Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cb9f654ff-p5m67 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-08-22T14:46:34.191Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 10 - “The Shapes My Brain Holds”

Kantian Spontaneity and Woolf’s The Waves

from Part III - Kant and Literature

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 May 2025

Claudia Brodsky
Affiliation:
Princeton University, New Jersey
Get access

Summary

This chapter suggests a blueprint for reading literature and philosophy together, through a Kantian notion of spontaneous cognitive form that is flexible and linked with the underpinnings of objective knowledge. While “stream-of-consciousness” fiction is often recruited to enforce empiricist paradigms of the mind, this chapter argues that Woolf’s The Waves discloses what Kant called the mind’s spontaneity. Due largely to her well-known description of the “incessant shower of innumerable atoms” that rain down on the mind, Woolf has been almost exclusively interpreted as an empiricist. This chapter argues, by contrast, that while Woolf may take the sensory impression as a central unit of analysis for her depictions of a consciousness at work, she also routinely exceeds and indeed ironizes the empiricist framework she inherits, laying bare its limits. Woolf most clearly moves beyond the conceit of naturalistically rendered consciousness in the The Waves, which reveals modernist production of fiction at its most Kantian, or at least as a form working in the impasse between Hume and Kant. In representing the internal synthesizing abstractions that underlie the appearance of objects, Woolf’s fiction joins Kant’s epistemology in requiring a type of representation different from description, since what is being rendered has not yet taken the form of an object. Drawing not on Kant’s third Critique but on an anti-psychologistic reading of the first Critique, the broader aim of this chapter is to suggest the real untapped potential that cognitive spontaneity in its theoretical use maintains for aesthetics.

Information

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Book purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Addison, Catherine. A Genealogy of the Verse Novel. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2017.Google Scholar
Allison, Henry. Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, R. Lanier. “Neo-Kantianism and the Roots of Anti-Psychologism.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 13.2 (2005), 312.Google Scholar
Banfield, Ann. The Phantom Table: Woolf, Fry, Russell, and the Epistemology of Modernism. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Barnes, Winston H. F.The Myth of Sense-Data.” In Perceiving, Sensing, and Knowing, ed. Robert J, Swartz. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1965.Google Scholar
Berrong, Richard M.Modes of Literary Impressionism.” Genre 39.2 (2006), 203228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackstone, Bernard. Virginia Woolf: A Commentary. London: Harcourt, 1949.Google Scholar
Bojesen, Emile. “The Education of Consciousness: Virginia Woolf’s The Waves.” Foro de Educación 16 (2018), 99112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brodsky, Claudia. The Imposition of Form: Studies in Narrative Representation and Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2016.Google Scholar
Brodsky, Claudia. The Linguistic Condition: Kant’s Critique of Judgment and the Poetics of Action. London: Bloomsbury, 2021.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brodsky, Claudia. Words’ Worth: What the Poet Does. London: Bloomsbury, 2020.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Canady, John. Mainstreams of Modern Art: David to Picasso. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1959.Google Scholar
Cascardi, Anthony J. The Bounds of Reason. New York: Columbia University Press, 1988.Google Scholar
Cascardi, Anthony J. Consequences of Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.Google Scholar
Cascardi, Anthony J.The Novel.” In Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Literature, ed. Richard Eldridge. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. “Review of B. F. Skinner, ‘Verbal Behavior.’” Language 35.1 (1959), 2658.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conant, James. “Why Kant Is Not a Kantian.” Philosophical Topics 44 (2016), 75125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copland, Sarah. “Conceptual Blending in The Waves.” In Blending and the Study of Narrative: Approaches and Applications, ed. Schneider, Ralph and Hartner, Marcus. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter, 2012.Google Scholar
Dalgeron, Emily. “Reality and Perception: Philosophical Approaches to To the Lighthouse.” In The Cambridge Companion to To the Lighthouse, ed. Pease, Allison. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2015.Google Scholar
DiBattista, Maria. Woolf’s Major Novels: The Fables of Anon. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1980.Google Scholar
Fernihough, Anne. “Consciousness as a Stream.” In The Cambridge Companion to the Modernist Novel, ed. Shiach, Morag. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A. The Language of Thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1975.Google Scholar
Garrity, Jane. “Global Objects in The Waves.” In A Companion to Virginia Woolf, ed. Berman, Jessica. Miley, MA: John Wiley & Sons, 2016.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. “Kant and the Problem of Experience.” Philosophical Topics 34.1–2 (2006), 59106.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. “Kant’s Perceiver,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 87 (2013), 221228.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. “Spontaneity without Rationality: A Kantian Approach to Self-consciousness and Perceptual Content.” In Perceptual Knowledge and Self-Awareness, ed. Giananti, Andrea, Roessler, Johannes, and Soldati, Gianfranco. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2024.Google Scholar
Graham, J. W.Point of View in the Waves: Some Services of the Style.” University of Toronto Quarterly 39.3 (1970), 193211.Google Scholar
Grice, H. Paul. “Logic and Conversation.” In Syntax and Semantics, 3: Speech Acts, ed. Cole, Peter and Morgan, Jerry L.. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd ed. Ed. Selby-Bigge, L. A. and Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978.Google Scholar
James, William. The Principles of Psychology. New York: Dover, 1950. 2 vols.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Norman Kemp Smith. London: Macmillan, 1929.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Patricia. “Guyer on the Value of Freedom.” In Kant on Freedom and Spontaneity, ed. Moran, Kate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Patricia. “A Kantian Critique of Transparency.” In Kant and the Philosophy of Mind: Perception, Reason and the Self, ed. Gomes, Anil and Stephenson, Andrew. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Patricia. Kant’s Thinker, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Patricia. “Kant on Self-consciousness.” The Philosophical Review 108.3 (1999), 345386.Google Scholar
Kronfeld, Chana. On the Margins of Modernism: Decentering Literary Dynamics. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995.Google Scholar
Kronfeld, Maya. “The Philosopher’s Bass Drum: Adorno’s Jazz and the Politics of Rhythm.” Radical Philosophy 2.5 (2019), 3447.Google Scholar
Kronfeld, Maya. “Structure in the Moment: Rhythm Section Responsivity.” Jazz and Culture 4.2, Special Issue, Jazz in the Present Tense (2021), 1422.Google Scholar
Kronfeld, Maya. “Toni Morrison’s Jazz as a Theory of Knowledge.” In Spontaneous Form: Consciousness and Philosophical Fiction, Maya Kronfeld (ms. in preparation).Google Scholar
Lakoff, George. Women, Fire and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about the Mind. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1990.Google Scholar
Land, Thomas. “Kant’s Spontaneity Thesis.” Philosophical Topics 34 (2006), 189220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lodge, David. The Art of Fiction: Illustrated from Classic and Modern Texts. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2014.Google Scholar
Meltzer, Françoise. “Color as Cognition in Symboliste Verse.” Critical Inquiry 5.2 (1978), 253273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, Kate. “Introduction.” In Kant on Freedom and Spontaneity, ed. Moran, Kate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parten, M. B.Social Participation among Preschool Children.” Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 27.3 (1932), 243269.Google Scholar
Pippin, Robert. “Kant on the Spontaneity of Mind.” In Idealism as Modernism: Hegelian Variations, Robert Pippin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Pippin, Robert. Kant’s Theory of Form: An Essay on the Critique of Pure Reason. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1982.Google Scholar
Posnock, Ross. Renunciation: Acts of Abandonment by Writers, Philosophers and Artists. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2016.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, John. Intentionality. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Norman Kemp. A Commentary to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Stroud, Barry. “Naturalism and Skepticism in the Philosophy of Hume.” In The Oxford Handbook of Hume, ed. Russell, Paul. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.Google Scholar
Warren, Daniel. Reality and Impenetrability in Kant’s Philosophy of Nature. New York: Routledge, 2001.Google Scholar
Woolf, Virginia. Diary of Virginia Woolf. Ed. Bell, Ann Olivier. New York: Harcourt, 1985, Vol. 4.Google Scholar
Woolf, Virginia. The Letters of Virginia Woolf. Ed. Nicolson, Nigel and Trautmann, Joanne. New York: Harcourt, 1982. 4 vols.Google Scholar
Woolf, Virginia. “Modern Fiction.” In The Essays of Virginia Woolf, ed. McNeillie, Andrew. London: Hogarth, 1994, Vol. 4.Google Scholar
Woolf, Virginia. Orlando: A Biography. New York: Harcourt, 1993.Google Scholar
Woolf, Virginia. The Waves. New York: Harcourt, 1959.Google Scholar
Wordsworth, William. The Prose Works of William Wordsworth. Ed. Owen, W. J. B. and Smyser, Jane Worthington. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994. 3 vols.Google Scholar
Zhang, Dora. “Feeling with Woolf.” In Strange Likeness: Description and the Modernist Novel, Dora Zhang. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2020.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Accessibility standard: Unknown

Accessibility compliance for the PDF of this book is currently unknown and may be updated in the future.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge-org.demo.remotlog.com is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×