Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-mz6gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-10-09T04:59:01.333Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 August 2025

Olof Pettersson
Affiliation:
Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
Pauliina Remes
Affiliation:
Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Information

Type
Chapter
Information
Platonic Autonomy
Self-Determination, Unity, and Cooperation
, pp. 256 - 266
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Book purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Bibliography

Adam, J., The Republic of Plato, vol. 2 (Cambridge University Press, 1963).Google Scholar
Ademollo, F., The Cratylus of Plato: A Commentary (Cambridge University Press, 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alcoff, L., ‘Epistemic Identities’, Episteme 7 (2010), 128137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, R. E., Socrates and Legal Obligation (University of Minnesota Press, 1980).Google Scholar
Allen, R. E. (trans.) The Dialogues of Plato, Vol. 1: Eutyphro, Apology, Crito, Meno, Gorgias, Menexenus (Yale University Press, 1984).Google Scholar
Ambury, J. M., ‘The Place of Displacement: The Elenchus in Plato’s Alcibiades I’, Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011), 241260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ambury, J. M., ‘Socratic Character: Proclus on the Function of Erotic Intellect’, in Layne, D. A. and Tarrant, H. (eds.) The Neoplatonic Socrates (University of Pennsylvania Press, 2014), pp. 109117.Google Scholar
Ambury, J. M., ‘Neoplatonic Pedagogy’, Dionysius 33 (2015), 4975.Google Scholar
Ambury, J. M., Neoplatonic Pedagogy and the Alcibiades I: Crafting the Contemplative (Cambridge University Press, 2024).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ambury, J. M. and German, A., Knowledge and Ignorance of Self in Platonic Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 2019).Google Scholar
Anagnostopoulos, G., ‘Plato’s Cratylus: The Two Theories of the Correctness of Names’, Review of Metaphysics 25 (1972), 693695.Google Scholar
Barker, E., Greek Political Theory: Plato and His Predecessors (Methuen and Co., 1918).Google Scholar
Barney, R., Names and Nature in Plato’s Cratylus (Routledge, 2001).Google Scholar
Bauer, H. H. (ed.), Lucretius, De rerum natura libri sex (Teubner, 1992).Google Scholar
Bengson, J., Cuneo, T. and Shafer-Landau, R., ‘Method in the Service of Progress’, Analytic Philosophy 60 (2019), 179205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benitez, E., ‘Deliberation and Moral Expertise in Plato’s Crito’, Apeiron 29 (1996), 2148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, H., ‘The Priority of Definition and the Socratic Elenchos’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 8 (1990), 1965.Google Scholar
Benson, H., Socratic Wisdom: The Model of Knowledge in Plato’s Early Dialogues (Oxford University Press, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, H., ‘What Should Euthyphro Do?’, History of Philosophy Quarterly 30 (2013), 115146.Google Scholar
Bjelde, J., ‘Knowledge is Teachable’, Mind 130/518 (2021), 475502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bloom, A. (ed. and trans.), The Republic of Plato (Basic Books, 1968, 2nd edition 1991).Google Scholar
Bobonich, C., Plato’s Utopia Recast (Oxford University Press, 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobonich, C., ‘Plato on Akrasia and Knowing Your Own Mind’, in Bobonich, C. and Destreé, P. (eds.) Akrasia in Greek Philosophy: From Socrates to Plotinus (Brill, 2007), pp. 4155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bosanquet, B., A Companion to Plato’s Republic for English Readers (Macmillan & Co., 1895).Google Scholar
Boys-Stones, G., Platonist Philosophy 80 BC to AD 250: An Introduction and Collection of Sources in Translation (Cambridge University Press, 2018).Google Scholar
Boys-Stones, G., ‘Plutarch’s E at Delphi: The Hypothesis of Platonic Authority’, in Erler, M., Heßler, J. E. and Petrucci, F. M. (eds.) Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition (Cambridge University Press, 2021), pp. 149162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brännmark, J., ‘Leading a Life of One’s Own: On Well-Being and Narrative Autonomy’, in Olsaretti, S. (ed.) Preferences and Well-Being, vol. 59 (Cambridge University Press, 2006), pp. 6582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brickhouse, T. C. and Nicholas, D.S., Socratic Moral Psychology (Cambridge University Press, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brisson, L. and Pradeau, J.-F., Platon: Les Lois, traduction, introduction, et notes, vol. 1, (Flammarion, 2006).Google Scholar
Brisson, L. and Pradeau, J.-F., Les Lois de Platon (Presses Universitaires de France, 2007).Google Scholar
Broadie, S., Plato’s Sun-Like Good: Dialectic in the Republic (Cambridge University Press, 2021).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J., ‘Normative Requirements’, Ratio 12 (1999), 398419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, E., ‘The Unity of the Soul in Plato’s Republic’, in Barney, R., Brennan, T. and Brittain, C. (eds.) Plato and the Divided Self (Cambridge University Press, 2012), pp. 5373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnet, J., Plato’s Euthyphro, Apology of Socrates, and Crito (Clarendon Press, 1924).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M., ‘Ancient Freedoms’, Howison Lecture at the University of California, Berkeley, published posthumously as Appendix I in Atack, C., Schofield, M. and Sedley, D. (eds.) Explorations in Ancient and Modern Philosophy vol. 3 (Cambridge University Press, 2022), pp. 329355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M., ‘Plato and the Dairy-Maids: The Distribution of Happiness Inside and Outside the Ideal City of the Republic’, in Atack, C., Schofield, M. and Sedley, D. (eds.) Explorations in Ancient and Modern Philosophy vol. 3 (Cambridge University Press, 2022), pp. 96118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, S. and Westlund, A., ‘Personal Autonomy’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018), Zalta, E. N. (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/personal-autonomy/ (accessed 29 January 2025).Google Scholar
Callard, A., Aspiration: The Agency of Becoming (Oxford University Press, 2018).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cammack, D., ‘Deliberation and Discussion in Classical Athens’, Journal of Political Philosophy 2 (2020), 135166.Google Scholar
Carone, G. R., ‘Akrasia in the Republic: Does Plato Change His Mind?’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 20 (2001), 107148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carpenter, A., ‘Judging Strives to be Knowing’, in Brisson, L. and Notomi, N. (eds.) Plato’s Republic: Proceedings of the IXth Symposium Platonicum (Academia Verlag, 20122013), pp. 262266.Google Scholar
Carpenter, A., ‘Ranking Knowledge in Plato’s Philebus’, Phronesis 60 (2015), 180205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carpenter, A., ‘Perfect Knowledge and Its Affects’, in Jirsa, J., Karfik, F. and Špinka, Š (eds.) Plato’s Philebus (OIKOYMENH, 2017), pp. 208229.Google Scholar
Carpenter, A., ‘Ideals and Ethical Formation: Confessions of a Buddhist-Platonist’, in Coseru, C. (ed.) Reasons and Empty Persons: Mind, Metaphysics, and Morality: Essays in Honor of Mark Siderits (Springer, 2023), pp. 387415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Consigny, S., ‘Gorgias’ Use of the Epideictic’, Philosophy and Rhetoric 25 (1992), 281297.Google Scholar
Coady, D., ‘Two Concepts of Epistemic Injustice’, Episteme 7 (2010), 101113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coope, U., ‘Free to Think? Epistemic Authority and Thinking for Oneself’, Journal of the British Academy 7 (2019), 1123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coope, U., Freedom and Responsibility in Neoplatonist Thought (Oxford University Press, 2020).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, J. M. (ed.), Plato: Complete Works (Hackett, 1997).Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M., Reason and Emotion (Princeton University Press, 1998).Google Scholar
Curtis, E. A., Socially Situating Moral Knowledge (University of Colorado, 2013).Google Scholar
Cuypers, S., Self-Identity and Personal Autonomy (Ashgate, 2001).Google Scholar
Denyer, N., ‘Authority and the Dialectic of Socrates’, in Bryan, J., Wardy, R. and Warren, J. (eds.) Authors and Authorities in Ancient Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 2018), pp. 4157.Google Scholar
Destreé, P., ‘Aristotle on the Causes of Akrasia’, in Bobonich, C. and Destreé, P. (eds.) Akrasia in Greek Philosophy: From Socrates to Plotinus (Brill, 2007), pp. 139166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devereux, D., ‘Socrates’ Kantian Conception of Virtue’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (1995), 381408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dodds, E. R., Plato: Gorgias (Oxford University Press, 1959).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duke, A., Hicken, E. F., Nicoll, W. S. M., Robinson, W. B. and Strachan, J. C. G. (eds.) Platonis Opera: Volume I (Oxford University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Dworkin, G., The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge University Press, 1988).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehige, C. and Wessels, U. (eds.), Preferences (Walter De Gruyter, 1998).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferrari, G. R. F., ‘Socratic Irony as Pretense’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34 (2008), 133.Google Scholar
Fine, G., ‘Knowledge and Belief in Republic V’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 60 (1978), 121139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, G., ‘Knowledge and Belief in Republic V–VII’, in Everson, S. (ed.) Companions to Ancient Thought 1: Epistemology (Cambridge University Press, 1990), pp. 85115.Google Scholar
Fisher, N. R. E., Slavery in Classical Greece. Reprinted with corrections. Classical World Series (Bristol Classical Press, 1995. Original ed. 1993).Google Scholar
Forman, L. L., Selections from Plato (Macmillan, 1911).Google Scholar
Forsdyke, S., Slaves and Slavery in Ancient Greece (Cambridge University Press, 2021).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fowler, H. N., Plato in Twelve Volumes, vol. 12 (Harvard University Press, William Heinemann Ltd., 1921).Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H., ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’, in Frankfurt, H. (ed.) The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 1125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, M., ‘Plato’s Arguments and the Dialogue Form’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol.: Methods of Interpreting Plato and His Dialogues (1992), 201219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, M., A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought (University of California Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Fricker, E., ‘Testimony and Epistemic Autonomy’, in Lackey, J. and Sosa, E. (eds.) The Epistemology of Testimony (Oxford University Press, 2006), 225256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, M., ‘Rational Authority and Social Power’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 98 (1998), 159177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, M., ‘Feminism in Epistemology’, in Fricker, M. and Hornsby, J. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Feminism in Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 2006), pp. 146165.Google Scholar
Fricker, M., Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing (Oxford University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuller, S., ‘What Can Philosophy Teach Us About the Post-Truth Condition’, in Peters, M. A. et al. (eds.) Post-Truth, Fake News (Springer Nature, 2018), pp. 1326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ganson, T. S., ‘The Rational/Non-Rational Distinction in Plato’s Republic,’ Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 36 (2009), 179196.Google Scholar
Gardiner, G., ‘Evidentialism and Moral Encroachment’, in McCain, K. (ed.) Believing in Accordance with the Evidence (Springer Verlag, 2018), pp. 169195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garlan, Y., Slavery in Ancient Greece. Revised and expanded edition of Les esclaves en Grèce ancient (Librairie François Maspéro, 1982), tr. J. Lloyd (Cornell University Press, 1988).Google Scholar
German, A., ‘Freedom and Subjectivity: Platonic Reflections on a Hegelian Theme’, in Schmidt, C. (ed.) Post-Subjectivity (Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2014), pp. 163182.Google Scholar
Gill, C., Personality in Greek Epic, Tragedy, and Philosophy: The Self in Dialogue (Clarendon Press, 1996).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A., Knowledge in a Social World (Oxford University Press, 1999).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gonzalez, F., ‘Plato’s Perspectivism’, Plato Journal 16 (2016) 3148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, M., ‘Hypostasizing Socrates’, in Layne, D. A. and Tarrant, H. (eds.) The Neoplatonic Socrates (University of Pennsylvania Press, 2014), pp. 97108.Google Scholar
Griffin, M. trans., Olympiodorus: Life of Plato and On Plato First Alcibiades 1–9, Ancient Commentators on Aristotle (Bloomsbury Academic, 2014).Google Scholar
Griffin, M. trans., Olympiodorus: On Plato First Alcibiades 10–28, Ancient Commentators on Aristotle (Bloomsbury Academic, 2016).Google Scholar
Griffith, T. and Schofield, M. (eds.), Plato: The Laws (Cambridge University Press, 2016).Google Scholar
Grube, G. M. A., rev. Reeve, C. D. C. (trans.), Plato: Complete ed. Cooper, J. M. (Hackett Publishing Company, 1997), pp. 9711223.Google Scholar
Hardwig, J., ‘Epistemic Dependence’, Journal of Philosophy 82 (1985), 335349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harte, V., ‘Conflicting Values in Plato’s Crito’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 81 (1999), 117147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haslanger, S., ‘On Being Objective and Being Objectified’, in Antony, L. and Witt, C. (eds.) A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity (Westview, 2002), pp. 209253.Google Scholar
Hatzistavrou, A., ‘Socrates’ Deliberative Authoritarianism’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 29 (2005), 75113.Google Scholar
Heath, J., The Talking Greeks: Speech, Animals, and the Other in Homer, Aeschylus, and Plato (Cambridge University Press, 2005).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herder, J. G., Werke in zehn Bänden, in Bollacher, M., Brummack, J., Gaier, U., Grimm, G., Irmscher, H. D., Smend, R. and Wisbert, R. (eds.) (Deutsche Klassiker Verlag, 1989).Google Scholar
Herder, J. G., Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit, ed. Bollacher, M. (Deutsche Klassiker Verlag, 1989).Google Scholar
Hills, A., ‘Understanding Why’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 115 (2015), 661688.Google Scholar
Hills, A., The Beloved Self: Morality and the Challenge from Egoism (Oxford University Press, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howell, R. J., ‘Google Morals, Virtue, and the Asymmetry of Deference’, Noûs 48 (2014), 389415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irani, T., Plato on the Value of Philosophy: The Art of Argument in the Gorgias and Phaedrus (Cambridge University Press, 2017).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, T., Plato’s Moral Theory: The Early and Middle Dialogues (Oxford University Press, 1979).Google Scholar
Irwin, T., Plato’s Ethics (Oxford University Press, 1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, R., ‘Late Platonist Poetics: Olympiodorus and the Myth of Plato’s Gorgias’, in Schenkeveld, D. M., Abbenes, J. G. J., Slings, S. R. and Sluiter, I. (eds.) Greek Literary Theory After Aristotle (VU University Press, 1995), 275299.Google Scholar
Jackson, R., Lycos, K. and Tarrant, H. (trans.), Olympiodorus: Commentary on Plato’s Gorgias (Brill, 1998).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaggar, A., ‘Ethics Naturalized’, Metaphilosophy 31 (2000) 452468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
John, S., ‘Epistemic Trust and the Ethics of Science Communication’, Social Epistemology 32 (2018), 7587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamtekar, R., Plato’s Moral Psychology (Oxford University Press, 2017).Google Scholar
Kelly, T., ‘Epistemic Rationality as Instrumental Rationality: A Critique’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66 (2000), 612640.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kent Sprague, R. (trans.), Plato: Laches and Charmides (Hackett Press, 1992).Google Scholar
Ketchum, R. J., ‘Names, Forms and Conventionalism: Cratylus 383–395’, Phronesis 24 (1979), 133147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kiesewetter, B., The Normativity of Rationality (Oxford University Press, 2017).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klosko, G., The Development of Plato’s Political Theory (Oxford University Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koller, H., Die Mimesis in der Antike: Nachahmung, Darstellung, Ausdruck (Francke, 1954).Google Scholar
Kolodny, N., ‘Why Be Rational?’, Mind 114/455 (2005), 509563.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M., ‘Self-Constitution in the Ethics of Plato and Kant’, The Journal of Ethics 3 (1999), 129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R., Socrates and the State (Princeton University Press, 1984).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, N., ‘Plato on the Correctness of Names’, American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971), 126138.Google Scholar
Kukla, R., ‘Objectivity and Perspective in Empirical Knowledge’, Episteme 3 (2006), 8095.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kurke, L., Aesopic Conversations: Popular Tradition, Cultural Dialogue, and the Invention of Greek Prose (Princeton University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Lackey, J., ‘Experts and Peer Disagreement’, in Benton, M. A., Hawthorne, J. and Rabinowitz, D. (eds.) Knowledge, Belief, and God: New Insights in Religious Epistemology (Oxford University Press, 2018), pp. 228245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laks, A., ‘Freedom, Liberality, and Liberty in Plato’s Laws’, Social Philosophy and Policy 24 (2007), 130152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laks, A., Plato’s Second Republic: As Essay on the Laws (Princeton University Press, 2022).Google Scholar
Lane, M., ‘Persuasion et force dans la politique platonicienne’, in Brancacci, A., Murr, D. El and Taormina, D. P. (eds.) Aglaïa: autour de Platon: Mélanges offerts à Monique Dixsaut (Vrin, 2010), pp. 81108.Google Scholar
Lane, M., ‘Placing Plato in the History of Liberty’, History of European Ideas 44 (2018), 702718.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lane, M., Of Rule and Office: Plato’s Ideas of the Political (Princeton University Press, 2023).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, R., ‘Feminism in Epistemology’, in Fricker, M. and Hornsby, N. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Feminism in Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 2000), pp. 127145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Liddell, H. G. and Scott, R., A Greek-English Lexicon (The Clarendon Press, 1968).Google Scholar
Lombardo, S. and Bell, K., (trans.), Plato: Protagoras (Hackett Press, 1992).Google Scholar
Long, A. A., ‘Slavery as a Philosophical Metaphor in Plato and Xenophon’, in Patterson, R., Karasmanis, V. and Hermann, A. (eds.), Presocratics and Plato, (Parmenides Publishing, 2012), pp. 351366.Google Scholar
Long, A. G., Conversation and Self-Sufficiency in Plato (Oxford University Press, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Long, C. P., Aristotle on the Nature of Truth (Cambridge University Press, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lorenz, H., The Brute Within: Appetitive Desire in Plato and Aristotle (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lott, T., ‘Disagreement and Knowledge: The Case of Plato’s Alcibiades’, Trames 24 (2020), 403421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycos, K., ‘Olympiodorus on Pleasure and the Good in Plato’s Gorgias’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12 (1994), 183205.Google Scholar
Mackenzie, C., ‘Three Dimensions of Autonomy: A Relational Analysis’, in Veltman, A. and Piper, M. (eds.) Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender (Oxford University Press, 2014), pp. 1541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marchant, E. C. and Bowersock, G. W. (trans.), Xenophon: Scripta Minora, Loeb Classical Library 183 (Harvard University Press; William Heinemann, Ltd., 1925).Google Scholar
Marquez, X., A Stranger’s Knowledge: Statesmanship, Philosophy and Law in Plato’s Statesman (Parmenides Publishing, 2012).Google Scholar
Matheson, J. and Chock, V. J., ‘Science Communication and Epistemic Injustice’, Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 8 (2019), 19.Google Scholar
Matheson, J. and Lougheed, K. (eds.), Epistemic Autonomy (Routledge, 2022).Google Scholar
McCabe, M. M., Plato’s Individuals (Princeton University Press, 1994).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCabe, M. M., ‘Is Dialectic as Dialectic Does? The Virtue of Philosophical Conversation’ in her Platonic Conversations (Oxford University Press, 2015), 100124.Google Scholar
McCabe, M. M., Platonic Conversations (Oxford University Press, 2015).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCoy, M., Plato on the Rhetoric of Philosophers and Sophists (Cambridge University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCoy, M. B., Image and Argument in Plato’s Republic (SUNY, 2020).Google Scholar
Medvecky, F., ‘Institutionalized Science Communication and Epistemic Injustice’, Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 8 (2019), 1520.Google Scholar
Mele, A., Autonomous Agents: From Self-Control to Autonomy (Oxford University Press, 1995).Google Scholar
Meyer, S. S., Aristotle on Moral Responsibility (Basil Blackwell, 1993)Google Scholar
Meyer, S. S. (trans.), Plato: Laws 1 & 2, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2015).Google Scholar
Meyer, S. S., ‘The Laws’ in Fine, G., (ed) The Oxford Handbook to Plato, 2nd edition (Oxford University Press, 2019), 359378.Google Scholar
Meyer, S. S., ‘Civic Freedom in Plato’s Laws’, Polis 38 (2021), 512534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, J. S., On Liberty [1859], in Robson, J. M. (ed.) The Collected Works of J.S. Mill, vol. 18 (University of Toronto Press, 1977).Google Scholar
Miller, F., ‘Platonic Freedom’, in Schmitz, D. and Pavel, C. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Freedom (Oxford University Press, 2016), pp. 143159.Google Scholar
Miller, M, ‘Platonic Provocations: Reflections on the Soul and the Good in the Republic’, in O’Meara, D. (ed.) Platonic Investigations (Catholic University Press, 1985), pp. 163193.Google Scholar
Miller, M., ‘The Arguments I Seem to Hear: Argument and Irony in the Crito’, a work of Plato. Phronesis 41 (1996), 121137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrow, G. R., Plato’s Cretan City (Princeton University Press, 1960).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moss, J., ‘Appearances and Calculations,’ Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34 (2008), 3568.Google Scholar
Moss, J., Plato’s Epistemology: Being and Seeming (Oxford University Press, 2021).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moss, J. and Schwab, W., ‘The Birth of Belief’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 57 (2019), 132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muller, R., La doctrine platonicienne de la liberté (Vrin, 1997).Google Scholar
Murdoch, I., ‘Vision and Choice in Morality’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 30 (1956), 3258.Google Scholar
Murdoch, I., ‘The Idea of Perfection’, in her Sovereignty of Good (Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1970), pp. 144.Google Scholar
Naas, M., ‘From Spontaneity to Automaticity: Polar (Opposite) Reversal at Statesman 269c–274d’, in Sallis, J. (ed.) Plato’s Statesman: Dialectic, Myth, and Politics (SUNY Press, 2017), pp. 1531.Google Scholar
Nagel, T., The Last Word (Oxford University Press, 1997).Google Scholar
Nehamas, A., ‘Meno’s Paradox and Socrates as a Teacher’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 3 (1985), 130.Google Scholar
Nehamas, A., ‘What Did Socrates Teach and to Whom Did He Teach It?’, The Review of Metaphysics 46 (1992), 279306.Google Scholar
Neiman, S., The Unity of Reason (Oxford University Press, 1994).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nietzsche, F., Gesammelte Werke (Musarionausgabe), Band XIX. Der Wille Zur Macht (Musarion Verlag, 1926).Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F., The Will to Power, trans. Kaufmann, W. (Random House, 1967).Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F., Jenseits von Gut und Böse, ed. Colli, G. and Montinari, M. (De Gruyter, 1999).Google Scholar
Nightingale, A., ‘Subtext and Subterfuge in Plato’s Cratylus’, in Michelini, A. N. (ed.) Plato as Author: The Rhetoric of Philosophy (Brill, 2003), pp. 223240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Connor, C., Goldberg, S. and Goldman, A., ‘Social Epistemology’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2024), Zalta, E. N. and Nodelmann, U. (eds.) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2024/entries/epistemology-social (accessed 29 January 2025).Google Scholar
O’Neill, O., Constructions of Reason (Cambridge University Press, 1998).Google Scholar
Ober, J., The Greeks and the Rational: The Discovery of Practical Reason, Sather Classical Lectures, 2019 (University of California Press, 2022).Google Scholar
Pangle, T. J. (trans.), The Laws of Plato (University of Chicago Press, 1980).Google Scholar
Pasnau, R., ‘Epistemology Idealised’, Mind 122/488 (2013), 9871021.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pasnau, R., After Certainty (Oxford University Press, 2017).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patterson, O., Slavery and Social Death (Harvard University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
Penner, T., ‘Plato and Davidson: Parts of the Soul and Weakness of Will’, in Copp, D. (ed.) Canadian Philosophers: Celebrating Twenty Years of the Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary volume 16 (1990), 3572.Google Scholar
Pettersson, O., A Multiform Desire (Uppsala University, 2013).Google Scholar
Pettersson, O., ‘The Science of Philosophy: Discourse and Deception in Plato’s Sophist’, Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (2017), 221237.Google Scholar
Pettersson, O., ‘Power and Person in Plato’s Alcibiades I’, Ancient Philosophy 41 (2021), 2336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettersson, O., ‘Commerce, Theft and Deception: The Etymology of Hermes in Plato’s Cratylus’, in Mikeš, V. (ed.) Plato’s Cratylus: Proceedings of the Eleventh Symposium Platonicum Pragense (Brill, 2022), pp. 124143.Google Scholar
Piper, M., ‘Autonomy, Normative’, in International Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://iep.utm.edu/normative-autonomy/ (accessed 29 January 2025).Google Scholar
Places, E. des and Diès, A. (ed. and trans.), Platon: Oeuvres Complètes XI–XII: Les Lois, 4 vols. (Belles Lettres, 1951–6).Google Scholar
Pollock, J., Contemporary Theories of Knowledge (Rowman and Littlefield, 1986).Google Scholar
Popper, K., The Logic of Scientific Discovery (Hutchinson, 1959).Google Scholar
Press, G., ‘Knowledge as Vision in Plato’s Dialogues’, Journal of Neoplatonic Studies 3 (1995), 6190.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D., ‘Seeing It For Oneself: Perceptual Knowledge, Understanding, and Intellectual Autonomy’, Episteme, 13 (2016), 2942.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raaflaub, K., The Discovery of Freedom in Ancient Greece, trans. R. Franciscono (University of Chicago Press, 1984), originally published as Die Entdeckung der Freiheit (Oscar Beck, 1985).Google Scholar
Raz, J., The Morality of Freedom (Oxford University Press, 1986).Google Scholar
Renaud, F., ‘Rhetorique philosophique et fondement de la dialectique: Le commentaire du Gorgias par Olympiodore’, Philosophique antique 6 (2006), 137161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Renaud, F. and Tarrant, H., The Platonic Alcibiades I: The Dialogue and Its Ancient Reception (Cambridge University Press, 2015).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosati, C., ‘Preference Formation and Personal Good’, in Olsaretti, S. (ed.) Preferences and Well-Being, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 59 (2006), 3364.Google Scholar
Santas, G. X., Socrates: Philosophy in Plato’s Early Dialogues (Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979).Google Scholar
Saunders, T. (trans.), Plato: The Laws (Penguin Books, 1970), in J. M. Cooper (ed.) Plato: Complete Works (Hackett Publishing, 1997).Google Scholar
Schmitt, A., Modernity and Plato: Two Paradigms of Rationality (Camden House, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schofield, M., Plato: Political Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schofield, M., ‘Friendship and Justice in the Laws’, in Boys-Stones, G., El Murr, D. and Gill, C. (eds.) The Platonic Art of Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 2013), pp. 283297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schöpsdau, K., Platon: Nomoi (Gesetze) Buch I–III (Vandenhoek und Ruprecht, 1994).Google Scholar
Schultz, A. M., Plato’s Socrates as Narrator: A Philosophical Muse (Lexington Press, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwab, W., ‘Explanation in the Epistemology of the Meno’ in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 48 (2015), 136.Google Scholar
Schwab, W., ‘Understanding Epistēmē in Plato’s Republic’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 51 (2016), 4186.Google Scholar
Schwab, W., ‘Plato’s Ideal Epistemology’, in Hetherington, S. and Smith, N. D. (eds.) What the Ancients Offer to Ideal Epistemology (Routledge, 2019), pp. 86105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scodel, H. R., Diaeresis and Myth in Plato’s Statesman (Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1987).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedley, D., Plato’s Cratylus (Cambridge University Press, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C., ‘Simple Souls’, in Wagner, E. (ed.) Essays on Plato’s Psychology (Lexington Books, 2001), pp. 137156.Google Scholar
Slings, S. R., Platonis Rempublicam. Oxford Classics Texts (Oxford University Press, 2003).Google Scholar
Smith, N. D., ‘Plato’s Analogy of Soul and State’, The Journal of Ethics 3 (1999), 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, N. D., ‘What is Liberty For? Plato and Aristotle on Political Freedom’, Skepsis 12 (2001), 7894.Google Scholar
Smith, N. D., ‘Socrates on Practical Deliberation’, History of Philosophy Quarterly 30 (2013), 93113.Google Scholar
Smith, N. D. and Brickhouse, T. C., ‘Socrates on Akrasia’, in Bobonich, C. and Destreé, P. (eds.) Akrasia in Greek Philosophy: From Socrates to Plotinus (Brill, 2007), pp. 117.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R., Animal Minds and Human Morals: The Origins of the Western Debate (Cornell University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Stalley, R. F., An Introduction to Plato’s Laws (Hackett Publishing, 1983).Google Scholar
Stalley, R. F., ‘Plato’s Doctrine of Freedom’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 98 (1998), 145158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stern, P., ‘The Rule of Wisdom and The Rule of Law in Plato’s Statesman’, American Political Science Review, 91 (1997), 264276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strauss, L., ‘On Plato’s Apology of Socrates and Crito’, in his Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy (University of Chicago Press, 1983), pp. 5859.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stroud, S., ‘Epistemic Partiality in Friendship’, Ethics 116 (2006), 498524.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tarrant, H., Thrasyllan Platonism (Cornell University Press, 1993).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tarrant, H., ‘Olympiodorus and the Surrender of Paganism’, in Garland, L. (ed.) Conformity and Non-Conformity in Byzantium (Verlag Adolf M. Hakkert, 1997), pp. 181192.Google Scholar
Tarrant, H., ‘Politike Eudaimonia: Olympiodorus on Plato’s Republic’, in Boudouris, K. (ed.) Plato’s Political Thought and Contemporary Political Theory 2 (International Center for Greek Philosophy and Culture, 1997), pp. 200207.Google Scholar
Tarrant, H., ‘Introduction’, in Jackson, R., Lycos, K. and Tarrant, H. (trans.) Olympiodorus: Commentary on Plato’s Gorgias. Philosophia Antiqua 78 (Brill, 1998), pp. 150.Google Scholar
Tarrant, H., ‘Olympiodorus and History’, in Hillard, T. W., Kearsley, R. A., Nixon, C. E. V. and Nobbs, A. M. (eds.) Ancient History in a Modern University, vol. 2 (Ancient History Documentation Centre, 1998), pp. 417425.Google Scholar
Taylor, C., Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge University Press, 1989).Google Scholar
Thomas, J. C., ‘Inquiry Without Names in Plato’s Cratylus’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (2008), 341364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trivigno, F. V., ‘Etymology and the Power of Names in Plato’s Cratylus’, Ancient Philosophy 32 (2012), 3575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trivigno, F. V., ‘The Moral and Literary Character of Hippias in the Hippias Major,’ Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 50 (2016), 3165.Google Scholar
Trivigno, F., ‘Above the Law and out for Justice: 291a1-297b4’, in Dimas, P., Lane, M. and Meyer, S. S. (eds.) Plato’s Statesman: A Philosophical Discussion (Oxford University Press, 2021), pp. 156176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vasiliou, I., ‘Conditional Irony in the Socratic Dialogues’, Classical Quarterly 49 (1999), 456472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, G., ’Slavery in Plato’s Thought’, The Philosophical Review 50 (1941), 289304; reprinted in Vlastos, G., Platonic Studies (Princeton University Press, 1981), pp. 148163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, G., ‘The Socratic Elenchus’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 1 (1983), 5970.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G., Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher (Cornell University Press, 1991).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, G., ‘The Socratic Elenchus: Method is All’, in Vlastos, G., Socratic Studies (Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogt, K., Belief and Truth: A Skeptic Reading of Plato (Oxford University Press, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weiss, R., Socrates Dissatisfied: An Analysis of Plato’s Crito (Rowman & Littlefield, 2001).Google Scholar
Westerink, L. G. (ed.), Olympiodori in Platonis Gorgiam commentaria (B. G. Teubner, 1970).Google Scholar
Wiland, E., ‘Moral Testimony. Going on the Offensive’, Oxford Studies in Metaethics 12 (2017), 5175.Google Scholar
Wiland, E., Guided by Voices: Moral Testimony, Advice, and Forging a ‘We’ (Oxford University Press, 2021).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. A. O., Shame and Necessity (University of California Press, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, E., The Death of Socrates (Harvard University Press, 2007).Google Scholar
Woodruff, P., ‘Self-Ridicule: Socratic Wisdom’, in Destrée, P. and Trivigno, F. (eds.) Laughter, Humor and Comedy in Ancient Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 2019), pp. 165181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woolf, R., ‘Socratic Authority’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 90 (2008), 138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Xenophon. Xenophontis opera omnia, vol. 5. Oxford Classical Texts (Clarendon Press, 1969).Google Scholar
Young, C., ‘Plato’s Concept of Liberty in the Laws’, History of Political Thought 39 (2018), 379398.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L., Epistemic Authority: A Theory of Trust, Authority, and Autonomy in Belief (Oxford University Press, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeyl, D., Plato: Gorgias (Hackett Press, 1994).Google Scholar
Giuliani, R., ‘“Truth Isn’t Truth,” Says Rudy Giuliani: But Nonsense Is Still Nonsense’, The Guardian (20 August 2018), www.theguardian.com/us-news/shortcuts/2018/aug/20/truth-rudy-giuliani-legal-adviser-trump (accessed 29 January 2025).Google Scholar
Giuliani, R., ‘“Truth Isn’t Truth,” Says Rudy Giuliani: But Nonsense Is Still Nonsense’, The Guardian (20 August 2018), www.theguardian.com/us-news/shortcuts/2018/aug/20/truth-rudy-giuliani-legal-adviser-trump (accessed 29 January 2025).Google Scholar

Accessibility standard: WCAG 2.1 AA

The PDF of this book complies with version 2.1 of the Web Content Accessibility Guidelines (WCAG), covering newer accessibility requirements and improved user experiences and achieves the intermediate (AA) level of WCAG compliance, covering a wider range of accessibility requirements.

Content Navigation

Table of contents navigation
Allows you to navigate directly to chapters, sections, or non‐text items through a linked table of contents, reducing the need for extensive scrolling.
Index navigation
Provides an interactive index, letting you go straight to where a term or subject appears in the text without manual searching.

Reading Order & Textual Equivalents

Single logical reading order
You will encounter all content (including footnotes, captions, etc.) in a clear, sequential flow, making it easier to follow with assistive tools like screen readers.
Short alternative textual descriptions
You get concise descriptions (for images, charts, or media clips), ensuring you do not miss crucial information when visual or audio elements are not accessible.

Visual Accessibility

Use of colour is not sole means of conveying information
You will still understand key ideas or prompts without relying solely on colour, which is especially helpful if you have colour vision deficiencies.

Structural and Technical Features

ARIA roles provided
You gain clarity from ARIA (Accessible Rich Internet Applications) roles and attributes, as they help assistive technologies interpret how each part of the content functions.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge-org.demo.remotlog.com is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Olof Pettersson, Uppsala Universitet, Sweden, Pauliina Remes, Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
  • Book: Platonic Autonomy
  • Online publication: 07 August 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009520461.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Olof Pettersson, Uppsala Universitet, Sweden, Pauliina Remes, Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
  • Book: Platonic Autonomy
  • Online publication: 07 August 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009520461.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Olof Pettersson, Uppsala Universitet, Sweden, Pauliina Remes, Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
  • Book: Platonic Autonomy
  • Online publication: 07 August 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009520461.013
Available formats
×