nature: They exist without relation to a specific time. While we have seen that Reinach calls them ‘eternal’, this timelessness of the a priori foundations of law tells us little about the temporality of law itself. Reinach wanted to show that in addition to natural things which are, of course, ‘in’ time, there are also objects of knowledge in the form of social acts which exist in their own temporal world.Footnote 43 In addition to their characteristic need to be consciously perceived (‘Vernehmungsbedürftigkeit’) and the presence of other characteristics common to social acts, namely intentionality, spontaneity and other-directedness, their temporality is an essential feature.Footnote 44 Social acts exist in their ‘own world of temporal … objects’ (in German: ‘eigene Welt zeitlicher … Gegenständlichkeiten’).Footnote 45 However, we already know that Reinach assumed that all law is based on a timeless foundation of the being or essence of its principles. This must also include the ontological foundations of the temporal structures of law itself. Just as law has an independent being that distinguishes it from all other objects, it also has a time structure that is not simply absorbed into the time structure of logical, natural things or the psyche. As little can be determined of the necessary properties of law from an examination of positive law alone, similarly, little can be determined about law’s temporal structure by examining only its historical emergence and passing away or from dates, periods, deadlines and so forth. As such, Reinach sought the foundations of the temporality of law in its a priori foundation.
For Reinach, the concept of temporality (‘Zeitlichkeit’) is logically ambiguous. The diagnosed ambivalence lies in the fact that processes ‘constitute themselves in time … but a thing is in time’.Footnote 46 Here, the preposition ‘in’ is used for both processes and things. For clarity’s sake, instead of ‘constitute’ and ‘are’, one could probably be allowed to say that processes bring themselves forth in time and things fall into time. Thus, by virtue of ‘constituting’, processes have a more active relation to time than things. It will soon become apparent that this difference between an active ‘bringing forth’ and a passive ‘falling into time’ is important for the temporality of social acts and law. Furthermore, Reinach held that processes are built up over time: they come into being, last for a while and then come to an end.Footnote 47 In contrast, states (‘Zustände’) lack this dynamic: they are in a certain sense complete and exist for a while, so they last. Whether one agrees with this or not, it is clear how Reinach tried to identify essential temporal differences between the phenomena of ‘process’ and ‘state’.Footnote 48 From an ontological perspective, this is precisely where ideal, natural and social or legal objects differ: Ideal objects are timeless – like the a priori foundations of law; natural objects fall into a time that is external to them while social and especially legal objects bring forth a particular characteristic of time. This is true even if they, in a certain respect, also fall into a natural time and may refer to natural time. Nevertheless, this relation to natural time remains external to them. With the foregoing in mind, it seems appropriate to provide a closer analysis of Reinach’s approach.
Reinach distinguished space, time and duration as different forms of continuity.Footnote 49 One finds continuity in both a line that is spatially continuous and a duration that is temporally continuous. What such a line and duration have in common is that their continuity is not composed of their parts. That is to say that many points do not result in a continuous line, nor do many moments result in a continuous time. They can only limit the continuum, not create it: Just as the beginning and end points limit a straight line, moments can limit time. However, this does not change the fact that time remains a continuum and even its smallest part does not become a moment. The parts of time always remain time and do not become something else, namely noncontinuous moments. Duration is a temporal continuum, however, according to Reinach, it can be interrupted. Thus, he argued that when it is divided, there is no duration between the two ‘pieces’ of duration, only time. This is because duration refers to a process that starts, goes on for a while and then stops. It is, therefore, characterized by the process and the process takes time. Duration is that which has a beginning and an end in time.Footnote 50 Because the process consumes something of time, it presupposes time. Although the process produces its duration, it leaves the primary time unchanged and can therefore be measured by it. This is why Reinach also speaks of time as the ‘primary’ and duration as the ‘secondary’ continuum. Duration, however, is peculiar to the process, ‘Every process has its duration, which belongs to it alone, while several processes can take place in the same time’.Footnote 51 One could say, then, that duration is time that is determined by a process, in that this process begins, has a certain course and ends. The consideration provided here will, therefore, call the temporality of duration based on the nature of social acts as processes ‘qualitative time’. In contrast, following Reinach’s terminology, time as a ‘primary continuum’ is not characterized by processes and, it is therefore referred to here as ‘objective time’.Footnote 52
Not all temporal phenomena are continua, for example, moments.Footnote 53 The beginning and end of the durations are moments that are not continuous, although they are still temporal. They have a different temporal structure than the duration that they limit and the time to which they refer. They depend on the process whose beginning and end they mark. Moments do not become, they simply are. Similarly, a state (‘Zustand’) does not become, it just is. Processes, however, become. Additionally, if this becoming has the temporality of duration, then Reinach can say that moments and states are nontemporal,Footnote 54 however, they still refer to objective time.
The difference between the line as a space continuum and the duration as a time continuum lies in their genesis. Reinach did not seem to accept Kant’s view that the unity of such a line can be explained by the temporal activity of drawing it.Footnote 55 It is not subjective consciousness or activity that creates the distance or the duration, it is the particular quality of the process. What is important for an understanding of the temporality of law, however, is the duration. Social acts are the processes that create duration and, correspondingly, legal acts such as a promise or a determination produce legal duration. This duration of legal processes as a temporal phenomenon can then also be related to the time they take. Thus, social time is not constituted by a line of independently fixed points in time that are earlier or later in the sense of an arrow of time but by the relative social acts that shape the present and, in relation to it, the future and the past. Social time – and with it legal time – is relative to the associated acts. The fact that social acts and law have their own temporality does not mean that they cannot be related to natural time, which can be measured by clocks. However, for Reinach, it was something else to examine the particular kind of present – instantaneous or extended in time – and to answer this question in the essence of the act or to relate it to measurable time.Footnote 56
If one accepts the validity of Reinach’s approach, he can help to understand that, firstly, the qualitative time of duration becomes an expression of the essence of processes, secondly, that these processes are social acts, and, therefore, thirdly, that unlike a spatialized time of ‘earlier than’ or ‘later than’, this concept of time is relative and not absolute.
9.2.2.2 Legal Temporality Based on Social Acts
For Reinach, the general ability to endure is a prerequisite for becoming a subject of law.Footnote 57 Mathematical objects do not have this ability. They do not participate in the coming into being and passing away of judged and measured natural things as, among other things, they are extratemporal.Footnote 58 Feelings and other mental events arise and pass away with a corresponding mental agitation. Legal entities such as a right or obligation are neither extratemporal nor do they arise or pass away with a psychical impulse or as a result of simple natural events. They continue even after the psychic impulse has ceased and independently of natural events unless the law explicitly refers to them.Footnote 59 This duration is necessarily part of the essence of the claim, as Reinach pointed out: Legal objects ‘seem to be temporal objects of a special kind of which one has not yet taken notice’.Footnote 60 This temporal structure – that they are neither merely natural-temporal nor extratemporal – is essential to legal objects.Footnote 61
First of all, it is noticeable that Reinach did not base his analysis of the a priori foundations of law on the concept of norms as, for example, Hans Kelsen does, but on social acts that can bring about ‘determinations’ (‘Bestimmungen’) as ‘normations’ (‘Normierungen’).Footnote 62 Not only does he criticize the polysemy of the term ‘norm’Footnote 63 but his starting point is different. Following Reinach, in contrast to natural law theories, not even the a priori foundations of law produce normative permissions or prohibitions.Footnote 64 They are ‘eternal laws of being’, not normative propositions.Footnote 65 If one adds the a priori structures, one can say that eternal a priori laws of being lay the foundation for the temporal social acts that produce ‘being-ought’ (‘Sein-Sollen’) through ‘determinations’. This is an essential preliminary decision for the temporality of law: whereas norms, as propositions, ought to aim at binding the future, the primary time dimension of acts is the present. Reinach even admitted that the ought-to-beFootnote 66 set by a legislator cannot be realized immediately. He distinguishes this from a provision in private law, which – like the waiver of a right – has immediate effect.Footnote 67 However, he avoids the consequence that in a legal system these legislative provisions – and thus norms – are the normal case that only provide the framework for the directly effective ‘determinations’. In other words, the legislator’s binding of the future only creates the legal precondition for the immediate effectiveness of civil law provisions.
Reinach, in contrast, started from the social act that is effective now and looks from there to the future binding of the ought-to-be. Social acts are intentional and spontaneous actions that are directed at another person and must be consciously perceived by that person.Footnote 68 The norm is, therefore, simply something that social acts can produce. In any case, in this way, he fails to conceptualize the structural principle of the hierarchical construction of norms as future obligations, which is characteristic of differentiated modern legal systems. Therefore, he misses a characteristic element of differentiated modern legal systems, according to which the determination of norms takes place in a tiered system of competences and procedures (‘Stufenbau der Rechtsordnung’). What is crucial to understand here is that by focusing on the social act as the foundation of law rather than the norm, the present becomes the defining dimension of the law rather than the future obligation.
The temporality of social acts is thus the basis for the temporality of law. In this sense, for example, conviction and assertion differ essentially in their temporality: While a conviction lasts, an assertion has no temporal extension.Footnote 69 As was the case for Franz Brentano, the present is also the central temporal dimension for Reinach. When a social act is performed, ‘something new enters the world’Footnote 70 and ‘something is thereby changed in the world’.Footnote 71 The social world of ‘other-directedness’ is not as it was before. Therefore, the social act is historical. In contrast, the past only generates ‘cold knowledge’.Footnote 72 Moreover, social acts have a teleological structure, namely they are aimed at a future event.Footnote 73 The minimal future event is that social acts become effective only when they are consciously perceived (‘vernommen’) or the addressee becomes aware of them (‘innewerden’).Footnote 74 Such a social act can be aimed at or produce a certain future, just as a question may be phrased in a manner that elicits a particular response. In the case of the social act of questioning, an extended present is simultaneously created in which the questioner waits for the answer.Footnote 75 Much natural time may pass during the waiting period, which can be measured with a watch, however, the question lasts until it is answered or until an answer can no longer be expected. The expression of the answer is a responding act that closes the future opened up by the question.Footnote 76 Successful communication requires the simultaneity of speaking and listening.Footnote 77 The fact that this time is also measurable in a natural time is not essential to communication, but only an external circumstance. If one follows Reinach to this point, one must distinguish duration, which is an expression of the subject, from this external relation to a time.
However, for Reinach not all social actions have the present as their characteristic temporal dimension as many may have a nature that is related to the past. When one apologizes, congratulates, thanks, praises and so forth, such acts necessarily refer to the past.Footnote 78 Other social actions cannot refer to the past, such as obligation and demand, which refer to the future.Footnote 79
9.2.2.3 The Temporality of Legal Acts
As noted above, for Reinach many social acts refer specifically to the temporal dimensions of the future, present and past. However, within these categories, acts can be distinguished between, such as with a command from a request: A command opens a social present that can only be closed by a future act – the fulfillment of the command. In this scenario, as with a question and answer, the first social act requires a future responding act.Footnote 80 Commands and questions are social acts that open a future that remains until the intended act – fulfillment, response – occurs.Footnote 81 Here, an intended future opens an extended present.Footnote 82
Reinach shows that an offer and acceptance also have a specific temporal structure, resulting from their nature. One cannot accept an offer through information or a communication, but only through a specific utterance of a presentistic nature. One should, therefore, temporally distinguish the ‘rigid’ legal act of acceptance of ‘I hereby accept’ from the narrative ‘I have already inwardly agreed’ and a declaration of intent, namely ‘I will agree’.Footnote 83 Like the ‘I do’ of the bridal couple in a church or before the registrar, acceptance is a performative act that can only take place and fulfill its meaning in the present. The groom, who holds out the prospect of saying ‘I do’ to his bride and does not actually say ‘I do’ is signaling to her that he is not serious about his intention and wants to think it over. The same is true for any potential contracting partner who only indicates acceptance. If the potential partner does not give any reasons for this, the delay in making his or her intention known is a reason to doubt if an intention to enter into the contract exists.Footnote 84
As is well known, for Reinach, the basic legal act is the promise. Promises have a particular temporal structure because, as social acts, promises are processes with a specific temporal duration.Footnote 85 While a message can refer to the present, the future and/or past, a promise, like a command or request, ‘always refers to a future time’.Footnote 86 However, while the behavior of others is central to commands and requests, a promise is centered on the person making the promise.Footnote 87 For Reinach, the promisor irrevocably binds his or her future in the presence of the promisee, even without the other’s acceptance, when the promise is consciously perceived (‘vernommen’). In this way, the promisor initiates ‘a train of events’.Footnote 88 The claim and obligating nature of a promise arises immediately when it is made.Footnote 89 Unlike experiences, a claim or an obligation arising from a promise ‘can last for years’.Footnote 90 Reinach can show that a promise has a teleological structure, ‘an inherent tendency to an end and to dissolve’.Footnote 91 Unlike the transfer of property, for example, which exhausts itself in its efficacy,Footnote 92 a promise refers to future action.Footnote 93 With Franz Brentano one could say that the still unreal future only becomes reality through the binding nature of the promise because it is made present.Footnote 94 The temporal structure of promises, claims and obligations is thus an important distinguishing feature from other phenomena such as experiences. From this structure, Reinach concluded that claim and obligation ‘seem to be temporal objects of a special kind’.Footnote 95
In his discussion with Wilhelm Schuppe, Reinach returned to this temporal structure. Whereas Schuppe believed that the immutability of the obligation results from the trust of the recipient rather than from the promise, Reinach countered that the obligation follows from the nature of the promise itself. Irrespective of whether the promisor has granted the promisee a right of revocation or has made a conditional promise, the promise is irrevocable ‘from the outset’. This means that a promise creates its future obligation and the extended present the moment it is made and consciously received.Footnote 96
The declaration of a promise establishes the present of the future obligation of that promise even without the acceptance of the addressee of the promisee. The promisor may, of course, make his promise conditional on the acceptance of the addressee.Footnote 97 In this case, if the addressee does not accept the promise or rejects it, no claim or obligation arises. This acceptance of the promise has a different time structure than the promise itself and, as has already been explained, it can only take place in the present.Footnote 98 Neither the person who indicates acceptance nor the person who promises to accept has actually accepted. An acceptor must accept by stating, for example, ‘I hereby accept’. This ‘I hereby accept’ establishes the present necessary for acceptance. Acceptance can only take place as a performative, present declarationFootnote 99 – or as Reinach would later say, ‘determination’. With Reinach we can conclude that, while a promise necessarily has a temporal structure of the future, an acceptance necessarily has a temporal structure of the present.
It seems appropriate at this point to follow an interesting modification that Reinach made when he introduced ‘conditional promises’ and ‘promises with conditional content’.Footnote 100 In both cases, a promisor modifies the extended present, albeit in different ways. With both modifications, one may ask: How are we to understand the time between the act of promising and the occurrence of the condition? In a ‘conditional promise’, the promisor makes the efficacy of the resultant obligation dependent on a possible future event.Footnote 101 For example, at time t, a promisor says: ‘I will only commit myself to action X when (time t’) I know that you will commit yourself to action Y’. Only when the condition is fulfilled is the promisor obliged to do X, without any further acts being required from either the promisor or the promisee.Footnote 102 For the act at time t, it is essential that the occurrence of the future event of the condition is open. In other words: by its very nature (‘essentially required’, according to Reinach), the condition has the character of an open future. If the future event were already certain when the promise is made, the effectiveness of the obligation could, at best, be limited in time.Footnote 103 In contrast, in a case involving a ‘promise with conditional content’, the promisor enters into an obligation immediately but ties its content to certain conditions that must be fulfilled: ‘I promise now (time t) to start doing X until Y happens (time t’)’. This obligation arises immediately when the promise is made, and thus represents the normal case of a promise.
What is interesting about both modifications of a promise is how to understand the time between the making of the promise and the fulfillment of the condition (t – t’). In the case of a ‘conditional promise’, this extended present has an ‘at first’ or provisional character, that is, it is oriented toward the occurrence of the condition and ends with the corresponding event. If the promisor makes a conditional promise, then the claim and obligation arise with the occurrence of the event specified in the condition (‘conditional promise’) and expire as if the promise had never been made the moment it becomes clear that the specified event will not occur.Footnote 104 In the meantime, the obligation does not exist and, therefore, it is not yet possible to waive the performance of the promise. Here, ‘initially’ means that the promisee’s waiver only becomes effective when the condition occurs, namely, in the period of time limited by the occurrence of the condition set by the promisor when the promisee can waive the claim just as conditionally. The same moment t’ becomes the condition for the emergence of the claim and the condition for the waiver: ‘The coming into existence of the claim is here the immediate cause of its death’.Footnote 105 The period of time t – t’ has the character of the provisional. In the case of conditional renunciation, the period lasts until the moment t’, which acquires the character of a common present through the condition of its obligation set by the promisor and the condition of its renunciation set by the promisee. Conversely, in the case of a ‘promise with conditional content’, the obligation is created immediately. Following Reinach, therefore a promisee may waive the relevant obligation during the entire period. This possibility to waive does not arise with the occurrence of the substantive condition but ends then. It is only in this respect that it is provisional: It is not a promisor’s obligation that is provisional, but rather only the performance of that obligation. In the time span t – t’ everything is related: the promise and the possibility of renunciation. Thus, by modifying the promise, a promisor has the power to make the extended present t – t’ temporally as provisional toward a future event (‘conditional promise’) or already as fully realized (‘promise with conditional content’).Footnote 106 At any moment of the extended present t – t’, the promisee can react with a renunciation. In both cases, the character of this time span t – t’ does not result from natural time sequences, rather, it is characterized by the promise and the possibilities of the promisee to react to it; whether it has the character of the provisional or is the present depends on them. According to Reinach, this entire structure of a promise is based on the timeless a priori of law (‘wesensgesetzlich gefordert’, ‘essentially required’). No matter how manifold the acts of a promise and its acceptance are, no matter how inadequate the legal regulations of this, ‘their pure ideas are based on secure and immutable laws’.Footnote 107
Therefore, one can agree with Reinach stating that promises and acceptances are ‘temporal objects that have a character of their own and are neither physical nor psychological’,Footnote 108 as long as one adheres to their ontological properties and distinguishes them from the experiences in which they appear to us. However, they are neither timeless nor out of time like the a priori structures. Rather, the declaration of a promise and its perception simultaneously generate a duration that is essential for social acts, and both acts only relate to each other because they constitute an extended present.Footnote 109 This duration is opened by the declaration of a promise and closed by its fulfillment. Acceptance – if necessary – falls into this present as a point in time constituted by the acceptor.
Taken together we can see with Reinach that a promise is a social act and as a social act, it is a process with a beginning of a certain permanence and an end, that is, it has a duration. However, a particular character of this duration follows from the nature of promises: The duration is directed toward a future realization of the promise in question. The beginning, continuation and end of this duration can be modified as continuous or provisional by conditions. The temporally structured present in this way is not an arbitrary construction of a promisor but follows from the nature of the promise given and the conditions or time limit set. This duration takes place based on objective time, which makes it possible to measure the moments of the social act of the promise in question, of the entry into the condition and of the time limit. However, what is measured – the social act of the promise – does not derive its duration from this time but from the essential process. As with a movement, the measurable moments do not define the duration of the process but are its expression, namely, its beginning and its end.
Reinach did not examine other legal acts with the same level of detail as he did the promise as a basic legal act. However, the examples below show how he anchored temporality in the nature of the respective social legal: Although Reinach did not explicitly speak of future commitment, he did say that the obligatory relationship tends toward its realization and it has a purpose. An obligation is related to ‘the time at which it should be fulfilled’.Footnote 110 Correspondingly, a claim is directed toward its fulfillment. Such terms signal the teleological and thus future-oriented character of the relationship between the promisor and the promisee. At the moment when a claim is either fulfilled or a waiver becomes effective, that claim expires. Reinach also made a temporal distinction between relative rights, such as claims, and absolute rights that, for example, relate to property. While claims have a provisional temporal structure because they are ordered toward an end, absolute rights have something finite about them.Footnote 111 If a claim is fulfilled by the conduct of another party, it ends. However, rights arising from property can be exercised at any time. As such, both claims and absolute rights can have time-bound content.Footnote 112
In addition, for Reinach a contract also has a specific, a priori existing temporality which results from the connection of the temporality of the mutual declarations: In the extended present, the contracting parties instantiate a future structure. This binds the future of the obligor and opens the future of the obligee.Footnote 113 In the case of reciprocal obligations, therefore, there are mutual future commitments, and the resultant extended present is not closed until all the contractual obligations have been fulfilled. For Reinach, this necessary temporal structure of contracts results from the necessary temporality of the social acts underlying contracts.Footnote 114
Finally, there are social acts, such as judgments, that directly change something in the world. Reinach called them ‘determinations’ (‘Bestimmungen’) and these are relatively commonplace as they arise with an acceptance of an offer and the enactment of laws and statutes. ‘Determinations’ are not rooted in previous structures – although they may be shaped by them – but bring something new.Footnote 115 ‘Determinations’ are not future-oriented but have an immediate effect – which is the existence of a claim or property.Footnote 116 In contrast to a command, which is realized only if it is obeyed in the future, a ‘determination’ is realized immediately. Take § 1 of the German Civil Code (BGB): ‘The legal capacity of a human being begins with the completion of birth’.Footnote 117 The indicative of the formulation shows that this effect occurs when its precondition is fulfilled. The legislator ‘enacts that claim and property ought to be, and presently something is changed in the world. What is posited by the enactment is not merely something which ought to be and is waiting to be realized, rather it becomes real at the moment of the positing and through the positing: property and claim exist in virtue of the enactment’.Footnote 118 Transfer would be another example.Footnote 119 The present here has a very different character from the teleological present of a promise:Footnote 120 The act of transfer exhausts itself in the present. However, in the case of enacting laws, this does not mean that a legislator establishes a norm that contains an obligation. In its application, the law then becomes a command from the user to the person subject to the norm to do this or that. ‘Determinations’ and commands remain distinct social acts. This command then – like other commands – has a reference to the future and is not exhausted in the present of its utterance.Footnote 121 While a promise creates a claim and an obligation with its conscious perception, it only becomes effective with the fulfillment of its resultant obligation where the transfer of rights is a social act that is realized in the presence of the transfer. It closes the future that was opened, for example, by the establishment of the obligation. Furthermore, these direct social acts can do this because their meaning does not refer to a future and there is, therefore, a certain freedom in the ‘determinations’.Footnote 122 As Reinach states, ‘Only that which can be and can also not be, which can have a beginning, duration, and an end in time, is the possible content of “determinations”’.Footnote 123 That, which is in itself timeless and necessary – like the a priori structures – cannot be included in the content of ‘determinations’.Footnote 124
Just as social acts are not phenomena of consciousness, such as emotions or cognitions, this temporality does not arise from consciousness, as in Husserl’s transcendental second phase, but for Reinach is objectively grounded in the nature of the corresponding acts.Footnote 125 Admittedly, the past plays a subordinate role in legal relations and, perhaps as a consequence, Reinach hardly mentioned it. Nevertheless, it is clear that the past becomes important around the time of the acceptance of a promise: A promise made in the past must still exist at the time of the conscious perception or, if necessary, its acceptance. Reinach shows that the interaction of the a priori temporally structured social acts then results in a specific present: A question opens up a present that is closed by its answer. A promise opens up a present that extends as far as its hearing and can be closed by the fulfillment of that promise or its renunciation and can be structured in time by the promisor through conditions. Absolute rights grant their holders an unchangeable, permanent present in which they are authorized to make use of these rights. By their very nature, provisions are temporally punctual social acts, however, they open up an extended present in which new rights or obligations exist for the person concerned: The transfer of a right now allows the recipient to make use of it. An enacted law is valid for a certain or indefinite period. When an acceptance of an offer is required, an extended present of contractual obligations is also required. Through these social acts, an extended present or duration is brought forth which can have a future-oriented, teleological character toward their fulfillment or take on a more static, unchanging character.
This duration – or extended present in the Bergsonian sense – is an essential characteristic of legal time.Footnote 126 It is precisely demonstrated by the fact that essentially founded legal institutions can exist independently of fluctuating sentiments and interests. For Reinach, it is an essential characteristic that claims, obligations and other legal forms ‘arise, last a definite length of time, and then disappear again’.Footnote 127 They ‘can last for years without change’, because they are independent of emotions or other experiences. Rights over things (‘Sachenrechte’) ‘survive a change in the owner of the thing … without any respect of the person of the owner at a given time’.Footnote 128 These rights can ‘survive the change in the owner’.Footnote 129 It is in the nature of these rights to endure and not to be limited by temporal events that the law does not consider relevant, as in the case of deeply personal rights (‘höchstpersönliche Rechte’).Footnote 130 These enduring phenomena are the basic social phenomena, from which temporally punctual acts, such as the attitude of questioning and the explicit question, can be explained.Footnote 131 Again, this extended present of duration can be measured and quantified in natural time even though it arises from the nature of rights, claims and obligations.
Reinach thus showed that acts, especially social acts, have their own temporality which distinguishes them from natural time on the one hand and from the extratemporality of a priori structures on the other. While intentionally future-oriented, presently effective or permanent acts and legal structures can certainly be measured in natural time, their temporality is not determined by it.Footnote 132 Reinach’s phenomenology of legal time is realistic, not because it adheres to the superficial temporality of natural events, but because it takes social legal acts as its starting point and examines their nature in terms of their own temporal structures. For this reason, he also distinguished between natural objects, which simply fall into time, ideal objects, which are extratemporal or even eternal, and social acts, which must be temporal but whose temporality is to be substantiated concretely from their essence and not from their natural appearance. However, precisely because this time is essential time, it is not a subjective time of a time consciousness or even a social construction.Footnote 133 In these social, and especially legal, acts one finds those events that produce duration and thus time in the sense shown above. Social and legal times for Reinach thus arose from social acts, although not from their arbitrariness but from their essential structure. Accordingly, it is not surprising that this structure of time does not consist of an external quantitative ‘earlier-than’–‘later than’ or ‘before-after’. Rather, this legal time is a qualitative time that emerges from the specific temporality of social acts. It exists as a shared social present where the future emerges from the meaning of a promise and its declaration. Intentionality is the structural aspect of the social act that characterizes the future. It is opened as another possibility for a promisee and closed as an obligation for the promisor. In this way, the future is also a social future that emerges from the actions of those involved.
9.2.3 To Sum Up
All in all, Reinach took the first steps toward the recognition of a legal time as a distinct form of time, which one can distinguish from other times, but which can also serve as the basis for the synchronization of the other social times.Footnote 134 However, one can also find problematic aspects both in his theory of time and his theory of law.
Although Reinach said that the temporality of legal acts is one of their essential characteristics, distinguishing them from both ideal and purely empirical objects of knowledge, his theory of time is nevertheless fragmentary. It had to be reconstructed here from very different passages of his works. Many aspects of the temporality of law have already been decided by essential a priori structures. This may be one reason why for Reinach, as it does for Brentano, the present plays a prominent role. In contrast, both the openness of the future, which makes free action possible, and questions concerning the past, play only a subordinate role. Throughout his writing, it becomes clear how Reinach’s pioneering work on a theory of the temporality of law did not draw on the groundbreaking insights of Edmund Husserl’s investigations into the phenomenology of inner time consciousness and Heidegger’s fundamental ontological foundation of ‘Being and Time’. However, while for both Husserl and Heidegger the social dimension is not very important, from the outset, Reinach constructed his theory of the temporality of law from the a priori foundations of social acts, thus revealing a worthwhile path for later attempts.
By their social acts and especially by determining the law through its positivization, people can deviate from the a priori structures.Footnote 135 In this respect, they have a negative freedom but lack the positive freedom to create new essential structures. The inherent justification of discourses that produce something genuinely new from the convictions of the participants thus is outside Reinach’s understanding of the temporality of law. Whenever a legal discourse produces new values, principles or rules, the a priori doctrine of law will claim that their essence already exists. However, since values differ, discourse and normative guidance are needed to agree on what is produced. For this reason, the concept of the norm would also have to be placed at the center of the analysis of the temporal structure of law, which Reinach does not do.
Process and norm come together when one considers the importance of the futurity of social action, something also emphasized by Reinach. Law, by virtue of its norms, implies a commitment to the future because human action is shaped by the awareness of an open future of options. Norms should guide human actions and correct them where necessary. Since this freedom also refers to the process of norm-setting in, for example, contracts, laws and criminal norm assertions, there is a need for a reflexive structure of law. Law subjects the open future horizon of norm-setting, norm interpretation and norm enforcement to norms in turn. These are norms that relate, for example, to the conclusion of contracts, the legislative process, and enforcement. A working theory of the temporality of law would have to take into account both a qualitative understanding of the dimensions of time and the normativity of law, something Reinach failed to do but that he did, arguably, open the door toward.
9.3 Gerhart Husserl
To better appreciate Adolf Reinach’s pioneering work on a theory of law and time and, at the same time, to gain some perspective on the direction in which a phenomenological theory of legal time may develop, it is helpful to take a look at Gerhart Husserl’s work. This is because the latter’s theory has an advantage over Reinach’s work by having a more detailed legal basis and by assuming a greater plurality of temporal experiences.
In the context of his phenomenological investigations of the relationship between law and time, Gerhart HusserlFootnote 136 did not explicitly refer to his father’s ‘Lectures on the Phenomenology of the Internal Consciousness of Time’.Footnote 137 However, it is likely that when he published an article entitled ‘Recht und Welt’ (‘Law and World’) in the Festschrift for his father in 1929, Gerhart was aware of the lectures held in 1905 and that were edited in 1928 by Martin Heidegger and published in volume XI of the ‘Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung’. Husserl had already committed himself to a phenomenological approach in his graduation thesis of 1925, which he dedicated to his father.Footnote 138 He did not thematize it but applied the method of phenomenological reduction. In the years that followed he returned to phenomenological considerations and, in ‘Time and Law’, he went into explicit detail and, among other things, provided a vivid example using the ‘shoe’ to explain the nature of functional objects and then also of the law.Footnote 139 Besides applying his approach, the completely different ‘Eigenart’ (specific character) of Martin Heidegger left some traces in Husserl’s work.Footnote 140 Heidegger’s first main work on fundamental ontology ‘Being and Time’ was published in 1927 in Volume VIII of the aforementioned yearbook.
9.3.1 Abstract and Concrete Time of Law
9.3.1.1 The Abstract Time of the Works of Art and Law
Husserl’s analysis of the relationship between law and the world is based on the principle of experience. A priori propositions have a legal meaning but are not valid law; they must first be transformed into social reality to attain legal validity.Footnote 141 Here, Husserl is thus distancing himself from Reinach.Footnote 142 He starts by viewing a human being as ‘being in the world’. This being in the world can be naive, immediate or ecstatic.Footnote 143 In the experience of nature there is doubt, everything is uncertain, and everything is as transitory or temporary as man himself. Indeed, in natural attitudes, Gerhart Husserl emphasized the omnipresence of a death consciousness even more strongly than Edmund Husserl. This did not yet lead the former to the preeminent position of the future for Dasein (‘existence’), as Heidegger did in ‘Being and Time’.Footnote 144 Thus, one finds only echoes of fundamental ontology in Husserl’s works.
By turning to transcendental ideas, people overcome these doubts and uncertainties in, what Husserl calls, ‘an ecstatic attitude’. This attitude does not mean escaping from the world, even if it entails alienation from the world, but taking the situation of doubt seriously and fully investing one’s own person in this world. The ecstatic attitude then becomes the conscious assumption of the world in which a naive person simply finds themself and it seeks to provide an affirmative attitude toward this world. In this transgression of the consciousness, a transcendent time structure is also experienced: in religion, eternity, and also in pictorial works of art, we hold to our present against the current of experience.Footnote 145
The time of a work of art is essentially negatively determined – a nonnatural, ‘illusory time’. First of all, a musical composition has an ‘abstract time’, which only enters into concrete time-being through its ‘temporalization’ in the performance. The composition is only a ‘norm’ for its repeated reproduction, which can and must then be concretely experienced and kept in consciousness (‘retendiert’)Footnote 146 if it is to be perceived as an experience in the natural world. The determination of the composition as a norm and its being in time as ‘abstract time’ is also to be kept in mind for an analysis of law. Husserl does not understand the ‘ecstatic transcendence’ of naturally naive world behavior as a transition into a fully valid temporality of one’s own; rather, he sees it only as an abstraction into an illusory time. The composition receives its concrete reality only through its reentry into the natural-bodily world. Only in this way does the norm become the object of time consciousness.Footnote 147
In a subsequent step, Husserl compared the creation of art to the realization of law.Footnote 148 In doing so, law is also put into a state of ‘abstract time’ and must then be ‘temporalized’. While Reinach distinguishes between the timeless form of the a priori foundations of law and legal temporality, Husserl moves from the ‘abstract time’ of norms in books to the more concrete temporality of the realization of legal norms. This approach will be examined in more detail below.
9.3.1.2 Detemporalization of Law
For Gerhart Husserl, law was a ‘work of will’ of the legal community (‘Rechtsgemeinschaft’).Footnote 149 He believed that like a work of art, law has its own being in time, although not in natural time. Law is not eternal nor is it designed for a temporal end and, while it is valid, it is not regarded as coming from the past and being carried out to a future end.Footnote 150 It is not an object of memory or expectation and it exists beyond our experienced present.Footnote 151 Just as law is valid in an abstract way, it also has an ‘abstract time’. Law has this abstract temporality because it does not refer to a singular social fact or ‘spatio-temporal reality’.Footnote 152 In this ‘abstract validity’, it has not yet reached either legal reality or legal temporality. The abstract time of a legal norm is produced by an abstract formulation of the facts. Here, possible courses of action are recorded against a developing future and, once created, a law becomes a product of will (‘Willenswerk’) that exists as a norm detached from legal consciousness, ‘even if all subjects of law under its spell sleep dreamlessly’.Footnote 153 Like Reinach, Husserl viewed legal validity as abstract in terms of the psychological attitudes that may or may not realize it, but while Reinach ties this abstraction to the a priori structures of law, Husserl referred to the abstract legal norms in books.
Essentially, this abstract time means ‘timelessness’ because no temporal element can be named for law in this form. Thus, law has lost its temporal reality and has been transformed into a potentiality. From there it must be transformed into legal reality by the deliberate acts of ‘legal comrades’. Here, in Husserl’s theory, legal comrades are persons and legal orders that mutually support each other; however, man would lose his legal personhood and a legal order its validity if the attitudes of the community toward the law were to change. They would thus leave the world of law and fall back into a natural world. This inaccessible ‘will’-attitude guarantees permanence in that the individual cannot dispose of it and therefore cannot ‘reject’ it.Footnote 154 At the same time, however, law depends on every human being for its validity.Footnote 155
Husserl’s desire to hold on to consciousness as the basis for the temporality of law seems to require an objective consciousness of the legal community in the case of laws. The duration of law as the basis of its abstract time is dependent on the duration of a permanent collective will of the people. For this, he relied on the constant expression of this will. However, there are some doubts about this aspect of his concept: On the one hand, this attitude is supposed to lift the individual out of the naively experienced world into a legal world to justify and support him; on the other hand, however, this will is not supposed to be available to him. This raises the question: Why should our (collective) will and the law not be changed for good reasons? Another concern here is that this ‘attitude of will’ seems to be a mere fiction. However, if law is to be moved from existing in abstract time into concrete and perceptible time, the permanent attitude of will also needs to be empirically proven. It remains unclear in Husserl’s work what this will is. In a defense of a psychological justification of law, Husserl objects to calling it somehow emotional, just as Reinach did not want to rely on psychological facts for the construction of law. The reason for both men having this somewhat common perspective is that the ‘abstract’ being of law should not be the object of a feeling, which, if it were, would lose its objectivity.Footnote 156
9.3.1.3 Putting Law into Time
Husserl’s second step in the constitution of experiential law further concretized law by placing it in time (‘Verzeitung’ ~ temporalization). In this regard, he noted: ‘In fact, it is a matter of crossing over from the other side of the timeless world of law to this side of the reality of the will, which lies in the natural flow of time, to which the legal proposition, as one affected by norms, is concretely related’.Footnote 157 This is the task of the judge in particular as in the legal force of his judgment, the law acquires concrete validity and ‘world-shaping power’.Footnote 158 This fixes law in time and, as long as it is determined in this way, it can be the object of personal feelings and the like and has become evident.
Therefore, Husserl makes an important exception to the necessity of ‘temporalization’, namely, constitutions. For him, constitutions represent ‘the legal being of the legal community’ with a particular temporality. They do not require an explicit application to be concrete because they are – again – ‘supported and held by the permanent will of the legal community, which is beyond the experience of today, but at the same time has its roots in the living personhood of the respective existing human beings’.Footnote 159 In fact, a constitution represents the will of the relevant legal community.Footnote 160 It is not clear here whether Husserl now introduces another temporality besides the natural and the abstract one; however, doing so seems to be necessary: Constitutions certainly cannot have natural temporality because they are based on a certain will-intent with its own temporal structure that is different from the natural temporality of emotional acts. What was needed here was not an ‘ideation’ involving the natural time-transcending commitment of the ‘legal comrades’ but only an ‘awakening of the constitutional will-intent’.Footnote 161 However, this entails constitutions being either transferred into a world of psychic experience, resulting in their temporalization (‘Verzeitung’), or them remaining as they are, awakened in the mind itself. This means they cannot be natural-temporal because a will attitude that brings a constitution into being, according to Husserl, only brings about abstract temporality. A constitution should not be, however, in abstract time because it already has reality in the common will of the people. Here, too, Husserl’s theory of the attitude of will (‘Willensgesinnung’) does not lead to a clarification of the question of temporality.
At the next level of concretization, Husserl argued that administrative action should not seek temporization or the creation of new law but the abstract normative facts should be given a concrete and adequate form. An official simply makes use of his or her authority and performs an act of will which is then legally evaluated. He ‘moves in the sphere of action of natural experience. He places his work in the flowing time in which social things come into being and pass away. His effort is to create the permanent, not the once and for all’.Footnote 162 The contact with the interests of the natural social world makes the other decisions uncertain. Their actions are all still legally open and thus in the natural realm of doubt. Judges are tasked with freeing the law and its concretization from this doubt and determining the law. Only the judge’s decision represents a real, certain, ‘Verzeitung’ of the abstract law. More specifically than Reinach, Husserl shows here that the extended present with an open future of a legal process of concretization can only be closed by certain legal acts, namely judgments.
With this subjective approach, Husserl certainly contributes to a foundation of the temporality of law on the consciousness of law and time. However, it does not do justice to the manifold possibilities of acts applying the law. One need only think of the force of validity (‘Bestandskraft’) of administrative acts and with the rules of limitation or res judicata. How can the acts of judges do so if they do not put law into time? The failure of natural acts to obey temporal constraints clearly has legal consequences. Yet, this did not have a place in Husserl’s theory of the temporality of law. This already shows that the limitation of the temporalization to the courts is too narrow and does not sufficiently take into account other forms of transforming temporally abstract laws into concrete legal time.
9.3.2 Doubts and Revisions of the Temporality of Law Based on Legal Consciousness
From the above brief reconstruction of Husserl’s theory,Footnote 163 one can conclude that two aspects are decisive for the temporality of law: on the one hand, the ‘de-temporalization’ of the content of law to a legal order that is in a form supported by an individually unavailable will and where law is in abstract, nonexperiential time. On the other hand, law must be ‘temporalized’ to be able to have a world-shaping effect. This happens in court decisions which definitively establish the law and make it capable of experience in space-time as only in this form is the law accessible to the consciousness of time. As plausible as these two steps are, problematic aspects remain: first, the foundation of the permanence of ‘abstract law’ on the attitude of will and, in general, its closer determination and, second, the limitation of the temporalization to the activity of the judge. Despite all the differences that have become apparent with regard to the conception of the ‘phenomenology of inner time consciousness’, the insufficiency of a foundation of time on this subjective time remains with respect to objective structures such as law.
Husserl himself may have had doubts about his conception, a notion borne out by his later considerations where he shifted the focus and wrote more intently about the temporalizing moments in the action of the legislator.Footnote 164 In 1955, in ‘Law and Time’, he emphasized more strongly the relationship of the legal order to the concrete historical situation and linked the fate of the norm to the legal community. This was a notable shift from both the first part of his work on the validity of law in 1925 and in ‘Law and the World’ from 1929.Footnote 165 In ‘Law and Time’, he argued that the application of norms now affects their temporal structure and they reach back into the past, whereas in his earlier works, legal norms seemed to have no past. The legislative act becomes the keystone of this past. In the act of reception of this prehistory of laws, Husserl presents this keystone initially as an act of ‘de-timing’ (‘Entzeitlichung’), which here means a reduction of the legal propositions to their ‘core of meaning’. As long as they are ‘untimed’ (‘entzeitet’), they have no normative force and must first be incorporated into a legal order. In this respect the act of the legislator is the keystone of prehistory. However, the arm with which he reaches into the future is of finite length and the ongoing actualization of the law is a matter of its application, with the latter remaining the focus of his concept. Thus, while in his earlier works Husserl emphasized the abstract temporality of norms that are lifted out of the flow of temporal events, he eventually took into account the fact they change and that they are dependent on historical time as a time filled with historical content. Indeed, he noted that abstract time in this context means objective, measurable time.Footnote 166 In his later works, historicity began to play a more important role in Husserl’s work and fundamental ontological thinking gained greater traction. One can almost perceive Heidegger’s influence when Husserl speaks of the temporal structure of the legal claim, which has the nature of a tool and is directed toward an end.Footnote 167 This is then distinguished from the temporal structure of continuing obligations, which are not directed toward their end but are carried by the ongoing fulfillment of meaning.Footnote 168
Husserl’s clarifications lead to a more differentiated view of the temporality of legal objects. The abstract comparison of subjective and objective time has receded somewhat, giving way to a broader view of the multiple temporalities of legal content.
9.4 Conclusion
In conclusion, the foregoing has briefly contrasted Reinach’s approaches to a theory of the temporality of law with Gerhart Husserl’s theory of the temporality of legal consciousness. This was done to show the different conceptions of the temporal structure of law arrived at by the various approaches of phenomenology. While Reinach made his observations based on realist phenomenology, Gerhart Husserl worked with the transcendental and, to some extent, the fundamental ontological method. This led Reinach to anchor the temporality of law in the timeless a priori structures of fundamental legal acts and an objective temporality of law. Husserl, in contrast, excludes this sphere and understands timelessness itself as a social structure, namely the abstract time of the laws, borne by a permanent attitude of will. He is interested in the temporality of positive law as it results from the temporalization by the users of law. Both philosophers arrived at a point where they saw a specific temporality of law; for Reinach, this resulted from essentially structured legal acts while for Husserl it was born from legal consciousness.
Ultimately, for Reinach, the temporality of law rested in the unchangeable a priori temporal structures of legal acts in which everything seems to have already been decided. For him, everything rests on their realization, even though a legislator can deviate from this in its ‘determinations’. However, the fact that concrete law is also an expression of deliberations, evaluations, optimizations and considerations, while not excluded by Reinach, was not sufficiently included in his theory of the temporality of law. After World War I, the emergence of democratic, administrative and judicial procedures with their different temporal structures and novel ideas about a newly anticipated future, presenting the past and a will to maintain the legal state, played a greater role than at the end of Germany’s constitutional monarchy when Reinach developed his theory. In his writings during the Weimar Republic and later on, Gerhart Husserl was able to incorporate these historical legal developments into his theory of the realization of law as temporalizing. In contrast to Reinach, he does not distinguish between a timeless a priori sphere and a temporal one but between an abstract time of the enacted law and its realization in concrete legal acts.
Both Reinach and Husserl broke new ground, each in his own way, laying the foundations for a theory of the temporality of law. However, the positive law of the present is more than determining timeless a priori structures or expressing a temporal consciousness of law. This is because it produces its own temporality, one grounded in the extended present of the law’s validity, which opens up a future horizon in which legal persons can rely on predictable meanings of their legal acts. Law regulates its own present, future and past and herein lies its temporality. Adolf Reinach and Gerhart Husserl, as legal phenomenologists, opened the door to approaches to a theory of law’s temporality that can be further developed. Finally, and despite the incompleteness of their respective works, they have shown that contrary to the ancient idea of a possible approximation of positive law to an immutable natural law, law has its own temporality.Footnote 169
10.1 Introduction
Speech act theorists, such as John Austin, Peter Strawson, Zeno Vendler, John Searle, Michael Hancher or Mitchell Green,Footnote 1 take a gift to be among the range of things we can do with words. From their perspective, a gift is an illocutionary act, an act performed in uttering a meaningful sentence. In the right circumstances, saying, for example, “This bike is yours” is what it takes to gift it to you.Footnote 2 The consensus is that the utterance, whether implied or expressed, is a necessary component of the act.
Speech act theorists give their insights about gifts in passing. Once compiled, their scattered remarks reveal some remarkable disagreements and aspects left in the dark. One disagreement regards to what extent the giftee participates in the act. Most speech act theorists require gifts to be taken in by their recipients. As for any other illocutionary acts, the need to be heard and understood is taken to be among its felicity conditions. However, Peter Strawson contemplates the possibility of a gift unknown to its recipients in the form of a “will that is never read”.Footnote 3 Speech act theorists who insist on the need of an uptake diverge about whether the giftee is further required to accept the gift for the act to be completed. Besides these points of division, speech act theorists have neglected the deontic dimensions of gifts. If I give you my bike, what I seem to be giving you is the right to use it forever while ipso facto losing mine. John Austin hints at the related deontic changes when he classifies gifts (together with ordering, prohibiting, enacting law) among “exercitives” by which “powers, rights and influence” are conferred.Footnote 4 Likewise, Zeno Vendler includes gifts among “operatives” (along with “arrest, sentence, condemn, fine, offer, surrender”) issued when “I say something and the social, ritual, or legal effect ipso dicto takes place”.Footnote 5 Austin and Vendler do allude to the deontic effects of gifts but leave it at one’s guess what they precisely are. These are quandaries about gifts, at best quickly addressed in the past, providing the occasion, seized in the present chapter, to expound on the topic. To further reflect on how gifts are made with words, I mobilize Adolf Reinach’s The Apriori Foundations of the Civil Law, first published in 1913.Footnote 6 Reinach has written very few and sparse remarks on gifts.Footnote 7 However, his theory of “social acts”, developed almost fifty years before How to Do Things with Words (1962), provides the notions and distinctions that are useful to elucidate the aspects of gifts which Austin and his followers have parenthetically addressed or neglected. As many commentators have stressed, what Reinach calls “social acts” are very much like Austin’s “illocutionary acts”.Footnote 8 Following the crowd, I will also assume that “they are the same acts”Footnote 9 and, to avoid confusion, I use the slashed terms “social/illocutionary” to refer to both at once.
The discussion is structured around the previously outlined issues. Section 10.2 addresses Strawson’s example of the will that is never read. This example does not refute the giftee’s need to grasp the utterance in which gifts are made, I argue, because the act of writing a will is not yet the social/illocutionary act of making a gift to one’s heir. The question whether gifts need to be accepted is discussed in Section 10.3. In light of Reinach’s discussion of acceptance of promises, I argue that, although a gift need not be accepted, to refuse it blocks its completion. Section 10.4 critically examines Austin’s intuitive view of a gift as always involving a “gesture”, in the usual form of a handing over of something. This view, I argue, misguidedly focuses on the things that are gifted, whereas it is in fact the ownership over these things that is in all cases transferred to the giftee. Relying on Reinach’s insights on transfers and ownership, I put forth the “Ownership View of Gifts”, as I call it. I then consider the alternative view of charity-gift proposed by Waldron in Section 10.5. According to Waldron, a gift can be made by waiving property rights.Footnote 10 While I show that Waldron’s view does not withstand scrutiny, I also show how a gift can be made by an act of waiving one’s claim over someone else’s property rights. It is the main result of the present Reinachian inquiry that most of the puzzles raised by gifts dissolve once attention is redirected from its physical aspects – from the gestures, the thing that is gifted, its change of location – to the metaphysical underpinning of the speech act that is performed.
10.2 Does the Gifter Need to Secure Uptake?
The present inquiry focuses on those gifts that are made in the performance of a locutionary act.Footnote 11 Relevant examples of the latter are “I hereby give you my bike”, “Here is a gift for you”, “Look what I got for you!”, “Have some wine”, or simply “My gift!” while pointing at the thing thus being gifted. The act done in each of these utterances is a gift.Footnote 12 Giving birthday presents, giving cash gifts, writing a will, making a bequest, distributing grants, bestowing prizes, donating money, almsgiving, etc. are commonly taken to be instances of gifts. Are they all genuine instances of the kind? The nature of gifts – what a gift fundamentally is – is a question that has been largely neglected.Footnote 13 It is also one that need not be resolved for the purpose of the present inquiry. Nothing should be presumed about the genus of gift, not even that the alleged instances of gifts listed above have any common properties in virtue of which they are gifts. It suffices that certain utterances have the social/illocutionary force of a bequest, of a birthday gift, of almsgiving, etc., and that the latter are commonly described as “gifts” in ordinary language.
As a social/illocutionary act, a gift depends on the linguistic competencies of its two parties. I focus on the illocutionary acts of making a gift, in contrast to requesting one (“Will you give me your bike?”), to promising to make one (“I pledge to give 10 percent of my income to the poor”), to discouraging (“No tipping”) or to encouraging one (“Give What You Can”). Verb-terms and expressions commonly spoken to express the making of a gift are “to give”,Footnote 14 “to bring something as a gift” or simply “to gift”.Footnote 15 Some clarifications are in order. First, the utterance through which a gift is made need not contain the term “gift” nor any similar expressions. “Take it!”, “Have it!”, “I bought it for you!” are efficient alternatives.Footnote 16 Moreover, the same utterance can serve different illocutionary acts. In some context, someone may say “The pen is yours!” to give it to you, to order you to grab it, to warn you against the risk of losing it, etc. Reinach admits that a social/illocutionary act can be performed silently as long as it is “expressed in mien, gestures”.Footnote 17 In some circumstances, nodding, raising one’s eyebrows, smiling while pointing at the bike are the outward signs of the illocutionary act. Finally, let us note that the verb give can serve other illocutionary acts than a gift. If I say: “I am giving a party next Saturday”, “giving” means “organizing”, so it is correct to understand what I say as me announcing the event.
Both for Reinach and Austin, a social/illocutionary act must be heard and understood. Austin speaks of the “need to secure correct understanding”Footnote 18 of the audience. According to Reinach, an uptake is a necessary condition of a social/illocutionary act. “The turning to another subject”, he claims, “and the need of being heard [by that subject] is absolutely essential for every social act”.Footnote 19 Social acts need “to be announced or communicated” in contrast to “internal acts” (such as forgiving, deciding) which “can lack any announcement to others”.Footnote 20 However, Strawson wonders if securing uptake applies to the case of a bequest that remains undisclosed to its recipient:
[…] a man may, for example, actually have made such and such a bequest, or gift, even if no one ever reads his will or instrument of gift… Might not a man really have made a gift, in due form, and take some satisfaction in the thought, even if he had no expectation of the fact ever being known.Footnote 21
The case of a will that is never read is not meant to refute, but merely to downplay, the need to secure uptake. The latter, as Strawson grants, remains “essentially a standard, if not an invariable”Footnote 22 element of all social/illocutionary acts.
Against Strawson, one may insist that making sure the utterance is understood is not a mere desideratum, but an essential aspect of illocutionary acts. As Reinach argues, the utterance “is not something that is added thereto as an incidental extra; rather, it stands in the service of the social act and is necessary in order that this should fulfill its announcing function”.Footnote 23 That announcing function is precisely not satisfied in Strawson’s case of the will that will never be read. However, merely restating the necessity of being read (heard, understood, having an uptake, etc.) of all social/illocutionary acts does not suffice to rule out Strawson’s case. Indeed, isn’t the point of that example to cast doubt on the necessity of uptakes that both Austin and Reinach take to be necessary to social/illocutionary acts: to suggest that unbeknownst gifts really are gifts?
There is an ambiguity in the act of making a will which may have mislead Strawson into thinking that it qualifies as an illocutionary/social act. The ambiguity is between the act of writing a will and the outcome of that act in the form of a legal document named “a will”. The suggestion here is that the need to secure uptake is true about that document, but not about the act of writing that document. Reinach’s subtle distinction between acts that are “other-directed” and acts that are “addressed” is relevant to capture Strawson’s confusion. Reinach defines “other-directed acts” as acts that are “essential[ly] directed to a subject other than the originator”.Footnote 24 For instance, to forgive or to envy are always to forgive and to envy someone. By contrast, acts that are addressed to someone require the participation of another person who “consciously takes in” the act: who hears and understands the utterance through which the act is made. While all social/illocutionary acts are thus “addressed” according to Reinach, they are not all other-directed. Indeed, “other-directedness” characterizes certain “internal acts” such as forgiving you and being afraid of you. The addressed/non-addressed distinction and the directed/non-directed distinctions are hence orthogonal. Promises are both other-directed and addressed. Declarations and enactments are addressed (therefore social/illocutionary acts) but are not other-directed.
These distinctions may have eluded Strawson and led him to mistakenly assume the other-directedness of the act of writing a will makes it a social/illocutionary act. However, once one rather focuses, as Reinach invites us to, on the need to be addressed, it becomes clear why the act of writing a will is not an instance of the social/illocutionary kind. The writing of a will, like any other act of writing, is fully completed before it is read by anyone. “A good thing done”, the testator may think once she is (indeed) done with the task. However, the mere writing of the will, while a crucial step in the making of a gift, is not (yet) a gift. It is only when the outcome of the writing – the written document – is read and understood by the court and the heirs at the testator’s death that the latter really are gifted what is left to them in the will. Until then, the document has not fulfilled its purpose: no gift has been effectively made. In short, the will qua a document must be addressed to the heirs and taken in by them. The sheer act of writing is not addressed in the related Reinachian sense of the term but also does not count as a gift, either legally or from an a priori point of view.Footnote 25
The necessity of hearing and understanding the utterance by which gifts are made (discussed and defended in this section) is different from the necessity or the mere conceptual possibility of accepting them, which is discussed in the next section.
10.3 Do Gifts Require Acceptance?
In How to Do Things with Words, John Austin asks: “Are you required to accept the gift if I am to give you something?”, then notes that “in formal business, acceptance is required”,Footnote 26 but then wonders if it also features in casual gifts. If so, what appears to be the act of one person – a “unilateral act” as Austin names it – turns out to be the act of two, namely, a “bilateral act”. In the latter case, the giftee participates in the act in a more demanding form than by simply hearing and understanding the utterance in which it is made. He would have to accept the act.Footnote 27 The question is not whether gifts can be refused (of course, they can). The question is whether a gift has been made in the circumstance where it is refused. If a gift is a bilateral act, refusing it prevents it from being brought into completion. Austin then ponders if the seeming bilaterality of gifts is a defining feature of all social/illocutionary acts: “The question here is how far can [illocutionary] acts be unilateral. Similarly the question arises as to when the act is at an end, what counts as its completion?”Footnote 28
Is acceptance of a gift essential to its making? If the gift causes trouble to its recipient (think of a dog), it seems that the giftee must have the option to do something to prevent the act. The other intuition relates to the contrary case where the giftee, being wholly pleased with what she is gifted, would rightly consider accepting it as unneeded. The asymmetry between the cases of the unwanted gift and that of the welcome gift is not well accounted for if gifts are (merely) thought of as either unilateral or bilateral acts.
Reinach’s insights on acceptance, I submit, provide a way to reconcile the two intuitions. Reinach clarifies the term by distinguishing between five different meanings of acceptance, among which is the “purely inner experience, an inner ‘saying yes’ an inner assent”Footnote 29 to some social/illocutionary act. Accepting a gift is just the experience of the internal act of approving of it, of finding it to one’s taste. Alternatively, accepting can itself be “a social act in its own right”.Footnote 30 To accept is, in this other sense, always to accept or express a response to another social/illocutionary act (an invitation, to take a bet, an offer, etc.). Three possibilities can be distinguished in this regard. Accepting a social/illocutionary act can either be:
(i) a possible response to that act
(ii) an impossible response to that act
(iii) necessary to the completion of that act.Footnote 31
Let us look at the related three cases more closely with the view to figuring out which one, if any, is relevant to the cases of accepting the gift. First, acceptance is a possible response vis-à-vis those social/illocutionary acts which do not depend on it for being done. Nominations and invitations are cases in point. While you do have the option to either decline or accept my invitation to dinner, I have invited you regardless. Not so, it seems, as far as gifts are concerned, if it is true that a gift has not been made in the case its recipient refuses it. Unlike refusing an invitation, refusing a gift does stop its completion.
Secondly, acceptance is impossible vis-à-vis certain social/illocutionary acts which are such that to either accept or decline does not make sense. Reinach holds commands and requests to be examples of acts that are not meant to be accepted nor declined. Reinach writes that “with [commands and requests] it is a question of imposing an obligation on the addressee of the social act, and this of course really does not need some acceptance”.Footnote 32 For example, a teacher who commands a late student to arrive on time next time imposes an obligation on that student. The teacher should not worry about securing the student’s acceptance although she might not be indifferent as to whether the student takes her command seriously or whether she internally assents to it. Obligations created by commands and requests are such that the option to accept, or, for that matter, to decline them, is just not there. To be sure, commands can be obeyed or disobeyed, and requests can be answered or left unanswered. However, to disobey is to not act as one is commanded to act, but the important point is that the command has been fully made independently of whether it is obeyed or not. Unlike a command, however, a gift is such that the option to refuse it is there.
A third way acceptances relate to illocutionary/social acts is by being a necessary component of such acts. Acceptance is here required for the completion of the illocutionary/social act of which it is the necessary response. According to Austin, a bet is a relevant instance of the latter. “For a bet to have been made”, Austin notes, “it is generally necessary for the offer of the bet to have been accepted by a taker (who must have done something, such as to say ‘Done’)”.Footnote 33 A bet is an instance of a “bilateral act”, and the question is whether a gift is, as Austin also suggests, another bona fide instance of the kind. The idea is that it takes two for one to make a gift, the giftee playing his part of the act by accepting the gift, either explicitly or implicitly.
Michael Hancher concurs with this hypothesis.Footnote 34 The bilaterality of certain social/illocutionary acts, Hancher argues, is brought to light by the redundancy of adding “and he accepted the act” to any description of the related act. In particular, the bilaterality of appointment is underlined by noting that, in the following two sentences, “the extra clause [in (b)] goes without saying”:Footnote 35
[a] Smith appointed Jones to the committee.
[b] Smith appointed Jones to the committee and John accepted it.
Applying Hancher’s argument to gift, one may note the same stylistic awkwardness in:
[c] Julie gave her bike to Paul, and Paul accepted it.
Acceptance is already featured in (what is misguidedly described as) Julie’s act. Julie’s act is a bilateral act, one may further argue, because, unlike declining an invitation, declining a gift prevents it from being made. And this is in accordance with the intuition, previously described, about how the refusal of gifts which carry obligation results in their cancellation.
However, construing gifts as bilateral acts fails to account for the asymmetry underlined previously between the cancelling effect of refusing unwelcome gifts and the superfluity of accepting wanted gifts. The related asymmetry may be explained, I shall argue, in light of Reinach’s view about how the acts of accepting and declining respectively relate to promises. Reinach holds acceptance to be an unnecessary component of promises. Acceptance is not required “for the efficacy of the promise” according to Reinach and “can at most serve to confirm” it.Footnote 36 It is “not necessary to a promise that it be accepted.” The addressee of the promise, Reinach claims, only needs to “take cognizance of the act of promising”.Footnote 37 Acceptance is therefore a possible response to a promise (akin to acceptance being a possible response to an invitation). However, Reinach also holds conversely that “an act of declining [a promise] prevents both claim and obligation from coming into being”.Footnote 38 For example, if you decline my promise to invite you to play tennis with me once a month, you prevent me from incurring the obligation to invite you to play. The option of blocking a promise toward oneself seems important to secure when the promise gives rise to an obligation to act in some unwanted way. In the contrary case, accepting a promise appears as a superfluous addendum. Reinach’s view about the distinct jural effects of accepting and of declining promises points toward the following fourth hybrid case in which:
(iv) on the one hand, accepting a social/illocutionary act is an impossible response to that act and, on the other hand, declining the same social/illocutionary act brings its performance to a close.
The asymmetry previously outlined regarding accepting and refusing gifts, I submit, is another instance of these fourth hybrid cases. While it is not necessary for a gift to be accepted, declining a gift prevents its completion. The underlying explanation for the related asymmetry could be analogously related to the importance of not imposing on the recipient of a gift any potentially unwanted obligations. In particular, when a gift entails the transfer of certain obligation(s),Footnote 39 the option to prevent the gift from being made by refusing it should be at the giftee’s disposal.
The important point to retain is that whereas a gift does not require acceptance for being done, refusing a gift does block its completion. The distinct roles of accepting and refusing gifts, to which Reinach draws our attention through his analysis of acceptance of promises, seem to have been overlooked by Austin and Hancher. Having resolved the questions of the essential role of uptake (Section 10.2), and of the unessential role of acceptance (Section 10.3), I shall now emphasize the deontic dimensions of gifts.
10.4 Gifting by Transferring Ownership
A gift is intuitively visualized as someone handing something over to someone else. Austin has done a lot to show what is wrong with that view, redirecting our attention from the physical actions – here the handing – to the utterance. The latter, as Austin claims, is “a, or even, the leading incident in the performance of the act”.Footnote 40 However, Austin also remains faithful to the intuitive view by granting a key role to the gesture. “It is hardly a gift if I say ‘I give it you’ but never hand it over”.Footnote 41 The gesture associated with a gift need not be a handing. It can be a passing, a pointing, etc. In all cases, the intuitive idea seems to be that whatever is gifted to someone must be put at her disposal. To be sure, as it has certainly not escaped Austin, certain giftables (cars, houses, lands, etc.) are not liable to be handed over.Footnote 42 Implicit in the received view are therefore metaphysical limits as to what can be gifted. Only entities that are liable to be held and relocated are “giftables”.Footnote 43 These properties appropriately disqualify concepts, feelings, numbers, weddings as possible objects of gifts. However, the view also restricts “giftables” to “movables”, unduly ruling out gifts of things that are too heavy for being handed to anyone (cars) or gifts of things that by their nature (lands) remain where they are.Footnote 44 Be that as it may, it is tempting, following Austin, to assume that the handing, or some cognate gesture, is necessary to most other central cases of giftsFootnote 45.
In this section, I show why that intuitive view is not correct, and not even an accurate account of the restricted range of cases of movable gifts (flowers, rings, etc.) it is supposed to be. The main problem of the intuitive view is that it targets the things (the bike, the flowers, the glass of wine) involved in gifts as what is given to the giftee, whereas it is in fact their ownership that is fundamentally targeted by the act. When I give you my bike, what I fundamentally do is to convey to you the ownership I have over it. The revision suggested here is meant to be commonplace. Still, the change of focus from the object of gift to its ownership also has important implications, as I intend to show, which speech act theorists have disregarded as the result of their focus on the things that are gifted instead of the change of ownership that these things undergo when they are brought to someone as gifts.
Let us remark, first, that the distinction between the thing that is owned and the ownership that someone has over that thing is sometimes hidden in ordinary talk. French people refer to what they own as “ma propriété” (“my ownership”) as if ownership was a generic category that comprises all the things that someone owns. Likewise, one commonly hears of “someone having ownership over something”. This misleadingly suggests that ownership can be had by someone, therefore being itself liable to enter into another ownership relation, in a regressus ad infinitum inasmuch as this new ownership relation would also be liable to be owned, etc.
Reinach’s theory of ownership, to which I now turn, scrupulously prevents the confusion.Footnote 46 This is because Reinach conceives ownershipFootnote 47 as a dyadic relation between someone (the owner) and a thing.Footnote 48 To have the ownership of a bike is to relate to that bike in a particular way. Reinach further qualifies the ownership relation as a “thoroughly ‘natural’ relation which is no more artificially produced than is the relation of similarity or of spatial proximity”.Footnote 49 Reinach also holds ownership to be a prelegal relation, one that “comes into being even where there is no positive law”.Footnote 50 The island on which Crusoe is shipwrecked provides the fictitious law-free environment in support of that view. “When Robinson Crusoe produces for himself all kinds of things on his island, these things belong to him”.Footnote 51 The ownership relation is further qualified as a primitive relation, that is, as one that “cannot be further resolved into elements”.Footnote 52 Moreover, but no less crucially, it is, Reinach claims, ownership over a thing which confers to the owner “the right to deal in any and every way with the thing”.Footnote 53 Against the proponents of the bundle of rights theory of ownership, Reinach urges us not to conflate the ownership relation with “the absolute right [of the owner] to deal in any way he likes with the thing which belongs to him”.Footnote 54 These absolute property rights, while distinct from the ownership relation, are also “grounded” in the latter. Reinach subscribes to the view that ownership “is itself not a right over a thing, but rather a relation (Verhältnis) to the thing, a relation in which all rights over it are grounded”.Footnote 55 As Olivier Massin suggests, the grounding relation between the absolute property rights and ownership is an essential relation.Footnote 56 It is in virtue of the essence of ownership that whoever owns a thing also has the absolute right to use that thing in whichever way she desires.
The ownership relation between an owner and what she owns stands in contrast to other kinds of relations between persons and things. In particular, the ownership relation differs from the relation of possession that someone has over the thing he has at his disposal. If the ownership/possession distinction sounds otiose, it is because often the owner of a thing also possesses it. However, it is among the sophistications of Reinach’s theory of ownership to accommodate the cases where possession is dissociated from ownership. The dissociation occurs when someone steals something. While the thief now has possession of the bike, he has not acquired its ownership.
Once ownership, so defined, is recognized as the targetFootnote 57 of gifts, it becomes clear why the gestures (the handing over, passing, putting forth, etc.) included in the intuitive view are not relevant to the act. Ownership occupies no space, has no weight, nor has the three-dimensions of its two relata. If so, while the thing that is gifted may be liable to be grasped, handed over to the giftee and be thus relocated, its ownership moves nowhere, and, in fact, is nowhere. And yet, it is really the ownership over the thing – being conveyed, as it were, from the gifter to the giftee – that undergoes the crucial ontological change in all cases. The complexity of gift as a “four-legged act” (involving a gifter, a thing that is gifted, the ownership of that thing, and the giftee) is revealed. We may accordingly redescribe a gift as an act by means of which someone (namely, the gifter) makes someone else (namely, the giftee) the new owner of a thing.
The alternative and presumably refined view of gift here outlined – the Ownership View of Gift (hereafter “OVG”), as I name it – differs from the intuitive view in several respects. First, the intuitive view, because it focuses on the thing that is gifted, is attentive to what now appear to be contingent features (the change of location, the episodic nature of the act). The OVG focuses on the ownership over that thing as the necessary target of gifts. From this perspective, a gift is an instantaneous act (while it takes time for a thing to be handed over to someone, the change of ownership undergone by that thing takes no time).
Secondly, whereas the intuitive view ascribes a central role to the physical gestures by which the gift is carried to the giftee, the OVG urges the neglect of these gestures and puts forth the (implied or explicit) utterances through which gifts are made as essential to their performance.
Thirdly, whereas, on the intuitive view, a gift is one by which the gifter gives a good to someone, the OVG offers a different view of the nature of the illocutionary of the act – one that makes someone the new owner of somethingFootnote 58 – that is performed when a gift is made.
Fourthly, whereas the intuitive view of gift, focusing as it does on the thing that is being gifted, is prone to identify the “commissive” aspect of gift (i.e., the fact that the speaker is committed to bring that thing to the giftee), the OVG, emphasizing the underlying ontological change of ownership, redirects attention to the power of gifts to change reality. As Reinach insists, the ontological change taking place when “a thing is conveyed ‘into the [ownership]Footnote 59 of another’ […] is more than a linguistic turn of phrase. It is really the case that the supporting member of the relation of owning (i.e. the owner) modifies the relation by his own act in such a way that he drops out of the relation and someone else takes his place, though for the rest the thing and the relation remain identically the same”.Footnote 60 To understand the nature of the power of the transfer of ownership, Searle’s distinction between speech acts with a “word-to-world” and those with a “world-to-word direction of fit”Footnote 61 is helpful. The typical utterances (“this is yours”) through which gifts are made have both directions of fit. Their propositional content not only “represents the reality as being so changed”,Footnote 62 it also modifies the reality to make it match the content. The distinctive power of gifts to change reality is one the intuitive view, fixed as it is on the contingent changes of location sometimes undergone by the thing that is gifted, cannot properly register. Uttering “I hereby transfer to you the ownership of the bike”Footnote 63 is more truthful, even if admittedly clumsy, to the ontological changes involved in gifts than “I hereby give you my bike”.
Fifthly, the two views differ in their conception of the illocutionary force of the utterances (how that utterance should be interpretedFootnote 64) through which gifts are made. Whereas the intuitive view refers to the illocutionary force of the utterance as to give, the OVG takes it to be to make someone the new owner of something. To my knowledge, there is no single English term for that illocutionary force – a noteworthy lacuna given the use of “appropriation” for the act of making oneself the new owner of a thing.
While all these differences vindicate the OVG, indeed revealing its greater accuracy, a proponent of the OVG also faces additional challenges from which advocates of the intuitive view are spared. In particular, if the illocutionary force of a gift is, as the OVG has it, the making of someone else the owner of a thing, it is presumably an act that has the effect of altering the deontic status of both the gifter (who loses the ownership of the thing and property rights over that thing) and the giftee (who correlatively acquires both). Following Reinach, we may refer to “the jural power to produce, modify, etc. rights and obligations through his own social acts” and the “natural ability” to, say, hand over something to someone.Footnote 65 The proponent of the OVG is expected to specify who has the related jural power to make someone the owner of a thing, and also which social/illocutionary act that person has to perform to that jural effect. The OVG will readily provide the requested clarifications as follows. For X (the gifter) to have the jural power to make Y (the giftee) the new owner of a, it needs to be the case that:
[1] X is the owner of a.
[2] X transfers ownership of a to Y.
Both requirements are commonsensical. In his entry “Speech Act” of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,Footnote 66 Mitchell Green gives voice to [1] when he points to the “preparatory conditions” that must be met for the speech to not misfire, illustrated by the case of a person who “cannot bequeath an object unless she already owns it”.Footnote 67 As far as the role of transfer in gift, it is widely recognized among legal theorists.Footnote 68 However, although scholars correctly point to the role of transfer in gifts, they fail to notice, let alone think through, as Reinach does, the ontological change and deontic aspects that transfers of ownership have the power to bring about.
First, the ontological change realized by a transfer of ownership is “to change the relation of belonging by changing its bearer”.Footnote 69 The content of the transfer – what is transferred – need not be an ownership relation. A transfer can, alternatively or additionally, bear on property rights, on a relative obligation, on a claim or on a jural power. In each case, however, the act of transfer is such that, as Edmund Husserl puts it, “through it” an entity “passes from one person to another”.Footnote 70 In other words, a transfer unfolds in such a way that at the beginning the transferor has the entity and the transferee does not have it, whereas at the end, the transferee has the entity and the transferor does not.Footnote 71
Secondly, both legal scholars and speech act theorists who reflect on gifts fail to register that “[t]he transferring of [ownership] also presupposes a power to transfer insofar as owning essentially implies the right to deal in any and every way with the thing, the power to transfer the thing into the ownership of others is contained in this right”.Footnote 72 The power (or right) to transfer ownership is just one of the “absolute rights” that the ownership relation, in virtue of its nature, confers to owners. “It is grounded in the essence of owning”, Reinach claims, “that the owner has the absolute right to deal in any way he likes with the thing which belongs to him”.Footnote 73 The jural powers grounded in ownership stand in contrast to the jural powers that have their source “in the person as such”.Footnote 74 Following Kevin Mulligan, the distinction between those jural powers that are grounded in ownership and those that have their source in personhood may be further explicated as follows. While being a person is all that is needed for having the jural power to “apologize, promise, accept promises, order, ask questions, answer questions, inform, grant, request, submit himself, thank”,Footnote 75 merely being a person does not suffice for being endowed with the jural powers to condemn, to declare (war), to baptize, to dissolve the government or to petition for bankruptcy. Likewise, I submit, being a (thin) person does not suffice for having the jural power to transfer to someone the ownership of a thing. Only those (thick) persons who have the ownership of that thing in the first place have the jural power to transfer its ownership to someone else. By extension, one may say that gifters do not have the power to make a gift of a thing they do not own. Speech act theorists, such as Hancher, point to the “commissive” dimension of gifts,Footnote 76 suggesting that utterances such as “Have some wine” commit the gifter to making what is gifted readily available. However, it may now appear that the March Hare’s misfired gift to Alice could instead be a matter of the March Hare not having the jural power of gifting the wine to Alice.
Because the OVG confines the category of gift to the transfer of ownership, it conceptually rules out the gifts of stolen things. Approached in consideration of Reinach’s distinction between ownership and possession, the gifts of stolen things would correspond to the case where what is transferred is the possession of a thing. Someone who has stolen a bike possesses the bike without owning it. She can transfer the possession of the bike to someone else without thus transferring the ownership of the bike. If Julie steals John’s bike, Julie possesses it while John still owns it although he has lost the power to use it. Julie can then transfer her possession of John’s bike. Paul is now the new possessor of the motorcycle, while John remains its owner. Now the pressing question is: Has Julie gifted John’s bike? The answer to that question is not entirely clear and depends on whether a transfer of possession that is dissociated from a transfer of ownership can have the illocutionary force of a gift. I shall point to two implausible implications as decisive considerations in support of ruling out the related case. First, it would entail that the recipient of the gift possesses that which she is gifted without being further endowed with its ownership or with the property rights to use the thing. While the recipient would be able to make use of the thing, she would not have the property rights to act accordingly.
It is time to recap the sequences that, on the OVG, unfold in many central cases. For X (a gifter) to gift her a to Y (the giftee), it needs to be the case that:
(i) X initially owns a.
(ii) X utters, either implicitly or explicitly: “I hereby transfer the ownership of a to Y”.
(iii) Y hears and understands X’s utterance.
(iv) Y does not decline the transfer of ownership.
(v) As the result of (i)–(iv), Y becomes the new owner of a.
The OVG, as it is outlined here, may appear to achieve generality at the cost of being at odds with the intuitive understanding of the act. One may object that it is at odds with the ordinary use of the term “gift” which does bear on things, not on their ownership, let alone a relation between someone and a thing. However, the OVG does not conflict with the widespread view that the objects of gifts are things. It really is the bike (not its ownership) that I bring to you as a gift. The rectification that the OVG urges to make regards technical aspects of gifts. In particular, the OVG presses for reconsidering the illocutionary act by which a gift is done in terms of a transfer of ownership from oneself to the recipient of that gift. The OVG also presses for reconsidering the illocutionary force of a gift as making someone the new owner of a thing.
10.5 Jeremy Waldron’s Encounter: How to Make Gifts by Waiving Ownership
Jeremy Waldron also purports to define “what charityFootnote 77 is and what it involves”.Footnote 78 Waldron intends to refute both the view “that charity involves a positive act of assistance”Footnote 79 and the correlated claim that “withholding charity can be seen as an omission – a mere failure to act”.Footnote 80 As he notes, “[t]his image of charity derives from the old biblical story of the Good Samaritan”, the latter being usually seen as actively doing what is needed to rescue the man. In the biblical story, “charity means putting oneself out, actively intervening for someone else’s benefits”.Footnote 81 As a plausible alternative, Waldron proposes “a different image of charity” as being achieved “by doing nothing”Footnote 82 (or almost nothing, as I will shortly explain).
Waldron tells two variants of the biblical story. In the first, two bad Samaritans actively prevent some weary travelers from helping themselves to the foods displayed on a table in their house. In the second version, one good Samaritan inactively lets weary travelers help themselves to the food. What the latter version reveals, Waldron argues, is that charity can consist in “passively allowing another to help himself to the resources”:Footnote 83
As we noted earlier, charity involves giving but giving – the exercise of the power of alienation of one’s property – need not involve any active or onerous expenditure of effort. If you have physical possession of my typewriter already (you were carrying it home for me, say, as a favor), and I say, “Keep it – it’s yours”, the only action I have to perform is the purely symbolic or gestural one of saying that a gift has been made. To give you something, I do not have to put myself out for your sake or come actively to your assistance. The airiest waiver of my property rights is reasonably sufficient.Footnote 84
The central claim here is that waiving property rights over something (in the present case, a typewriter) suffices for giving it to someone just in case the latter is able to help himself to, or is already in possession of, the thing. The conception of gift defended here advances two requirements. One is the “waiving of property rights”, which Waldron correctly conceives as being performed in the mere uttering “Keep it – it’s yours”. The other requirement is on the recipient of the gift, who is expected all by herself to enter into possession of that which is gifted.
According to Waldron, the originality of this conception is that it dispenses with the physical acts (such as “putting myself out for your sake”) which, on a more conventional conception, are necessary for making a gift. From this perspective, Waldron seems to endorse a version of the OVG presented in Section 10.4. However, Waldron’s view does depart from the OVG when, instead of a transfer of property rights,Footnote 85 it puts forth a waiving of these property rights as the act by which the change of ownership is brought about.
Waldron is right to note that the mere waiving of property rights does not suffice for making anyone the bearer of these property rights. Waiving property rights over a leaves a un-owned. Waldron is also right to claim that entering into a relation of possession with something can in itself create an ownership relation with that thing. However, Waldron is wrong to infer that the performance of these two amalgamated acts – a waiving on one side matched by an act of appropriation on the other – amounts to the making of a gift. Reinach’s insights about the social/illocutionary act of waiving can be mobilized to explain why it is so. Waiving, as Reinach notes, is “a social act which lacks the moment of other-directedness. Waiving refers merely to that which is waived, in this case to the claim; it is not directed to a person”.Footnote 86 Waiving, like declaring, revoking and enacting, belongs to the sub-category of social acts which are not other-directed. In support of that observation, one may note that the following sentence:
[d] “I hereby waive my property right over that thing to you.”
does not sound correct. The important point is that if a waiving is not other-directed, the act fails to display the other-directedness that is essential to gifts: the fact that the propositional content of the sentence through which a gift is made always refers to the recipients of that gift.
Although a gift cannot be done by merely waiving a property right over a thing, the social/illocutionary act of waiving can be involved in genuine cases of gift. Consider the case of Julie who promises to give Paul her bike if he gives her CHF100. Julie’s conditional promise is a defining feature of economic exchanges.Footnote 87 Suppose that Paul gives to Julie the requested amount and then changes his mind: he no longer wants to buy Julie’s bike and is also willing to not ask Julie to give him back the CHF100 that he transferred to her. Maybe Paul has been told that Julie put her bike on sale because she urgently needs the money. Because Paul wants to be kind to Julie, he is now disposed to gift her the CHF100 which he initially transferred in exchange for the bike. What Paul can do (and this is, in fact, the only thing he can do) so that Julie has the right to keep both his money and her bike is to waive his claim over Julie’s bike.
The fictitious example described here illustrates a way of making a gift other than by transferring the ownership of the thing that is gifted. Paul has already transferred the CHF100 to Julie, but the transfer was done in the context of an economic exchange between the two. The ownership of the CHF100 was shifted to Julie when she and Paul were still engaged in buying and selling each other’s goods. What makes the case tricky is that Paul makes Julie the new owner of his CHF100 not by transferring to her his ownership over the money, but by waiving his claim over Julie’s bike. The money is what Paul gifts to Julie. But the social/illocutionary act that Paul performs in order to gift the money to Julie is to waive his claim over Julie’s bike. It is a case of an economic exchange that evolves into a case of gifts as the effect of a social/illocutionary act, namely a waiving of a claim, that modifies the nature of the interaction. It is a case in which a buyer (Paul) takes the role of a gifter while the seller (Julie) becomes ipso facto the beneficiary of a gift.
10.6 Conclusion
This chapter is a follow-up to dispersed and occasional remarks on gifts that speech act theorists have made. Far from having the ambition to be a speech act theory of gifts, the upshots of the present inquiry can nonetheless be assembled in the form of a (non-exhaustive and provisional) list of conditions for the (illocutionary-)making of gifts. It is time to recap the main findings and also to gesture at some of the issues that a full-blown speech act theory of gifts would have to tackle.
I have first shown that a gift has not been made if the giftee has not grasped the utterance through which it is made. Strawson may have been misled by the other-directedness of the writing of a will that is never read into supposing that it is a bona fide instance of a speech act. While the orthodox view about the utterance being essential to the illocutionary act remains unchallenged, it is not entirely clear, as Maryam Ebrahimi Dinani rightly points out, what from Reinach’s perspective “the general requirement of grasp” precisely means.Footnote 88 In the case of gifts, it is an interesting question to ask the extent of the understanding that is implied in the grasping. While it seems reasonable to require that the addressee understands the nature of the act (as an instance of a gift) as well as the role (that of its recipient) she is ascribed in the act, it is less clear whether the addressee is also further expected to grasp the nature of the social/illocutionary act (an act of transfer) performed and also the illocutionary force of the utterance (making her a new owner) through which the act is made. What knowledge of these various hidden aspects of the gift should be expected on the part of the addressee? The level of understanding that the general requirement of grasp presupposes needs to be specified to avoid a theory of gift that is too cognitively demanding, because it is at odds with the intuitive, pre-theoretical understanding of the act that manifestly suffices for its successful performance.
A second result of the inquiry is that a gift may not be the “bilateral act” that Austin has in mind if its acceptance, in the form of a social/illocutionary act, is superfluous, as I have argued. Granted: the intended recipient of a gift has the option to prevent the act from being completed. However, if this is what is at stake, the option can be chosen simply by declining the gift in the relevant circumstance. It seems unnecessary, I have argued, that the recipient also does her part of the act, as it were, by accepting the gift in the alternative circumstance where she wants it.
There is another reason for rejecting the requirement of acceptance. It tends to confound what is fundamentally a single act with a collective one. The way the giftee is essential to the act of gifting is not by co-performing the act, but simply by uptaking it. The utterance through which the gifter makes a gift has to be heard and understood by the giftee, but the gifter is the only agent making that gift.Footnote 89 Thus, although a gift involves two persons, it remains the act of one person only. There is no we-gift, only an I-gift matched by a You-uptake.
Finally, it is a third result of the inquiry to press for a shift of focus from the thing that is the object of the gift to the ownership over that thing that is transferred to the giftee. The merits of the shift of attention are threefold: to lay bare the metaphysical underpinning of the act, to confront us with its conceptual boundaries, and to accommodate a greater range of cases. The unexpected variety of gifts is maybe the most striking result of the present inquiry. To gift my bike to you, I can either transfer its ownership to you, grant you the right to revoke your promise to pay for it or waive the right I have over the amount of money you owe me. One can also suppose that the actual diversity of the act is not fully laid bare by these three sub-cases, and therefore the subject matter warrants further exploration.Footnote 90
11.1 Introduction
Promises are ubiquitous in our social life: we plan our conduct based on the promises that we make and those addressed to us. We build our reputation on the promises we honor. We blame those who do not fulfil their promises, and we apologize if we are not able to deliver what we promised. The concept of a promise is also of crucial importance to disciplines such as law and economics, as promises arguably lie at the heart of contracts and economic exchanges.Footnote 1
Given the pervasiveness of promises in our social world, it should not be surprising if they come in many shapes and forms. In line with considerations about promises developed by Adolf ReinachFootnote 2 and Margaret Gilbert,Footnote 3 this paper focuses on the “informal” or “everyday” sense of promise according to which, if something qualifies as a promise, it imposes an obligation on the promisor and an equivalent claim (or: demand-right) on the promisee, regardless of whether or not the speaker uses the term “promise.”Footnote 4 One key question for any theory of promises, so understood, is: how do promises generate obligations and claims? This chapter addresses this question by comparing Gilbert’s theory of promise with the remarkably similar, and yet importantly different account developed by Reinach at the start of the twentieth century. This is the plan ahead.
In Section 11.2, we present Gilbert’s background motivations for her account of promises. The account aims at vindicating two intuitions about promises and at rejecting three “dogmas,” which she identifies as core to contemporary debates about promises. In this section we also show that Reinach warmheartedly shares Gilbert’s intuitions and that therefore he, too, rebuts the three dogmas.
In Section 11.3, we introduce Gilbert’s account of promises. According to her view, promissory obligations and claims are brought about by certain commitments that promisor and promisee jointly enter. Hence, the reason why promises generate claims and obligations is that promises are to be explained in terms of joint commitments, and joint commitments generate claims and obligations.
Sections 11.4 to 11.6 marshal ideas borrowed from Reinach’s theory of promise to reject the account: while endorsing Gilbert’s background motivations, Reinach’s theory rejects the possibility for promises to have a (or any) substantive explanation and, thus, provides reasons for dismissing Gilbert’s positive account of promise in terms of joint commitments. In particular, Section 11.4 argues, contra Gilbert, that promises do not necessarily require acceptance. Section 11.5 claims that Gilbert’s account misidentifies the authors of promises and Section 11.6 that it misconstrues the content of promises.
While the result of our discussion is mainly negative, Section 11.7 maintains that Gilbert’s research program of understanding the capacity of promises to generate claims and obligations without falling prey to the three dogmas remains wide open. We suggest that progress in this research program can be achieved by taking seriously Reinach’s idea that the search for a substantive explanation of the fact that promises generate claims and obligations is pointless and that promises generate those normative entities in virtue of their nature or essence.Footnote 5
11.2 Three Dogmas vs. Two Intuitions
Three dogmas, according to Gilbert, steer contemporary debate about promising: the Moral Requirement dogma, the No Willing dogma, and the Immoral Promises dogma.Footnote 6
The Moral Requirement dogma goes back at least to Thomas Scanlon’s understanding of promissory obligations: “When promises give rise to […] obligation, these can be accounted for on the basis of general moral principles.”Footnote 7 Scanlon’s idea is that honoring a promise is dictated by a moral requirement, which derives from moral principle(s) and that these moral principles do not depend on contingent agreements or other conventional arrangements among people.
Moral Requirement dogma: When promises give rise to obligations, they do so in virtue of some moral principles.
The Moral Requirement dogma, Gilbert argues, is the most important among the three assumptions because it directly sustains the other two, as we will soon see.
The second dogma, called “No Willing” dogma, is expressed in Hume’s notorious passage “‘Tis impossible that we could ever will a new obligation,”Footnote 8 which can be reformulated this way:
No Willing dogma: Mere willing cannot bring about obligations.
In a nutshell, this dogma captures the idea that a personal (private or inner) act of the will does not have the normative power to generate an obligation. The Moral Requirement dogma and the No Willing dogma are related: given that the obligation to honor a promise is a moral requirement and given that moral requirements are not grounded in voluntary agreements or arrangements among people, mere acts of the will cannot bring about promissory obligations. Finally, we have the
Immoral Promises dogma: Immoral promises do not put their subject under an obligation to act as promised.
Gilbert argues that this third dogma, too, gains persuasive force from the Moral Requirement dogma. For, if promissory obligations are moral requirements, then promises with an immoral content do not generate obligations. The moral requirement the promisor is actually subject to is not to keep immoral promises.
Gilbert contrasts these dogmas with two intuitions. The first intuition is what she calls “Inevitability Point.”Footnote 9 This point relates to Prichard’s view that “[o]nce call some act a promise [sic], and all question of whether there is an obligation to do it seems to have vanished.”Footnote 10 She formulates the intuition as follows:
Inevitability Point: “[I]f someone has made a promise to do something, then he is obligated to it, by virtue of his promise.”Footnote 11
Reinach concurs: “The promising produces a unique bond between two persons in virtue of which the one person […] can claim something and the other is obliged to perform it or to grant it.”Footnote 12 So, Reinach agrees with Gilbert that promises inevitably generate obligations. However, it is worth noting that Reinach here goes beyond Gilbert’s “inevitability point” as stated above, for her “point” does not state that the noted obligation correlates with a claim. However, we will soon see that, for Gilbert too, promissory obligations correlate with claims (or demand-rights).
The Inevitability Point, Gilbert adds, is something that is known a priori.Footnote 13 Reinach, again, agrees: “[…] claim and obligation are grounded with essential necessity in the act of promising as such.”Footnote 14 It is noteworthy that this last point can have two different readings: a strong and a weak one. The weak reading is this:
Inevitability Point (weak reading): If someone has made a promise to do something, then, in the absence of sufficiently powerful countervailing considerations, he is obligated to do it by virtue of his promise.
Yet, Gilbert and Reinach both insist that only the strong reading properly captures our intuitions on this matter:
Inevitability Point (strong reading): If someone has made a promise to do something, then he is obligated to do it by virtue of his promise.
They are not claiming that one is obliged to keep one’s promises, no matter what. Their position tacitly builds on the distinction between pro tanto and pro toto obligations.Footnote 15 Pro toto obligations are resultant or all things considered obligations: these are obligations which result from weighing all – possibly conflicting – pro tanto obligations that are attached to one and the same action.Footnote 16 Promissory obligations may conflict with and be overrun by other obligations, and then be contrary to resultant or pro toto obligations.Footnote 17 Against this backdrop, Gilbert and Reinach’s strong reading of the Inevitability Point is that an obligation is necessarily brought to existence by the promise, but this obligation is only pro tanto, so that it may conflict with and be overrun by other obligations.
On this strong reading, the Inevitability Point is incompatible with the Immoral Promises dogma. For, if promises always generate obligations, then so do immoral promises, contra the Immoral Promises dogma. Furthermore, this suggests, contra the Moral Requirement dogma, that promissory obligations are not moral obligations because moral principles cannot generate obligations with morally heinous content.
The second intuition Gilbert endorses is that promissory obligations are relational, that is, they are directed at somebody else: the promisee. Gilbert captures this idea by talking of “directed” obligations and “directed” claims (or “demand-rights”Footnote 18): it is because the promisor’s obligation is directed to the promisee that the promisee (and only them) have the “standing to demand” the promised action of the promisor. If Laura has an obligation to Sam to call him, then Sam can authoritatively demand of Laura that she call him. In a certain sense, Laura owes it to Sam to call him, and Sam therefore has the standing to demand that of her: if Laura does not do that, Sam is in a position to rebuke her. This suggests that any promissory obligation of the promisor, in virtue of its directedness, is equivalent to a promisee’s claim against the promisor:
The relationality of obligations and claims also is at the core of Reinach’s theory: “There […] exists a correlativity between [promissory] claim and obligation: each has identically the same content, and the relations of bearer and partner are mutually interwoven according to strict apriori law.”Footnote 19
This second intuition is in tension with the Moral Requirement dogma because it assigns a particular standing to the promisee, which the Moral Requirement dogma is not able to accommodate. Why? Recall that, according to the Moral Requirement dogma, promissory obligations are moral requirements.Footnote 20 When a moral requirement is violated, everybody has the same “standing to demand compliance, if anyone does.” If so, the Moral Requirement dogma leaves unexplained Laura’s special standing towards Sam, which is captured by the idea that Sam has an obligation directed towards Laura (and, conversely, Laura has a claim that is directed towards Sam).
The interim conclusion of this discussion is that the two intuitions put unsurmountable pressure on the Moral Requirement dogma. In addition, given that the No Willing dogma and the Immoral Promises dogma are directly supported by the Moral Requirement dogma, if this goes, they too stand on shaky ground. Gilbert and Reinach agree on all this: a good account of promises should preserve the two intuitions and reject the three dogmas. Put differently: promises are intentional acts,Footnote 21 which necessarily give rise to nonmoral, relational claims and obligations. They part ways, however, when it comes to the positive account of promises.
11.3 The Joint Commitment Account of Promising
Endorsing the two intuitions and, thus, rejecting the three dogmas leaves one with the proverbial elephant in the room: if promissory obligations necessarily arise from promises, though not in virtue of some moral principles, how do promises bring them about? To provide an answer to the question, Gilbert introduces her joint commitment account of promises:Footnote 22
Joint commitment account: X has made a promise to Y if and only if (1) X and Y are jointly committed to endorse as a body a particular plan of action P, and (2) X and Y created this joint commitment by virtue of appropriate, explicit expressions on the part of each, in conditions of common knowledge and (3) P specifies an action for X.Footnote 23
Promises are accounted for in terms of (joint) commitments. What are commitments? Although “committing oneself” has a psychological connotation, on Gilbert’s understanding, commitments – personal or joint – are normative, nonpsychological phenomena.Footnote 24 The psychological process of committing oneself should not be conflated with its normative product: “to commit” and “committing” are psychological; “to be committed” and “commitment” are normative.Footnote 25
Against this background, personal commitments are normative phenomena created by acts of the individual will, namely intentions or decisions.Footnote 26 In this sense, commitments are “creatures of the will.”Footnote 27 Although normative, no moral valence is attached to commitments: “[t]o commit oneself [in this sense] is to make it the case that one has sufficient reason to do a certain thing.”Footnote 28 If Laura decides to kill Sam, Laura now has a sufficient reason to do so because her decision has brought about a personal commitment, independently of its immoral content. (One could add that the commitment at stake is pro tanto, given that other reasons, and especially moral reasons, which may speak against the action, accrue to her.) Importantly, a personal commitment can be reneged on by its very bearer solo, as it were. Changing one’s mind is a personal affair, which may be difficult and may come with psychological costs, but which is possible without the subject consulting with anybody else. Yet, this very possibility is precluded when it comes to joint commitments. Why is that and, more generally, what are joint commitments?
A joint commitment is one commitment (not a combination of commitments) of two or more persons by these two or more persons. Roughly put, the form of joint commitments is this: “A and B are jointly committed to φ as a body” (where φ is an agential or psychological predicate). A joint commitment is brought about when individuals express their readiness for a particular joint commitment with one another, under conditions of common knowledge.Footnote 29 Importantly, “expressing readiness” should be understood as “expressing that state of [the] will that is readiness […].”Footnote 30 Imagine Laura telling Sam “should we go for a walk?” and Sam “sure, lets!”Footnote 31 In this case, Laura and Sam have expressed, under conditions of common knowledge, their relevant states of the will that is each one’s readiness jointly to commit to taking up as a body the goal of going for a walk. They are, therefore, jointly committed to doing so. Thus, in the same way in which personal decisions create personal commitments, so expressions of states of the will that are readiness to jointly commit (under conditions of common knowledge) create joint commitments. A joint commitment (just as with a personal commitment) provides each of the parties sufficient reason to conform to it: “If […] one is jointly committed […], [o]ne therefore has sufficient reason for performing actions that conform to the commitment, sufficient reason that is independent of one’s inclinations and self-interest.” Interestingly, Gilbert continues by stating that: “in the case of a personal decision, intention, and so on, the normative force of this commitment can be eradicated by one’s own fiat. Failing special background understandings, that is not so in [the] case [of joint commitment].”Footnote 32
So, joint commitments, in contrast to personal commitments, cannot be rescinded by a single party unilaterally (barring special background understandings). Why? Because a joint commitment, Gilbert claims, creates a set of directed obligations and correlative rights. These obligations and rights block the possibility for a single individual to renege on a joint commitment unilaterally. Put another way, each party of a joint commitment not only is obligated to the others to conform to the commitment, they can also authoritatively demand conforming actions of the others. Note that these obligations and rights are content-independent, meaning that they are not moral and do not derive from moral principles. As long as a joint commitment is in place, corresponding obligations and rights arise, regardless of the moral content of that commitment.
Before assessing the joint commitment of promises, three clarifications are in order.
First, Gilbert’s position on what X and Y are committed to, when X makes a promise to Y, has evolved through time. In a former version of her theory,Footnote 33 X are Y are held to be jointly committed to the decision that X performs a certain action. In the last version presented here,Footnote 34 X are Y are jointly committed to an action plan that specifies an action of X. While the distinction between commitment to decisions to act and commitment to plans to act matters in various respects, we shall consider the two versions of theory to be equivalent for the purposes of our paper given that our objections do not hang on that point.
Second, it should be stressed that, despite its name, the joint commitment account does not equate promises with joint commitments. As we have seen, commitments are normative phenomena that ensue from the persons’ acts of committing. The distinction between the joint commitment and the actions of X and Y that give rise to it is reflected in the use of the present and past tense in Gilbert’s definition. This is perhaps more easily seen in Gilbert’s earlier formulation of her view:
for one person to make a promise to another is for them jointly to commit themselves, by an appropriate, explicit process, to the decision that one of them (“the promisor”) is to perform one or more specified actions.Footnote 35
We infer from this that, on the joint commitment account, making a promise consists in the acts of jointly committing, not in the (normative) state of being jointly committed.
Thirdly, a clarification about the notion of “jointly committing” is in order. The acts of jointly committing mentioned in Gilbert’s account of promises must not, on pain of circularity, be understood as joint actions in a collective sense, according to which an action is joint if it is performed upon a shared intention.Footnote 36 For her notion of shared intention is explained by that of joint commitment: in brief, the intention to φ is shared by X and Y iff X and Y are jointly committed to intend as a body to φ.Footnote 37 So, if joint commitment were created by joint acts of committing (in the collective understanding of “joint acts,” which presupposes shared intentions), then her theory would become vulnerable to a charge of circularity. Therefore, the appeal to the notion of “jointly committing” in her account should be read in the noncollective (or “distributive”) sense, according to which X’s act of expressing personal readiness for the joint commitment in question and Y’s act of expressing personal readiness for the same joint commitment do not presuppose X and Y’s shared intention to perform the relevant acts. Once the necessary expressions have been made under condition of common knowledge, then the joint commitment will be in place, as is understood by the parties.
We now have all the elements required to appreciate Gilbert’s account of promises. Laura’s promise to Sam to call him later is Laura and Sam’s joint commitment to decide or endorse as a body the plan that Laura calls Sam later (a joint plan arrived at by a particular process e.g., Laura’s saying “I promise…” and Sam offering an accepting response; on such a “response” more later).
Why should one favor the joint commitment account of promises? Gilbert gives four arguments in its support.
1. The first argument is that the joint commitment account vindicates the two intuitions. Thus, the account explains why a promise necessarily generates an obligation and why that obligation is relational.
2. Second, the joint commitment account jettisons the three dogmas. It rejects the Moral Requirement dogma because no moral principle is appealed to in order to explain the pro tanto obligation of a promisor to perform the promise. The No Willing dogma is also dismissed: while the obligation, as a matter of fact, is willed into existence, but its creation does not happen merely in virtue of the individual will of the promisor, but in virtue of two individual wills.Footnote 38 Finally, the Immoral Promises dogma, too, is subject to rejection: promissory obligations are content-independent, which means that, regardless of their content, they are brought into being by the joint commitment.
Gilbert adds what in her eyes constitutes two further advantages of her view:
3. If promises are joint commitments to the decision that the promisor φs, then the jointness of that commitment requires that not only the promisor, but also the promisee, is active in a certain sense. This conforms to our intuitions, according to Gilbert, so that: “one point in favor of the joint commitment account of promises is that […] the promisee must do something of an accepting rather than a rejecting nature”Footnote 39 (note that acceptance does not have to be verbal, but it is not mere uptake or acknowledgmentFootnote 40).
4. Finally, Gilbert claims that her view entails that, when a promise is made, not only the promisor but also the promisee takes on some obligation (whose content is not specified in the content of the promise). She takes this to be a welcome consequence of her account, which again is supposed to conform to our intuition: imagine Laura promises to call Sam on the phone, Sam accepts that, but then he takes his phone off the hook. On Gilbert’s account, Laura can rebuke Sam authoritatively because Sam has the obligation to Laura not to make her calling him impossible.Footnote 41 Since joint commitments generate both obligations and rights, on each of its parties, this intuition is also explained by the account.
In the next three sections, we mount several objections against Gilbert’s theory of promises. These objections are grounded in elements of Reinach’s theory of promises. While we flag these elements by referring to Reinach’s text, our objections are substantive, rather than historical or exegetical.
11.4 First Objection: Acceptance
One important element in Gilbert’s theory of promises, which has been mentioned only briefly in the previous sections is this: “[p]romising,” she writes, “is understood to include whatever is necessary to supplement the actions of the promisor in order to complete the promise; this […] includes the promisee’s acceptance.”Footnote 42 Gilbert specifies that acceptance is a kind of concurrence as opposed to mere acknowledgment: “if Jeremy were to make a prediction, such as ‘I think I’ll be calling you tonight, it’s going to be hard being home alone,’ Julia might respond with ‘I hear you.’ This would be a case of acknowledgment without acceptance in the sense at issue.”Footnote 43 However, Gilbert otherwise does not elaborate extensively on the credentials of this act. In this section, we follow Reinach in canvassing various senses of “acceptance” and show that none of them are necessary for the promise.Footnote 44
First, “acceptance” could point to (1) an act of inner assent, which can be described as the experience of saying “yes” to a certain content that p as contrasted with the experience of merely entertaining the content that p or refusing it. The specific credentials of this act (e.g., whether it is a dispositional belief or an episodic action) are not of interest for our present purposes. What is important, though, is that this act (just as beliefs and other mental actions) is internal in the sense that it does not stand under the requirement of being expressed to others.
The second sense of acceptance (2) discussed by Reinach is the – nonintentional and noncommunicative – expression of (1), for example, nodding while reading a contract we are asked to sign. This sense of acceptance bears little or no relevance to our discussion, which is why we won’t dwell on it, but it allows us to distinguish a third sense of acceptance, which is (3) the intentional act of informing somebody about one’s acceptance of p in the sense of (1). In contrast to (2), (3) demands an addressee: informing your colleague that you have accepted the contract is an intentional act, which has to be distinguished from your (nonintentional) nodding in the presence of the colleague.
The fourth act is a sui generis intentional social or speech act of acceptance (4), which is performed, for example, when one accepts the contract by saying “I hereby accept the terms of the contract.” One might wonder whether (3) genuinely differs from (4). The following consideration shows that it does: while (3), in principle, can be addressed to anybody, (4) can be addressed sensibly only to the relevant person in the relevant given communicative situation: while one can inform their colleague about their inner assent to the contract, one cannot accept the contract in front of their colleague (in the fourth sense), unless they are or represent the other party of the contract. Furthermore, (3) can be repeated ad libitum, but (4) can meaningfully and efficaciously be performed only once. Finally, (3) can be made in the present, past or future tense (“[I inform you that] I have accepted” or “I accept” or “I will accept the contract”), but (4) admits only of the present tense.
Is acceptance in at least one of these four senses necessary for promises? Start with the first sense of acceptance. Inner assent, it can be contended, is irrelevant to promises: We have seen that the No Willing dogma declares mere internal willing unable to alter the space of interpersonal normative reasons, that is, to bring about normative entities like directed obligations or claims. But if mere internal willing does not have that power, neither does inner assent insofar as it is a personal (private and internal) act. Interpersonal reasons are just not the kind of entities that are created by individual and internal acts, be they acts of the will or of inner assent.
Since acceptance in the second sense merely is the nonintentional expression of (1), the inner assent’s irrelevance to promises extends to (2) as well. Hence, promises’ capacity to generate relational obligations and rights does not hinge on nonintentional expressions of inner acts. More importantly, it does not hinge on the intentional expression of internal assent either (in the sense of (3)). To see why, consider these two ideas. First, one can inform anybody about their assenting to a promise, but that does not amount to accepting the promise in the sense at stake here. Suppose Laura promises to Sam: “I will call you this afternoon!” and Sam, unbeknownst to Laura, informs Pam that he has assented to Laura’s promise. While one can grant a sense in which Sam, towards Pam, has “accepted” Laura’s promise and while this might have repercussions in the normative relations between Sam and Pam, no normative relation between Laura and Sam has been established by Sam’s act of informing Pam about his assent. Because of that, this act is not relevant to promises. Second, the promisee can inform the promisor of their assent. Admittedly, this act can be confused with the proper act of acceptance. However, its linguistic expression will help disambiguate the communicative situation. If the subject’s utterance is in the past or in the future tense (“I have assented to your promise” or “I will assent to your promise”), chances are that they are merely informing the promisor about their inner act. The same consideration holds if they repeat their utterance several times. In these cases, the promisor is likely to request clarification on what the promisee is doing. But no such request will be raised if the promisee’s utterance is in the present tense and/or if they complement it with relevant adverbs like “hereby.”Footnote 45 For these are linguistic signals that the promisee is performing a genuine act of acceptance.
Is acceptance qua specific intentional speech or social act different from (1)–(3) necessary for promises? Sometimes, this act is indeed required. Imagine Laura telling Sam: “I will call you, only in case you agree,” and Sam replying: “I hereby agree.” Laura is here issuing a conditional promise: its efficaciousness is contingent on an event, which is Sam’s act of acceptance – in the fourth sense illustrated above. For the promissory obligation to get off the ground, Sam has to accept Laura’s promise by performing an intentional act of a specific kind. (In this particular case, the promise is contingent on an act of acceptance, but promises could be made contingent on all sort of events: for example, “if it rains, I promise I’ll bring the dog for a walk.”)
However, not all promises are conditional. Imagine Laura who struggles to keep up with her jogging schedule. To motivate herself, she tells Sam, her flatmate, while he is doing the dishes: “I promise to go for a run at 5 pm.” In uttering those words, Laura creates a promissory obligation that motivates her to go for a run at 5 pm. Now, it is true that Laura’s motivation to make the promise is entirely private (she wants to keep her jogging schedule). However, this doesn’t mean that she has not entered a promissory obligation. In fact, the motivational power Laura intends to elicit precisely derives from its relationality: since Laura cannot renege on the obligation unilaterally, she is bound to honor it. The promissory nature of Laura’s obligation can also be inferred by the fact that Sam acquires a content-identical claim. This claim may well have practical insignificance to Sam, but this is not to say that it does not exist. Under specific circumstances, Sam may decide to enforce it. For instance, imagine that Sam schedules an online meeting for 5 pm, which requires the use of Laura’s room. Around that time, he notices that she hasn’t yet prepared for jogging and demands that she honors her commitment to go for a jog. Sam’s demand carries normative force, meaning that if Laura fails to meet it, Sam is entitled to rebuke her. This normative force wouldn’t exist if Laura had merely informed Sam of her intention to go for a jog at 5 pm. Having established all this, let’s go back to Laura’s promise; while Sam is doing the dishes, she tells him: “I promise to go for a run at 5 pm.” Does Sam need to accept the promise in a case like this? No, he can continue doing the dishes without saying a word.Footnote 46
For at least some promises, acceptance is therefore not necessary: call these promises “unconditional.” It is true that many promises that are explicitly unconditional appear to be tacitly conditional. So, for example, promises like “I will sell you the house at the best price” or “I will take care of your children for the next three days” are not explicitly formulated in conditional terms, but do require acceptance on the promisee’s end to generate obligations and rights. These observations suggest that conditional promises may be more ubiquitous than usually thought. But this does not imply that all promises are conditional. We surmise that the view that all promises require acceptance stems from a natural, but ultimately overbroad generalization from conditional to unconditional promises.Footnote 47
Perhaps acceptance-based accounts of promisesFootnote 48 are motivated by a concern to include a mechanism that safeguards the interest of the promisee, for example, in a case where they perceive the promise to endanger them (e.g., the promise of transferring shares in a company that involve liability). Charles Fried writes in this vein: “I admit unease […] about insisting on acceptance in the case where the promise is clearly communicated and where it would be captious to doubt that the promisee is delighted the promise.” But he then continues: “Since […] any putative benefit may in fact be unwanted by a particular (putative) promisee, there must at least be the option to refuse or reject not just the benefit but the promise of the benefit.”Footnote 49 We think that the concern is legitimate, but misplaced. For the promisee can avail themself of a mechanism to protect their interest unrelated to acceptance. In fact, the promisee has the power to release: in waiving their claims, they, by the same token, release the promisor of their obligation and make the promise null and void. (As we will see, one of the criticisms we raise in the next section against Gilbert’s theory is that it disavows this power.)
Our interim conclusion is that promising as such does not require acceptance. To dismiss this conclusion, defenders of an acceptance-based account of promises should dismiss the notion of unconditional promise as inconsistent and empty. However, this notion does not involve any internal contradiction and, hence, is not inconsistent. Also, many of our promises do appear to be unconditional.
11.5 Second Objection: The Authors of Promises
We ordinarily think of promises as actions of the promisor. However, the joint commitment account misidentifies the authors of the promises by equating the promisor’s singular act of promising with actions performed by promisor and promisee: “for one person to make a promise to another is for them jointly to commit…”Footnote 50 It is true that, on Gilbert’s theory, there is more to promises than that (e.g., appropriate and explicit expressions on the part of promisor and promisee must have occurred). While these details are important to Gilbert’s general account,Footnote 51 our focus in this section will be restricted to the idea that what appears to be an act of an individual (the promisor’s promising) directed at another (the promisee) turns out to be a plurality of acts of those individuals (the promisor’s and promisee’s committing). This amounts to a strongly revisionary account of the authors of promises.
Note, first, that our point is not that the promisor/promisee asymmetry gets lost on the joint commitment account. It does not: the promisor – not the promisee – figures as the author of the decided action in the content of the decision to which the promisor and the promisee commit. Our point rather is that what distinguishes the promisor from the promisee is not just that the promise bears on the promisor’s action. The distinction between the promisor and the promisee is first and foremost content-independent: the promisor is not only the author of the promised action, he also is the author of the promise (or, as Reinach calls him, the “originator”Footnote 52 of the promise). Gilbert’s account fails to capture that aspect of promises.
In answer, Gilbert might simply challenge the notion that promises, as we submitted, are, in fact, ordinarily conceived of as acts of the promisor and not as acts of the promisor and the promisee.Footnote 53 However, the following considerations suggest that that is very much the case indeed:
1. We tend to ascribe the authorship of promises to the promisor alone:
a. Suppose that, after Laura promised Sam to call him, Jim asks Sam: “Did you commit together with Laura to the decision that she will call you?” Sam is likely to answer in the negative: “No – this is Laura’s commitment!” If Laura were asked the same question, a similar answer may be expected – perhaps accompanied by an element of remonstration: “No, what I promise is entirely up to me, why should have I consulted with Sam in advance on what to promise to him?”.
b. Imagine an evil demon announcing that he will kill the first person who makes a promise after t. In a heroic sacrificial act, Sam shouts “I promise never to forget you Laura!”. Should the demon kill them both?
c. A promisor can plan to make a promise, without any uncertainty being caused by the possible lack of cooperation of the promisee. One’s promises are easy to plan, in contrast to agreements and joints actions.
2. The contrast between individual and collective promises (“I promise” vs. “we promise”) is, on the face of it, content-independent:Footnote 54 it is simply the contrast between the promise made by a single subject and the promise made by a plurality of subjects. The joint commitment account has to reject this. On the joint commitment account, the difference cannot depend on the number of subjects performing the act (one versus many). Rather, what distinguishes individual from collective promises pertains to their content: individual promises are joint commitments bearing on individual actions, while collective promises are joint commitments bearing on collective actions (more on the content of promises in the next section).
So, the ways in which we conceive of, plan, and evaluate promises converge in showing that promises are acts of the promisor. The joint commitment account is, as mentioned above, robustly revisionary in that respect. Couldn’t Gilbert bite that bullet? We doubt it. First, this revision concerns such a core feature of promises that one may wonder whether an account denying that promises are acts of the promisor can still legitimately claim to be about promises. Second, the revision entails four further problematic consequences to which we now turn.
(i) Too many obligations for the promisee. Let us start by formulating a worry concerning the standard obligation of the promisor, that is, the “performance obligation” to act as promised, which is at stake in the Inevitability Point. The worry is this: if X and Y jointly commit to endorse the decision that X will φ, then both X and Y should have an obligation to that effect. However, this is not so in the case of promises.
Gilbert denies that X and Y’s joint commitment entails that performance obligations accrue to both, X and Y: “[…] the only performance obligations associated with a promise X makes to Y are those of X […].”Footnote 55 But if the promisee incurs no performance obligation, then we confess to lose grip on the very idea that, when X promises Y to φ, X and Y are jointly committed to endorse the decision that X will φ. That is, we doubt that there is any ordinary notion of joint commitment such that X and Y are jointly committed to an action of X, without Y incurring any (performance) obligation as a result.Footnote 56 It just doesn’t seem that Y has committed to anything in such a case.
However, it is important to note that, in denying that X and Y’s joint commitment entails that performance obligations accrue to both X and Y, Gilbert is not denying that other, “ancillary” obligations accrue to the promisee. She writes: “the promisor’s performance obligation is not the only obligation arising, inevitably, in the context of a promise.” What are these obligations? “A promisee’s ancillary obligation,” she continues, “is at a minimum an obligation to his promisor not to act in ways that prevent his promisor from fulfilling the promise.”Footnote 57
Does the existence of ancillary obligations deflate our criticism? Let us reply by highlighting that we do not dispute the existence of such ancillary obligations. However, we resist the idea that they are generated by the promise. Instead, we suggest that these obligations are generated by a general moral principle. While the exact formulation of this principle is the topic for another paper, we can state it in a loose manner as follows: one ought not to thwart the realization of somebody else’s intention (barring special circumstances: e.g., if the intention carries a morally heinous content). Since honest promises presuppose the promisor’s intention to perform the promised action, the promisee (and, actually, given the moral nature of the principle at stake: anybody else) ought not thwart the realization of the promisor’s intention (barring special circumstances). So, if Laura promises Sam, in the presence of Robert, that she will meet Sam at the pub at 5 pm, then not only Sam but also Robert should refrain from actions that would hinder Laura from fulfilling her promise.
(ii) Loss of power of release for the promisee. A second problematic consequence of the joint commitment account pertains to the rescission of a promise. Gilbert claims that, since not only the promisor, but also the promisee, places himself under an obligation when a promise is performed, then the promisee cannot, on the face of it, unilaterally rescind the promise. This is in contrast with the widely accepted idea that the promisee has a “power of release.”Footnote 58 Gilbert offers two replies to alleviate the tension with this widely endorsed idea.
Her first reply is to question the systematic existence of such a power of release. Gilbert suggests that we are under the impression that such a power exists because, in our analyses of promises, we selectively focus on promises that the promisor has no personal desire to perform. These are cases in which the promise has been solicited by the promisee. While looking at this specific class of promises, it may sound plausible that the promisee has a power to release, given that the promisor has no interest in the promise. However, Gilbert claims that if the promisor does have the desire to promise, then the promisor will be justified in resisting the promisee’s attempt to waive their right unilaterally (thereby making the promise null and void). This is the example Gilbert makes to illustrate the point:
[…] suppose Joe promises to return Jane’s book on Tuesday. Jane calls him to say that it is not that important for her to have the book, so he may keep it. He might then say ‘No, I promised to return the book on Tuesday and that’s what I’ll do.’ It is at best not clear that Jane is [in] a position to say ‘But the promise is over, I just said so’.Footnote 59
We disagree: it seems to us that Jane is very much in a position to do so. We suspect that confusion is at play here between Jane’s rescinding the promise and Jane’s forbidding Joe from returning the book. Of course, Jane is in no position to issue such an interdiction. While Jane’s rescinding of the promise destroys Joe’s obligation to return the book, his permission to do so remains intact.
If you are nonetheless under the impression that Jane is in a position to forbid Joe to return the book, then perhaps, Reinach argues,Footnote 60 you conceived of Joe’s “promise” as a promise together with some nonpromissory act. For instance, it might be that by uttering the word “I promise to return your book on Tuesday,” Joe performed not one, but two acts: a promise to return the book and a request to Jane that she accept that he will return the book on Tuesday. Of course, if Jane accedes to the request, she takes on an obligation. This is the obligation to accept that Joe returns the book, and it is one that she cannot revoke unilaterally. While Jane retains the power to waive the claim deriving from Joe’s promise, she cannot exercise that power, given the obligation she entered by accepting Joe’s request. In this scenario, Jane therefore is under an obligation that she cannot rescind, but this is not, as the joint commitment account would have it, because the promisee is tied by the promise that was made to her, but because she is tied by her having accepted the concomitant request of the promisor.
Gilbert’s second reply is to point out that should one insist on the promisee’s power of release, one could modify the joint account so as to accommodate it in the following way: “a promise is a joint decision that one party, ‘the promisor,’ is to do something – a joint decision entered into by an appropriate explicit process – with which is associated the understanding that it stands at the pleasure of the other party – ‘the promisee’.”Footnote 61 Our reply is that while promisor and promisee may have that understanding and may even render it explicit in the process of making the promise, a great many promises are not associated with that understanding simply because the parties do not possess it. And yet, even in those promises, we would maintain that the power of release accrues to the promisee. So, for example, Laura promises Sam that she will call him at 5 pm. Sam (and, for what it’s worth, Laura too) might not be aware that Sam can release Laura (perhaps they have never reflected on these matters). Yet Sam does possess that power (even though, due to his ignorance on the matter, he will not exercise it). If that is correct, it goes to show that the power of release does not depend on such an understanding.
(iii) Too much responsibility for the promisee. Intuitively, the responsibility for a promise accrues to the promisor in a way that does not accrue to the promisee. Thus, in the case of immoral and, especially, unconditional promises, the promisor is blameworthy in a way the promisee is not. Likewise, the promisee does not get any credit for the courageous or generous promises made by the promisor. Since on the joint commitment account both the promisor and the promisee perform the promise together, such asymmetries in responsibility ascription run the risk of getting lost.
Gilbert may reply by relying on the fact that her account does not erase the difference between the promisor and the promisee but traces it back to the content of the joint commitment: the promisor, to recall, is the one whose action figures in the joint commitment. Thus, on the joint commitment account, it may be argued that the promisor incurs the responsibility of the promised action because that action is hers. By extension, if the promised action is immoral, then the promisor – not the promisee – is blameworthy.
However, there are two reasons why such a view fails to capture the relevant asymmetry in responsibility. First, given that both the promisor and the promisee are jointly committed to the decision that the promisor will perform the immoral action, the promisee, on the joint commitment account, should still incur some responsibility for that blameworthy action, should it be performed. But if Sam makes the unconditional promise to Laura to kill a cat for fun, how is Laura even partly responsible if Sam delivers on his promise?Footnote 62
Second, one might be blameworthy (or praiseworthy) for a promise without this deriving from the blameworthiness (or praiseworthiness) of the promised action. Suppose it is forbidden to make promises on Mondays. If Sam nevertheless unconditionally promised to Laura on Monday, Laura does not incur any responsibility for violating the interdiction. However, in such a case the asymmetry in blameworthiness cannot be traced back to the blameworthiness of the promised action. Indeed, the promised action may well not be blameworthy. In such a case, if Sam is blameworthy and Laura is not, this cannot be because they jointly commit a blameworthy action of Sam. In short, differences in blameworthiness of promises cannot always be derived from differences in blameworthiness of promissory contents.
(iv) Second-order promises and Euthyphro. Consider this second order promise: Sam promises Laura that he will promise to call her. On the joint commitment account, such a second-order promise amounts to Sam and Laura jointly committing to the decision that Sam will promise to call Laura, which in turn amounts to Sam and Laura jointly committing to the decision that Sam and Laura will jointly commit to the decision that Sam calls Laura. Let us focus on the wide scope, second-order promise. That promise is, ex hypothesis, a promise made by Sam. On the joint commitment account, this should mean that the promise bears on an action by Sam. However, the joint commitment account entails that this is not the case: the content of that second-order joint commitment is an action of Sam and Laura – namely a first-order joint commitment. This highlights that the joint commitment account is in no position to maintain that, with respect to the second-order promise, Sam is the promisor.
The natural reply on behalf of the joint commitment account is that the first-order joint commitment (of Sam and Laura to the decision that Sam will call Laura) is a promise by Sam, because it bears on an action by Sam (calling Laura). If so, the second-order joint commitment bears on an action by Sam – a first-order promise – so that it is itself, in turn, a second-order promise by Sam.
This reply, we submit, brings to the fore how wrong-side-up it is to identify the promisor via the content of the promise.Footnote 63 To determine whether a second-order joint commitment of Sam and Laura corresponds to a promise by Sam, by Laura, or is not a promise, we must look into the content of that second-order order commitment. Since that is another joint commitment, we have to look further and check the content of that first-order commitment. This puts the cart before the horse. We need not know what is promised to determine who has promised. Gilbert is certainly right that our promises necessarily bear on actions of ours. But they are not our promises because they bear on actions of ours. They bear on actions of ours because they are our promises.
For all these reasons we conclude that authorship of promises should not be attributed to both the promisor and the promisee, as entailed by the joint commitment account. We now turn to our third objection to the joint commitment account of promises.
11.6 Third Objection: The Contents of Promises
In this section we argue that the joint commitment account of promises mischaracterizes the contents of promises by equating them with decisions to act (or endorsement of action plans) and not with actions tout court. Remember Gilbert’s account:
Joint commitment account: X has made a promise to Y if and only if (1) X and Y are jointly committed to endorse as a body a particular plan of action P, and (2) X and Y created this joint commitment by virtue of appropriate, explicit expressions on the part of each, in conditions of common knowledge, and (3) P specifies an action for X.Footnote 64
On this view, “Laura promised to Sam that she will call him” ought to be paraphrased into “Laura and Sam jointly committed to endorse the plan [or ‘decide’] that Laura calls Sam.”Footnote 65 However, what we typically promise is neither to decide to act nor to endorse an action, but to act (sometimes, Reinach argues, the promisor promises results rather than actions – but these results still are results of the promisor’s actionsFootnote 66). All in all, Gilbert’s analysans is more complicated than the analysandum in two respects. First, promises – which prima facie are individual acts – are analyzed in terms of a plurality of acts. Second, promises – which prima facie have a first-order content directed at the action of the promisor – are analyzed in terms of committal acts of the will directed at a joint decision to act (or at the joint endorsement of some action plan). A first order individual act is analyzed in terms of a plurality of second order acts.
In principle, one could maintain that promises are in fact more complex than they seem to be by arguing that this complexity is a cost worth paying – for instance, because joint commitments allow analysis of a wide variety of other phenomena, such as agreements. However, we submit that such gains are overridden by substantial costs which, all things considered, should advise us against endorsing the joint commitment account of promises.
To begin with, there is a cost in intuitive simplicity: promises are something else than what they appear to be. Preferring an elaborate account of promises to our intuitive grasp of them stands in tension with Gilbert’s laudable attempt to stick to appearances in other places. For instance, elsewhere she argues against the view that agreements are exchanges of promises by raising the worry that an “agreement, for one, does not look like a pair of promises, mutual, exchanged or whatever.”Footnote 67 We agree, but by parity of reasoning, one should also note that promising does not look like jointly committing to a decision to act.
Furthermore, although one chief aim of the joint commitment account is to explain the Inevitability Point (according to which if X promises to φ, then X is, without exception, under the pro tanto obligation to φ), equating promises to joint commitments to a decision to act might be incompatible with that point. To see that, suppose that Laura promises to call Sam. If Laura and Sam are jointly committed as a body to the decision that Sam calls Laura, then it seems that Laura now has an obligation to espouse as a body the decision that Laura calls Sam. If that is the case, Laura will have promised to call Sam without ever having been under the obligation to call Sam (contra the Inevitability Point).
One could object to our reconstruction and note that, in this scenario, Sam and Laura are not committed to decide or endorse as a body the plan that Laura will call Sam, rather they have jointly decided that.Footnote 68 Accordingly, neither of them has an obligation to decide anything (unless it is a decision to accord with the joint decision). And since the joint decision has been made, it is incumbent upon Laura to make the call, if she is to accord with the decision they have made. Hence, the theory preserves the Inevitability Point. We welcome the objection because it enables us to specify that our criticism rests on two general assumptions about commitments as such. Below we provide reasons for endorsing these assumptions. Our criticism, therefore, is conditional: if those assumptions are misplaced, it fails.
Our first assumption concerns a general point about commitments, already highlighted in Section 11.4: a commitment (personal or joint) to φ is a sufficient reason for φ-ing (e.g., acting or forming a certain attitude). This goes to show that, at the moment in which the joint commitment has been formed, φ has not yet happened, rather the agents are motivated to make it happen. Note that the creation of the joint commitment might well lead to the immediate realization of its content. Perhaps, this is how joint commitments lead to the formation of, especially, psychological attitudes (in contrast to actions). But our assumption concerns the motivational or normative nature of the relation between the joint commitment and its content, not its temporal determination. It is at least in principle possible for the (personal or joint) committer to disregard the commitment: in this case, the commitment does not necessitate the committer to φ (regardless of the temporal relation that binds the commitment and φ in the case where the committer conducts themselves according to their commitment).
The second assumption relates to the idea, again discussed in Section 11.4, that a joint commitment cannot be unilaterally rescinded because it generates directed obligations and claims on X and Y. As Gilbert writes: “If Anne and Ben are jointly committed to doing something as a body, each owes the other appropriate actions by virtue of their joint commitment.”Footnote 69 It stands to reason that these appropriate actions must be in accordance with the joint commitment. Hence, our second assumption here is that the obligations inherit, as it were, the content of the joint commitment. So, e.g., if Anne and Ben have jointly committed to φ, where φ is to climb a mountain together, then each of them has the obligation against the other to climb the mountain (the same, of course, applies to cases where φ is a psychological and not an agentive predicate).
Now, according to Gilbert’s account, Laura has made a promise to Sam to call him if, among other conditions, Laura and Sam are jointly committed to endorse as a body a particular plan of action φ. Based on the first assumption, it seems to follow that the content of the joint commitment is to endorse as a body the particular plan of Laura’s calling Sam. Hence, Laura and Sam have a sufficient reason to endorse as a body that particular plan of action. But this means that the agents are motivated to endorse that plan, which has not yet happened at the moment when they have formed the commitment.
Further, the joint commitment cannot be unilaterally rescinded because Laura and Sam have acquired directed obligations. What is the content of the obligation accrued to the promisor, and in our example, to Laura? Based on our second assumption, this is the same content of the joint commitment. In other words, this is an obligation Laura has against Sam to endorse as a body the particular plan of calling Sam.
If our assumptions are on the right track, then Laura, in promising Sam to call him, acquires the obligation to jointly endorse the plan to call him – she does not acquire the obligation to call him. But then, as we highlight above, this infringes upon the Inevitability Point. Our two assumptions seem to consistently square with the two ideas about commitments and directed obligations presented in Section 11.4. Yet nothing in what we have argued excludes the possibility that that the Joint Commitment Account of Promises can do without the two assumptions. Though doing so, we presume, will come at the cost of revising other principles of the general theory of joint commitments. We won’t explore this possibility, but ask further whether Gilbert’s theory of joint commitments couldn’t be amended (or interpreted) in another way so as to obviate the mischaracterization of the promises’ contents and to salvage the general idea that promises are joint commitments?
Consider the scenario in which a child and their parents, after a disastrous parents–teacher meeting, enter the joint commitment that the child will spend more time doing his homework. This seems to be a case of joint commitment the content of which is the action of only one of the commitment’s parties. Based on this idea, Gilbert’s theory of promises could be revised by now claiming that promises are joint commitments whose content is the promisor’s decision only (and not a joint decision of promisor and promisee): for example, if Laura promises to call Sam, then Laura and Sam jointly commit to Laura’s decision that she calls Sam. The revised version of the account secures the Inevitability Point (Laura’s promise obligates Laura to the decision of calling Sam) and correctly attributes a first-order content to promises, while maintaining that promises are joint commitments.
Unfortunately, this amendment appears to have all the advantages of theft over honest toil (which is why, we presume, Gilbert nowhere hints at this possibility). For one can only commit to what is up to oneself or to what is (on some salient interpretation) under one’s control: actions or attitudes of another are not something one can commit to.Footnote 70 Accordingly, the subject of the psychological predicate in the commitment’s content can only be the subject of that very commitment and this holds for both singular and joint commitments. Our joint commitment is a commitment of ours that has an action or an attitude of ours as its content – something that is up to us or stands under our joint control.
If that is correct, then alleged cases of joint commitments which have the action of a committer as their content are not genuinely joint. Going back to the previous example, the putative case of joint commitment that the parents and the child have turns out to be a combination of two different commitments: the child’s commitment to spend more time doing homework and the parents’ commitment that they will do their best to facilitate the child doing their homework. These two commitments have different contents and therefore do not qualify as one joint commitment.
Because it imposes an acceptance-condition on all promises and because it mischaracterizes the author and content of promises, we conclude that the joint commitment account of promises must be rejected. Of course, this result is doomed to reignite the original question: How should one then explain the Inevitability Point? If promissory obligations and claims are not grounded in joint commitments, then what grounds them? While we won’t be able to fully answer these questions in this paper, the next section advances a suggestion on how progress could be made in these matters.
11.7 Gilbert, Reinach, and a Fourth Dogma about Promises
A general consideration shall conclude our assessment of the joint commitment account of promises: in addition to the three dogmas about promises discussed in Section 11.3, we suggest the existence of a fourth dogma. In a nutshell, this dogma assumes that the fact that promises generate claims and obligations calls for a substantive explanation. In order to better clarify what we mean by this “fourth dogma,” it might be helpful to come back to Reinach’s account of promises.
As we have seen, Reinach insists that all promises, including immoral ones, generate pro tanto obligations – this is in accordance with Gilbert’s Inevitability Point (strong reading) as well as with Gilbert’s rejection of the Immoral Promises Dogma. Furthermore, Reinach maintains that promissory claims and obligations are not moral, which is in accordance with Gilbert’s rejection of the Moral Requirement Dogma. Also, Reinach argues that promises are speech acts that bring about obligations – and this, again, is in accordance with Gilbert’s rejection of the No Willing dogma. Finally, Reinach holds that promissory claims and obligations are relational or directed – in accordance with Gilbert’s Directed Obligation. Thus, Reinach and Gilbert independently arrive at the same five key desiderata for an account of promises.Footnote 71
While one can only be struck by these many affinities, there is one fundamental divergence between the two accounts. Gilbert rejects – correctly, we believe, with Reinach – substantive explanations of the binding character of promises that equate promises to expectation triggers, solicitations of trust, useful social practices, etc., or that appeal to moral constraints. However, she concurs with these accounts of promises in that she accepts that some substantive explanation has to be given as to why promises generate obligations and claims. In fact, her main contribution to the debate is to propose a new explanation that, by accounting for promises in terms of joint commitments, is alternative to those previously theorized.
Reinach, on his part, rejects all substantive explanations of the binding character of promises: promises – so his claim goes – generate obligations and claims in virtue of their very nature. On his view, this is a truth that does not need to be grounded in any other: promises are what they are and not anything else. More precisely, promises are generators of obligations and claims. Obviously, this does not mean that nothing else informative can be said about promises: Reinach agrees that we still need to clarify what kind of event a promise is, what kinds of obligations and claims promises generate, whether promises need to be heard and/or accepted in order to have force, and more. But looking for some explanation of why promises generate obligations and claims is, in his view, a pointless endeavor. It is pointless because promising is a primitive kind of action and cannot be reduced to other, more primitive kinds of action.
Does Reinach’s position matter in this context? We submit that it does – for two main reasons. First, it matters because, if Reinach is right, then the view that the Inevitability Point demands a substantive explanation may be a fourth dogma about promises (a dogma to which even Gilbert has fallen prey). Second, it also matters because, if it can be shown that abiding by the fourth dogma generally dooms an account to failure, then the question of whether Reinach is right is an urgent one. However, tackling the question of whether – and/or to what extent – Reinach is right can only be a topic for future research.
11.8 Acknowledgments
This chapter underwent a lengthy development process and benefited from feedback and discussions with numerous colleagues. We are grateful to John Michael and Donnchadh O’Conaill for their comments on previous drafts and to Jed Lewinsohn for discussing the acceptance of promises with us. We presented the chapter detail at events in Cork, Frankfurt, Lugano, Oxford, and Warwick, where we received very valuable feedback from the audience. Finally, we would like to express our deepest gratitude to Margaret Gilbert for her generous feedback on our chapter, which has greatly contributed to refining our arguments, although we suspect she remains unpersuaded.
The aim of this essay is to analyze the basic concepts that underlie contract formation. I start from one axiom about the nature of contracts. Contracts, that is, the set of deontic relations (i.e., rights, obligations, etc.) that constitute a contract, are necessarily a product of both parties’ assents. Thus, contracts presuppose some kind of agreement: We simply cannot acquire a contractual right or obligation against or towards another person unless we and that person in some form agree to us having such a right or obligation. Accordingly, this axiom (the ‘Necessity of Agreement Axiom’ or simply ‘NOA’) entails that one cannot unilaterally create or assume a contractual right or obligation, namely create or assume a contractual right or obligation against or towards another person without the assent of one’s obligor or obligee. Contractual rights are, necessarily, those that are formed, created or brought about by agreement.
I will explore NOA’s implications for our understanding of contract formation. I maintain that if we adopt NOA, there are at least two different ways through which two persons can enter into a contract, that is, two mechanisms by which one may form contractual agreements. One is well known to anyone familiar with any modern system of positive contract law: ‘offer and acceptance’. The other, interestingly neglected by most contract lawyers and theorists, is what I call ‘contractual subscription’. I develop the concept of contractual subscription, and then proceed to discuss the notions of offer and acceptance. Drawing on Reinach’s idea of a ‘social act’, I provide an account of ‘juridical acts’.Footnote 1 Juridical acts, I argue, are a type of social act, and contractual offers are a kind of juridical act. Finally, I analyze the role of another important notion in contract formation, that of a ‘promise’.
Many writers have argued that contractual relations are necessarily constituted by promises. Here I contend that promises are not only not necessary to enter into a contract but that, in their elementary form at least, promises are never sufficient to form a contract. I distinguish between what I call a ‘basic promise’ and a ‘promissory offer’. Developing a Reinachian insight, and against other philosophers and jurists, I argue that promises in their basic form produce their deontic effects immediately once they’re apprehended or known by the promisee. They thus bind without the promisee’s assent mediating. Therefore, if we remain committed to NOA and basic promises can create rights without the promisee’s agreement intervening, these rights cannot be contractual rights. We shall see that promissory offers (and offers more generally) are not essential to the process of contract formation. But only promises that are promissory offers and not basic promises can begin the process of contract formation.
This chapter is about the basic theoretical architecture of contract formation, and thus proceeds at a relatively high level of abstraction. It should, however, shed light on some traditional topics in contract law doctrine, such as the discussion about the structure of so-called ‘unilateral’ contracts, the problem of the moment of contract formation, and the status of the power to revoke an offer. Furthermore, I do not explore the related yet largely independent issue of the morality of contract formation, namely the moral principles that should (and typically do) inform our views about contract formation. I hope, however, that the views I defend about the conceptual structure of contract formation will clear up the territory for new forms of moral or normative inquiry in the domain of contract law. Our examination of the conceptual bases of contract formation will motivate normative questions such as: is there any value that requires contracts to be formed only by offer and acceptance and not by what I refer to as contractual subscription? Are we morally better off endorsing or rejecting NOA? What is the moral significance of the distinction between basic promises and promissory offers? I briefly elaborate on only one of these questions (Section 12.4), but I do hope that the account I offer of the rich landscape of concepts that govern contract formation will set up a framework for the careful study of these and other questions in the morality of contract. Let’s begin by exploring NOA.
12.1 The Necessity of Agreement Axiom
The NOA axiom holds that a contract binds only if all the contracting parties agree or give their mutual assent.Footnote 2 One may identify at least two versions of NOA by distinguishing different forms of ontological dependence of contractual rights upon the parties’ assents.
One of them, which we may call ‘modal-dependence’, holds that contractual rights’ existence or bindingness is simply conditional upon the parties’ mutual assent, that is, that their mutual assent is necessary for the existence or bindingness of their contractual rights. This view, however, leaves open the question of whether the parties’ mutual assent is what ultimately grounds their contractual rights, that is, whether such rights ultimately obtain because of or in virtue of the parties’ mutual assent. For instance, according to the modal-dependence version of NOA, contractual rights’ ground may be a legislative act which in turn makes the parties’ mutual assent an enabling necessary condition for the bindingness of such rights. If this is the case, contractual rights’ bindingness is conditional upon the parties’ assents, yet they are grounded in an act of legislation (i.e., in a law that makes the parties’ mutual assent necessary for contract formation). By contrast, according to a version which we may call ‘ground-dependence’, all contractual rights necessarily obtain because of or in virtue of the parties’ mutual assent: a right is contractual in kind only if it is grounded in, and not merely modally dependent upon, the parties’ mutual assent. Later I further elaborate on this distinction and contend that these two different ways of understanding NOA have important implications for our views about the structure of contract formation. For the moment, however, we should stress that according to both the ground-dependence and modal-dependence versions of NOA, a person cannot hold a contractual right against another unless both parties have given their assent to the creation or bindingness of such right.Footnote 3 Therefore, under either of these versions, NOA entails that persons simply cannot bring about a binding contractual right unilaterally, that is, without their contracting party’s assent mediating.Footnote 4
Though widely accepted, I do not think NOA is what we may call a ‘commonsense truth’ about the nature of contracts, that is, an undeniable fact about their nature that we can know by simple observation of the pre-theoretical phenomenology of contracting. Indeed, we will see that some legal systems appear to consider what below I call basic promises (which are unilaterally binding) as sufficient grounds for legal liability, and contract theorists have offered serious arguments in favor of their contractual character. Thus, if NOA is not a commonsense truth about contracts, it requires justification: a theory of contract must make the case for (or against) the agreement-dependency of contractual rights. In this essay, I will assume the soundness of NOA and focus primarily on analyzing some of its implications for our understanding of the structure of contract formation. However, at the end of Section 12.4 I sketch the beginnings of a thesis regarding NOA’s justification.
Once we endorse NOA, we can think of different possible mechanisms of contract formation, that is, different ways through which persons can reach a contractual agreement. Let’s explore two of these contract formation mechanisms.
12.2 Contract Formation and Contract-Enabling Norms
We can think of at least two ways in which persons can give their mutual assent to a contractual relation. First, they can form a contractual agreement through the process standardly known as ‘offer and acceptance’. Second, they can reach a contractual agreement by assenting to a set of contractual terms (i.e., rights, obligations, etc.) that are not fixed by a contractual offer in the first place. In this case, they form their contract through what I call ‘contractual subscription’.Footnote 5 Though some recognize the limits of the offer and acceptance model of contract formation,Footnote 6 contract law scholars have neglected the task of providing a theoretical analysis of other possible ways of reaching contractual agreements.Footnote 7 Consider the case of contractual subscription.
If A and B are contracting parties to a contract C, they formed such contract through contractual subscription and not offer and acceptance if: 1) they both agreed to being subject to the terms of C (i.e., to the rights and obligations C constitutes) and 2) the terms of C were not fixed, in the way I specify below, by an offer from A or B. Though below I will offer another example, we may first use the case of entering into a marriage contract as a way of illustrating contractual subscription.
Marital relations entail a cluster of legal obligations and rights that spouses owe towards, and have against, each other. Spouses have no or little power to determine the content of many of these obligations and rights. Yet in modern societies at least, legal marital rights and obligations are contractual in the sense we identified above: their bindingness is conditional upon the involved parties’ assents. However, even if marital rights and obligations are in this sense contractual, it would be mistaken to hold that spousal assent must be preceded by a process of offer and acceptance. It is not that it is merely odd or counterintuitive to portray spouses as making reciprocal offers and acceptances when manifesting their spousal assent, the point is that we need not think of their assent to form a marriage contract as mediated or constituted by the process of offer and acceptance. To see why, we must abstract out of the example of marriage for a moment.
Consider the following thesis: The formation of a contractual agreement necessarily presupposes an antecedent ‘legal norm’Footnote 8 which fixes the content of certain rights and obligations and makes their bindingness conditional upon the parties’ mutual assent. We may call this type of norm a ‘contract-enabling norm’. Contract-enabling norms have roughly the following structure: they make it the case that if A and B assent to being subject to terms C (i.e., rights and obligations of content C), then they are thereby bound by C. In themselves, contract-enabling norms do not constitute contractual relations (i.e., contractual obligations or rights), yet they are, according to this thesis, necessary to enable the creation of contractual relations by way of establishing conditional rights and obligations whose bindingness holds upon two persons’ assents. Thus, there must be conditional rights or obligations in the first place for even the possibility of contractual assent. This is because, according to this view, assenting or agreeing to a contract is precisely fulfilling the condition stated by a norm which fixes a right or obligation which would bind the parties if they give their assent.
I think a thesis along these lines informs the widespread view that contracts must be formed by the two-step process of offer followed by acceptance. Offers, according to this view, are precisely contract-enabling norms, which acceptances turn into fully fledged, binding contractual relations. Therefore, the view goes, since contract-enabling norms are necessary for contract formation, offers are of the essence of contract formation too. One may of course dispute this way of understanding the nature of contractual agreements and hold that persons can reach contractual agreements, that would bring about contractual rights, without anything like a contract-enabling norm mediating. But let’s assume, arguendo, that the thesis is sound, and thus that contractual agreements, which constitute contractual relations, necessarily presuppose the existence of contract-enabling norms in the first place. The point I wish to stress here is that there are different legal facts that may create or constitute contract-enabling norms. Offers, as I argue below, are just one of them. Offers are thus not necessary for contract formation even if contract-enabling norms are. To flesh out this idea, let’s go back to the case of marriage.
For the case of the modern contract of marriage, we can think of a marriage contract-enabling norm as established by civil legislation. For instance, Section 1312 of the BGB (German Civil Code) states that: ‘[o]n the occasion of the marriage, the registrar as a rule is to ask the parties contracting the marriage separately whether they intend to enter into marriage with each other and, after the parties contracting the marriage have answered this question in the affirmative, state that they are now, by operation of law, lawfully joined spouses […]’.Footnote 9 Thus according to this provision, if the spouses declare to the relevant legal official their assent to getting married, they become lawful spouses and thus acquire a series of reciprocal legal obligations and rights. Among them, for example, they acquire the obligations and rights established by Sections 1353, 1356–59, or 1360 which holds that: ‘[t]he spouses are reciprocally obliged to appropriately maintain the family through their work and with their assets. If the household management is left to one spouse, that spouse as a rule performs their duty of contributing to family maintenance through work by managing the household.’Footnote 10 Section 1312, in conjunction with the other cited and other provisions, constitute a contract-enabling norm: they fix a set of conditional legal obligations and rights that two persons render reciprocally binding by providing their assent in the legally required form. Since in this case legislation already establishes a contract-enabling norm for the contract of marriage, such contract may be formed by the parties by subscription, namely by manifesting their mutual assent in the form required by the legislated contract-enabling norm established in the BGB. No offer is needed in this case.
Marital rights and obligations are not the only type of legal right and obligation that persons may incur by contractual subscription. Another prominent example is the case of some forms of fiduciary duty. For instance, in many legal systems, corporate directors acquire a set of legal obligations, notably duties of loyalty and care towards the shareholders of the corporation which appointed them. These duties and their correlative rights are conditional upon both the appointed directors and shareholders’ assent: a director A is only under a fiduciary duty towards the shareholders of corporation B if both A and the shareholders of B assented, in the legally specified way, to A becoming a director of B.Footnote 11 Thus, if this is the case, directors’ fiduciary duties are contractual in kind: their binding force is conditional upon both parties’ assents. However, as in the case of marriage, to a large extent the content of such duties is fixed by contract-enabling norms created by judicial precedents (typically in common law jurisdictions) and legislation (in civilian jurisdictions). These legislative or judge-made contract-enabling norms establish such fiduciary duties while rendering their binding force conditional upon the reciprocally bound parties’ assents. In this case the parties, corporate shareholders and directors, bind themselves through the mechanism of contractual subscription and not offer and acceptance.Footnote 12
Contractual offers constitute one distinct class of contract-enabling norms. As I contend later in more detail, a contractual offer is a contract-enabling norm created by a contracting party, that is, by one of the at least two persons whose rights will be modified by entering into the contract. In preliminary terms, we may hold that a person A makes a contractual offer to person B if she creates an obligation or right of content C, whose bindingness is conditional upon B giving her assent to C (i.e., to the bindingness of C). Thus, revisiting the definition provided above, we can maintain that a contractual agreement is formed by contractual subscription if both parties have assented to being subject to the terms fixed in conditional form by a contract-enabling norm different from an offer (i.e., a contract-enabling norm not created by any of the involved contracting parties). Conversely, as we will see later in more detail, if the agreement is ultimately formed by the assent of one of the parties to the conditional obligations and rights fixed by a contract-enabling norm created by the other contracting party, the contractual agreement is formed by the process of offer and acceptance. Thus, contractual agreements need not be preceded by an offer, which is just one type of contract-enabling norm. As we saw in the case of marriage and corporate directors’ fiduciary duties, legislative enactments and judicial precedents can also constitute contract-enabling norms. Furthermore, not only legislation, judicial precedents and offers are capable of constituting contract-enabling norms. We should remain open to the idea that other legal norm-creating facts such as, in certain circumstances, customs or social practices may also constitute contract-enabling norms.
I have mentioned different possible sources of contract-enabling norms (i.e., legislation, judicial precedents, offers and, arguably, customs), which in turn lead to at least two different possible mechanisms of contractual agreement formation, namely offer and acceptance, and contractual subscription. Some may dispute this claim by arguing that in certain jurisdictions the law recognizes only offers and not legislation, judicial precedents or customs as facts that may create contract-enabling norms, and thus that in such legal systems contractual agreements can only be formed through offers followed by acceptances and not by contractual subscription. Others, perhaps invoking the value of contractual freedom, may contend that the moral value of contract law requires that only offers, which are contract-enabling norms created by the parties, and not those created by legislation, judicial precedents or custom should be capable of producing genuine contractual agreements. I think both views are mistaken. The first one is descriptively flawed, for all the jurisdictions at least I am familiar with comprise legislated, judge-made and, or customary contract-enabling norms. The second one ignores the plurality of values that may justify different aspects of our contractual practice.Footnote 13 Yet in any case, these queries are not our concern here. My aim is to lay out the basic theoretical possibilities of contract formation and not the ways in which such possibilities are instantiated in particular legal systems, or the limits on such possibilities imposed by our preferred theories about the morality of contract.Footnote 14 The key points we should take away for our subsequent discussion are the following: 1) contract-enabling norms, I have assumed, are necessary for persons to reach contractual agreements; 2) offers are just one way of establishing contract-enabling norms; and 3) if a contract-enabling norm is constituted by a legal source (e.g., legislation, judicial precedents or custom) different from an offer, the parties subject to that norm reach their contractual agreement, and thus form a contract, by contractual subscription and not by offer and acceptance.Footnote 15
Let’s now explore in more detail offer and acceptance as a mechanism of contractual agreement formation. Later on, I will move on to analyzing offers’ relationship with another notion that has been central to the development of the law of contracts: promise.
12.3 Offers and Acceptances
We are not concerned here with all kinds of offers. The offers that are relevant in the domain of contract formation are what we may call ‘juridical’ offers. People offer to others their condolences, their advice, etc. Yet these offers, or at least some of them, need not have juridical effects: they need not bring about any modification in the offeror’s or offeree’s rights.Footnote 16 Offers, in our sense, are a type of juridical act, that is, belong to the class of acts that necessarily have an immediate effect in the world of right. Thus, before exploring offers, we must take a slight detour and look at the notion of a juridical act.Footnote 17
12.3.1 Juridical Acts
As I will understand it here, a juridical act is any (intentional) public act which, at least under one true description, produces an immediate effect on our rights. The concept of a juridical act has three important components.Footnote 18
First, juridical acts are ‘intentional’ acts. Unlike what we may call mere juridical facts, juridical acts are constituted by intentional acts, that is, by what persons intentionally do rather than by what simply happens to them or by what they inadvertently do. An example of a juridical fact is, for instance, the fact of being born. The fact of a person being born has some immediate effects in the domain of right, that is, it makes it the case that such person acquires various rights. Yet such rights (i.e., the ones that hold in virtue of being born) are obviously not grounded in any intentional act by such person, for, we may assume, being born is not an intentional act. Juridical acts, by contrast, are made of intentional acts and this, among other things, means that one cannot (genuinely) perform a juridical act (e.g., make a contractual offer) inadvertently, that is, without one knowing that one is doing so.Footnote 19
Second, juridical acts are constituted by (intentional) public acts, that is, they are at least in part made of acts that are not purely mental in kind. I thus cannot perform a juridical act (e.g., make a contractual offer) merely by thinking. In order to perform a juridical act, a person must (intentionally) perform an act which is external in kind (e.g., pronounce some words, sign a document, etc.). The public character of juridical acts derives from a more basic aspect of their nature: they are social in kind. As Reinach puts it, social acts are necessarily other-directed. They are necessarily addressed to others, and, accordingly, they are completed as acts insofar as they can imprint themselves in their addressees’ experience.Footnote 20 Since these acts can only imprint themselves in their addressees’ experience if the addressees are capable of knowing or apprehending these acts in the first place – and, we may assume, we cannot know each other’s thoughts but through external facts – juridical acts, like all social acts, must be at least in part constituted by public facts.Footnote 21
Although all juridical acts are, in Reinach’s sense, social acts, not all social acts are juridical acts in our sense. Acts such as to threaten, warn, insult, congratulate, etc., are also social in kind: they are necessarily addressed to others and are thus completed as acts once they can be apprehended by their addressees.Footnote 22 Yet unlike these social acts, social acts that are juridical acts have immediate effects in the domain of right.Footnote 23 This leads us to the third element of our definition.
The fact that juridical acts have what I call immediate deontic effects means, first of all, that juridical acts (if validly made) necessarily produce certain deontic effects (i.e., a right, obligation, etc.). This is what distinguishes them from other social acts, like congratulating or threatening someone, which can but do not necessarily produce any deontic effect. Furthermore, this feature of juridical acts entails that there is a special kind of constitutive explanatory relationship between a juridical act and its immediate deontic effects: the obtaining of juridical acts’ immediate deontic effects is, in a distinctive way, explained by such juridical acts. Elsewhere I argue that this kind of special explanatory relationship, which I call an essential explanatory dependency, holds because juridical acts metaphysically ground their immediate deontic effects.Footnote 24 For instance, (validly made) promises – which we will see below are a kind of juridical act – essentially explain the obtaining of promissory rights and obligations, and they do so because (validly made) promises ground promissory rights and obligations. This way of understanding the relationship between juridical acts and their immediate deontic effects allows one to draw an important distinction between the immediate deontic effects of a juridical act and those deontic effects whose obtaining is merely conditional upon, yet not grounded in, such acts. For instance, in many legal systems, those who enter sales contracts (which are often made of juridical acts) incur an obligation towards the government to pay sales taxes. However, though its bindingness is conditional upon the making of a sales contract, such an obligation is not grounded in the contract as, we may assume, the seller’s obligation to deliver the goods or the buyer’s obligation to pay the price are. The tax obligation, we may say, modally depends on the existence of the parties’ sale agreement (i.e., the agreement is necessary for the tax obligation to become binding on the buyer and seller), yet it is not grounded in it, namely it is not an immediate deontic effect of the juridical acts that constitute the parties’ contract.Footnote 25
After these remarks on the nature of juridical acts in general, we are ready to turn to offers.
12.3.2 What Is an ‘Offer’?
In broad, preliminary terms, we may characterize an offer as a juridical act in virtue of which a person (i.e., the offeror) creates or modifies a right, or assumes an obligation towards, another person whose assent is a condition for the bindingness of such right or obligation. The ‘offeree’ is the person to whom the offer is addressed and whose rights (in addition to the offeror’s) will be bindingly changed if she gives her assent. The assent given by the offeree to an offer is her ‘acceptance’.
As juridical acts, offers have all the basic properties of such acts: they are intentional public acts which have certain immediate deontic effects. What distinguishes offers from other juridical acts is the peculiar structure of the deontic effects they generate, namely the fact that they create rights whose bindingness is conditional upon the offeree’s assent. Yet before focusing on offers’ distinctive deontic effects, a remark on the (intentional and public) acts that may constitute the juridical act of an offer is needed.
It is, to an important extent, a task for social conventions and the positive law to specify the intentional public acts that may count as capable of producing certain immediate deontic effects, that is, the public acts whose intentional performance by a person constitutes a juridical act. And, of course, such conventional or legal act-specification admits a large range of possible acts counting, by virtue of law or convention, as constituents of juridical acts. Some may be tempted to maintain that contractual offers (and arguably other juridical acts too) are necessarily constituted by a special kind of public act: speech acts.Footnote 26 Yet this view should be rejected. It is certainly possible to make an offer by the offeror saying, using verbal or written words, to the offeree that she thereby grants the offeree a certain right under the condition that she assents. But even if we hold that we always have the power to make offers by using words, it is mistaken to hold that we can only make offers in this way. For instance, in many legal systems (silently) taking a good from a shop’s shelf to the counter counts as an offer, that is, as an intentional public act whereby a person assumes an obligation to pay for the good under the condition that the seller accepts the deal and transfers possession over the good to the purchaser. It would be implausible to hold either that such acts cannot constitute offers, or to understand them as necessarily involving some kind of hidden speech act. Though there is certainly more to be said about the relationship between offers made through speech acts and through other acts,Footnote 27 what distinguishes offers from other juridical acts is primarily the structure of the deontic effects that offers generate. It is this aspect of offers that will occupy us in what follows.
As mentioned before, an offer produces a right (or obligation, etc.) whose binding force is conditional upon its addressee’s (the offeree’s) assent. This broad formulation of the concept of an offer, however, comprises different possible kinds of offer. We may at least distinguish offers by the specific type of deontic entity they generate and by the mode of acceptance they require. Let’s consider the first distinction.
By making an offer, a person may be aiming at (and succeed in) creating different types of conditional rights. For instance, A may offer to B a property right over an object that he owns, O. In this case, we may understand A as creating in B an in rem entitlement or right over O, only in case B assents to the acquisition of such right.Footnote 28 Other offers do not purport to modify our property or in rem relations but only our in personam or obligational relations. For instance, A may assume an obligation to perform an act under the condition that B assents. In this case, A creates a claim-right or in personam right in B that A performs said act, whose bindingness is conditional upon B’s assent. Furthermore, offers can create other types of deontic entities. For instance, A may create in B a power (e.g., a power to act on A’s behalf or ‘power of attorney’), whose bindingness is conditional upon B assenting to the acquisition of such power. Many contemporary legal cultures operate under the idea that contracts only involve a modification in the parties’ obligations or in personam rights, and thus assume that only obligational or in personam offers are distinctively contractual in kind.Footnote 29 I think this view is mistaken. Contracts often modify in rem rights, powers, and other deontic incidents that cannot be reduced to obligations or in personam rights. A conceptual framework for analyzing contracts that confines contracts to the purely obligational domain overlooks the richness of the landscape of possible contractual agreements.
There is, however, a narrower conception of contractual offers that deserves careful scrutiny. According to this view, contractual offers necessarily create one distinctive type of deontic entity in the offeree, namely the legal power of acceptance. The identification of this view of what it is to make an offer leads us to a second form of classifying offers and, as we will see, to two possible ways of understanding the role of acceptance in contract formation.
12.3.3 What Is an ‘Acceptance’?
I have so far characterized offers as juridical acts whereby persons create rights whose bindingness is conditional upon the offeree’s assent. I will call this way of understanding offers the ‘mutual assent’ conception of an offer. Contrast now this conception of an offer with what we may call a ‘power-conferring’ conception of offers. According to the power-conferring conception, for A to make a contractual offer to B it is not sufficient that she merely creates a right or obligation in or towards B whose bindingness is conditional upon B’s assent. This view holds that offers must grant the offeree a legal power to accept A’s offer, that is, the ability to bind the offeror to the terms of her offer by the offeree performing a special kind of juridical act.Footnote 30 The performance of such juridical act is what constitutes the offeree’s acceptance. There are several important differences between these two conceptions of contractual offers.
According to the power-conferring conception, an offer must create in the offeree a legal power to bind the parties to the terms of the offer. A legal power, as I shall understand it here, is the ability to perform a juridical act, namely, as we saw, a public (intentional) act which has certain immediate deontic effects.Footnote 31 An offer is thus a juridical act that confers on its addressee, the offeree, the power to perform another juridical act, namely the act of accepting an offer. By contrast, it is not necessarily a juridical act, but an act of what we may call ‘mere assent’, that is sufficient to constitute an acceptance for the mutual assent conception of an offer.Footnote 32 Again, according to this conception, to make an offer is simply to create a right in the offeree whose bindingness is conditional upon the offeree’s mere assent, assent which may well be a purely mental act. Of course, this view, which entails that one may in principle accept an offer in foro interno, is compatible with the fact that offerors may qualify their offer and make part of the offer’s terms that the offeree’s assent must be, even if not constituted by public acts, manifested or expressed through specifically defined public means (e.g., by sending a letter to the offeror, by signing a document, etc.). Furthermore, the mutual assent conception of offers is compatible with the view that holds that the positive law should use objective standards to ascertain or discover the parties’ assents, and thus that, from the point of view of the positive law, the offeree accepts an offer when it is reasonable for an external observer to believe that she has done so. Yet as a conceptual matter, the mutual assent conception states that, whilst offers in themselves are juridical acts, acceptances need not be so and thus they may well be made of the offeree’s purely internal or private assent.
Different sorts of considerations may militate in favor of the positive law adopting a set of rules about offer and acceptance that come closer to a mutual assent instead of a power-conferring conception, or vice versa, and it’s not my aim to explore these considerations here. We must note, however, that the soundness of one of these conceptions or the other is intimately connected to our understanding of the nature of the Necessity of Agreement axiom, that is, to our views about the type of ontological dependence that holds between contractual rights and the parties’ agreement. Let’s see.
If we adopt what I called the modal-dependence version of NOA, rights and obligations are contractual in kind insofar as their binding force is conditional upon the parties’ assent. Assuming this way of understanding NOA, I have proposed that it is sufficient to form a contractual agreement that there is what I called a contract-enabling norm, that is, a norm which creates a certain deontic effect whose bindingness is conditional upon the parties’ (mere) mutual assents. We saw that offers, if we adopt the mutual assent conception, are a way of creating contract-enabling norms. By contrast, if we adopt what I called the ground-dependence view of NOA, contractual rights and obligations are those that necessarily obtain in virtue of the parties’ agreement. Therefore, if we follow this version of NOA, contractual rights and obligations must be necessarily grounded in, and not merely conditional upon, both parties’ assents. Hence such ‘assents’ must be constituted by juridical acts and not by what I referred to as mere assents; and, accordingly, the only type of legal norm that can make possible the creation of contractual agreements are precisely norms that confer or regulate legal powers; legal powers to contract either created by offers, or created or recognized by other kinds of legal source (e.g., legislation). By contrast, if we adopt the modal-dependence view of NOA, both offers that constitute mere contract-enabling norms and those that confer the legal power of acceptance are capable of creating a contract if acceptance follows.
I believe the modal-dependence view of NOA provides a better theoretical model for analyzing contract formation than the ground-dependence view. Whilst committed to the necessity of mutual assent for contract formation, it gives us a more malleable way of conceiving the relationship between contractual rights and obligations and different sources of law, and between different types of juridical acts (offers qua power-conferring or qua contract-enabling) and the formation of contractual agreements. This more nuanced and flexible understanding of the relationship between contractual agreements and different legal sources and juridical acts may be needed to make sense of the complexities of the modern social practice of contract. My aim here, however, is not to offer a defense of this claim (for this obviously requires separate, careful treatment), but to reveal different possible ways of thinking about the connection between the nature of contractual agreements and the rich array of notions that comprise the structure of contract formation. Let’s now finalize by discussing another important notion in contract formation.
12.4 Promises and Contract Formation
There are of course many ways of modelling the act of making a promise. Yet maintaining the theoretical framework used so far, we may define promising as a juridical act whereby a person (the promisor) assumes an obligation to act or refrain from acting in a given way towards another person (the promisee), who in turn acquires a claim-right to performance, namely an in personam right to performance directed towards the promisor. A great deal of contemporary contract theory, mostly in the Anglo-American context, is devoted to the examination of promising, assuming perhaps that the notion of a promise constitutes the most basic element contracts are made of.Footnote 33 Under this view, promising is necessary for contracting; one simply cannot enter into a contract without making or accepting a promise. There are, however, good reasons for rejecting this view.
From our previous discussion, we may quickly infer that there are at least two ways in which, under the proposed framework, we may form a contractual agreement without making a promise. First, promises’ immediate deontic effects are exclusively obligations and their correlative in personam rights. Yet as we saw, and as I argue elsewhere in detail, some contracts only modify the parties’ in rem or property rights: their immediate deontic effects are only in rem and not in personam in kind.Footnote 34 Thus, if there are contracts of this kind, they cannot be made of promises, for again all promises, even when they constitute contractual offers (as I discuss below), have only in personam effects as their immediate deontic effects. Thus, when made of the parties’ juridical acts, in rem contracts must be made of juridical acts which have in rem effects, and again, promises cannot be such acts.Footnote 35 Second, we saw that if we adopt the modal-dependence version of NOA, the parties may enter into a contractual agreement without any of them performing any juridical act: they may enter into a contractual agreement by what I called contractual subscription. If there is a contract-enabling norm created by legislation, judicial precedent, custom or by any other legal sources different from an offer (like we saw for the case of marriage and corporate directors’ fiduciary duties), the assenting persons enter into a contractual agreement by giving what I called their mere assents (and, if applicable, by complying with the formalities established by the contract-enabling norm). If this is correct, contracting parties may enter into contractual agreements and assume contractual obligations and rights without any of them performing any juridical act, either a promise or of another kind. Yet even if not necessary for contracting, is the making of a promise ever sufficient for contracting?
When formulating this question, we are of course not concerned with whether according to the positive law a promise is sufficient for contracting, because it is well known that in many legal systems the law adds other conditions than promising for contract formation (e.g., consideration, certain formalities, etc.); and furthermore in other legal systems, mostly in the civilian tradition, the notion of a promise is largely absent in the law of contract formation. Our question is theoretical in kind. We are asking whether the juridical act of a promise creates obligations and rights in the form required by NOA, namely whether promissory obligations and rights’ bindingness depends upon the promisor and promisee’ assents. The answer to this question, however, depends on our views about the nature of promising. Since at least the seventeenth century, the question of whether a promise requires acceptance or uptake by the promisee in order to bind has received significant attention. Some theorists have argued that promises are binding only insofar as the promisee assents to the bindingness of the obligation and right proposed by the promisor’s promise. According to this view, promises are essentially a kind of offer, a juridical act whereby the promisor (the offeror) creates in the promisee (the offeree) an obligation and correlative claim-right only if the promisee assents to the bindingness of such obligation and right. By contrast, others hold that promises are not offers, their bindingness is not conditional upon the promisee’s assent. According to this view, promises bind unilaterally, that is, without the promisee’s assent mediating, even if the promisee may, once the promise is formed, waive his right to performance thereby terminating the promisor’s obligation.Footnote 36
These opposing views are still well represented in contemporary work on the philosophy of promising. Joseph Raz, for instance, argues that it is a mistake to claim that someone has accepted a promise if, upon receiving it, she simply remains ‘stone-faced, saying nothing and not moving a muscle’. It is clear to Raz that there is no acceptance in this case and yet the promise binds the promisor once made, even if the promisee may immediately waive her claim-right to performance. He concludes then that there is no reason to hold that promises need to be accepted in order to bind.Footnote 37 The opposite conclusion is reached by Charles Fried, who invokes the example of a group of people who, without any request by Fried mediating, send him a letter promising they won’t have more than two children. This promise, according to Fried, is not binding, and the reason is that promisees must have the capacity to decide whether to acquire a right to performance against promisors. Therefore, according to Fried, promisees must always accept the promises made to them for such promises to create any binding obligations or rights.Footnote 38 I believe both Raz and Fried’s views capture important elements of the phenomenology of promise-making. We need a theory of the nature of promising that can make sense of cases in which promises appear to bind even if there is no acceptance by the promisee mediating and cases in which promises appear to bind only if the promisee gives her acceptance. In this respect, Reinach’s account of promising proves helpful.
According to Reinach, a promise is a kind of social act. Therefore, as we saw, as a social act the act of promising must necessarily have an addressee (the promisee); and such act is completed once the promisee can apprehend the promise in her experience. As he puts it, the promisee ‘[…] must take cognizance of the act of promising itself, he must, as we would put it somewhat more exactly, consciously take in the promising’.Footnote 39 Moreover, as we saw, promises have certain immediate deontic effects. According to Reinach, such effects are an obligation to act as promised, and a correlative claim-right to performance (a claim-right which, once created by the promise, can of course be waived by the promisee).Footnote 40 Yet Reinach’s account of the nature of promising suggests that the promisee’s acceptance is not required for promises to produce their immediate deontic effects. A promise creates an obligation and claim-right once the promisee apprehends it in her experience, that is, once she knows of the promise and its central elements (i.e., the identity of the promisor, and the content of the obligation and claim-right created by it). Thus, if the promisee cannot apprehend these elements about a promise made to her, she cannot acquire any promissory right against the promisor. Therefore, according to Reinach’s account, if the promise in Raz’s example was appropriately apprehended by the promisee, the promisor is obliged. The same applies to Fried’s example. The promise will indeed be binding if the promisors (i.e., the group of people who sent him the letter) know the identity of the promisee (i.e., Fried) and the promisee knows the identity of the promisors, and the content of the obligation and claim-right created by the promise. Reinach’s theory, however, can accommodate cases in which promises bind only insofar as accepted by the promisee.
Reinach acknowledges that some promises are made under the condition that the promisee accepts the promise.Footnote 41 Promisors have the power to render their promise into what we may call a ‘promissory offer’. Here again one may identify a power-conferring conception of promissory offers, that is, one which holds that promissory offers are juridical acts that besides creating a conditional obligation and claim-right to performance, confer a legal power to accept on the promisee, and thus that become unconditionally binding only if the promisee performs the juridical act of acceptance. Yet, as we did before, one may instead adopt a mutual assent conception of a promissory offer, according to which a promissory offer is a juridical act whereby a person (the promisor/offeror) only creates an obligation to perform and a correlative claim-right in another person (the promisee/offeree) whose bindingness is conditional upon the promisee giving her (mere) assent.Footnote 42 Promissory offers have in common with what I will call ‘basic promises’ the type of deontic effect they purport to ultimately generate, namely a fully fledged obligation in the promisor and correlative claim-right to performance in the promisee. Yet they are still offers, for the obligations and claim-rights they create bind only if their addressees assent to their bindingness. Thus, according to Reinach, among the different juridical acts that persons may choose to perform, they can make basic promises, which as we saw bind once apprehended by the promisee, and promissory offers, which bind once apprehended and accepted by the promisee. Furthermore, there is another important difference between basic promises and promissory offers.
As we saw, it is in the nature of promises to create a claim-right to performance in the promisee. The fact that promises create claim-rights to performance means that the promisee acquires a form of personal authority or exclusive deontic control over the promisor in the matter of the promise: it is exclusively up to the promisee to demand performance or to release the promisor from his obligation by waiving her promissory right. Among other things, the relationship of exclusive deontic control that promises generate entails that promisors do not have the unilateral power to revoke their promise, for again, if promises grant the promisee entitlements to exclusive deontic control over the promisor in the matter of the promise (i.e., a claim-right to performance), only the promisee and not the promisor can have the power to release the promisor.Footnote 43 To be sure, by mutual agreement, the parties to a relationship of obligation can entitle both the obligee and the obligor with the power to revoke such relationship.Footnote 44 Yet this type of deontic relationship differs from that created by promises which, as I have characterized them here at least, necessarily amount to relationships of right or exclusive deontic control by the promisee over the promisor in the matter of the promise.Footnote 45 The essential irrevocability (by the promisor) of promissory relationships helps us to further distinguish basic promises from promissory offers. Unlike a basic promise, there is nothing in the concept of a validly made promissory offer that prevents it from being revoked by the promisor before accepted by the promisee. This is because offers, once apprehended by the offeree, do not constitute binding relationships of right (i.e., of exclusive deontic control) until accepted. Yet once accepted, a promissory offer produces a relationship of exclusive deontic control and therefore the promisor lacks the ability to revoke the promise (unless, as we said, the promisee has agreed to the promisor having such capacity and in such case their relationship is not a promissory deontic relationship any longer but one of a different kind).Footnote 46
Let’s now conclude by analyzing the consequences of this way of understanding the nature of promises for the problem of contract formation.
12.4.1 Promises and the Necessity of Agreement
If we remain committed to NOA, promises in their basic form are not in themselves sufficient to initiate the process of contract formation, since basic promises produce obligations which are not conditional upon both involved parties’ assents. Thus only promises that constitute promissory offers can count among the facts that can get contract formation started.Footnote 47 A theory of contract that purports to give promises an essential role in the process of contract formation must thus either propose an alternative conception of promising whereby promises bind only insofar as the promisee gives her assent,Footnote 48 or simply abandon NOA and endorse the view that at least some contracts may bind unilaterally.Footnote 49 To be sure, the idea that basic, unilaterally binding promises do not constitute the foundations of contractual liability is of course compatible with holding that the positive law may consider them as capable of generating a sui generis or a merely legal, noncontractual form of liability. Indeed, this seems to be the case in the legal systems in which unilateral promises’ binding force is legally recognized.Footnote 50 At this stage, however, one may wonder why we should remain committed to NOA. Is there any reason we should maintain that only those rights whose bindingness depends on both parties’ assents should be deemed contractual in nature? In this chapter, my aim has been to map out some of the relevant notions that make up the conceptual landscape of contract formation if we assume NOA to be true. A defense of NOA, however, should amount to explaining the normative point, function or value of the fact that contractual rights and obligations can only be a product of both parties’ assents. It therefore entails getting into the terrain of the moral or normative foundations of contract, and I, of course, cannot embark on such an enterprise here. Let me finish, however, by outlining a thesis regarding where the justification of NOA may lie.
One may defend the soundness of NOA by invoking a view regarding the justification of the enforceability of contracts. According to this view, both basic promises and contractual agreements entail the parties immediately affecting (i.e., creating, modifying, terminating) their rights by choice or fiat. However, the view goes, there is a basic principle in the morality of rights which holds that one cannot, by sheer unilateral choice, change the basic principles that determine the permissible use of force, that is, produce a change in our enforceable rights. According to this principle, whilst I can unilaterally make it the case that I simply owe it to you, by making a basic promise, to give you $10, I cannot without your assent mediating grant you a claim to enforce such right against me – namely a claim that entitles you to exercise necessary and proportionate force (either directly or through institutional mechanisms) to extract performance or compensation upon my breach.Footnote 51 If this moral principle is sound, contractual agreements but not unilateral juridical acts can create enforceable rights. Of course, a just legislature can also create enforceable rights and thus render a unilateral promise, which is in principle unenforceable, legally enforceable.Footnote 52 Yet individuals, under this view, without the backing of such an additional collective juridical act (i.e., legislation) cannot create enforceable entitlements unless all the parties involved (i.e., obligors and right-holders) have assented to the creation of such entitlements. Thus, if it is in the nature of enforceable legal rights that they cannot be unilaterally created and validly made contracts create not merely binding but enforceable rights, then NOA must be sound.