Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-tfzs5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-10-14T04:09:13.536Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

General Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 August 2025

Joseph Stenberg
Affiliation:
Colgate University, New York
Get access

Information

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Book purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

General Bibliography

Adams, Don. 1991. “Aquinas on Aristotle on Happiness.” Medieval Philosophy and Theology, Vol. 1: 98118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, Don. 2004. “Aquinas and Modern Consequentialism.” International Journal of Philosophical Studies. Vol. 12, No. 4: 395417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, Marilyn McCord. 2012. “Why Bodies as Well as Souls in the Life to Come?” In Doolan, Gregory (ed.), The Science of Being as Being: Metaphysical Investigations. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press: 264297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, Robert. 1999. Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Adler, Mortimer. 1949. “The Doctrine of Natural Law in Philosophy.” In Scanlan, Alfred L. (ed.), University of Notre Dame Natural Law Institute Proceedings, Vol. 1. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press: 6584.Google Scholar
Aertsen, Jan. 1996. Medieval Philosophy and the Transcendentals: The Case of Thomas Aquinas. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aertsen, Jan. 1999. “Thomas Aquinas on the Good: The Relation Between Metaphysics and Ethics.” In MacDonald, Scott and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), Aquinas’s Moral Theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press: 235253.Google Scholar
Albert the Great. 1951–. Opera Omnia. Geyer, B. et al. (eds.). Münster: Aschendorff.Google Scholar
Albert the Great. 1890–9. Opera Omnia. Borgnet, Auguste and Borgnet, Emile (eds.). Paris: Vivès.Google Scholar
Alexander of Hales. 1924–48. Summa theologica. Quaracchi: Editiones Collegii S. Bonaventurae.Google Scholar
Anderson, Justin. 2020. Virtue and Grace in the Theology of Thomas Aquinas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1995. The Morality of Happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, Julia. 2001. Voices of Ancient Philosophy: An Introductory Reader. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, Julia. 2011. Intelligent Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1958. “Modern Moral Philosophy.” Philosophy (London, England), Vol. 33: 119.Google Scholar
Ardagh, David. 1974. “Aquinas on Happiness: A Defence.” The New Scholasticism, Vol. 53, No. 4 (Autumn): 428459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ardagh, David. 1975. “Aquinas on Happiness.” PhD dissertation, University of Washington.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1999. Nicomachean Ethics (Second Edition). Terence Irwin (trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett. (Abbreviated EN in the notes.)Google Scholar
Augustine, . 1887. Opera (Corpus scriptorium ecclesiasticorum latinorum. Vienna: Tempsky.Google Scholar
Augustine, . 1954–1981. Opera (Corpus Christianorum, series latina). Turnhout: Brepols.Google Scholar
Austin, Nicholas. 2017. Aquinas on Virtue: A Causal Reading.Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barad, Judith. 1991. “Aquinas on the Role of Emotion in Moral Judgment and Activity.” The Thomist, Vol. 55, No. 3: 397413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barbezat, Michael. 2024. “Medieval Happiness Reconsidered: The Unstable Human Heart in This World and the Next.” In Barclay, Katie, McMahon, Darrin, and Stearns, Peter N. (eds.), The Routledge History of Happiness. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
de Medina, Bartolomé. 1582. Expositio in primam secundae Angelici Doctoris D. Thomae Aquinatis. Salamanca: Typis haeredum Mathiae Gastij.Google Scholar
Bastit, Michel. 2014. “La justice Générale selon saint Thomas: Une politique de la félicité.” Revue Thomiste, Vol. 114: 129142.Google Scholar
Baur, Michael. 2012. “Law and Natural Law.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Beer, Samuel. 1986. “The Rule of the Wise and the Holy: Hierarchy in the Thomistic System.” Political Theory, Vol. 14, No. 3 (August): 391422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bejczy, István (ed.). 2008. Virtue Ethics in the Middle Ages: Commentaries on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, 1200–1500. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Bejczy, István Pieter, and Newhauser, Richard (eds.). 2005. Virtue and Ethics in the Twelfth Century. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biard, Joël. 1998. “La place de la félicité intellectuelle dans l’Éthique buridanienne.” Miscellanea mediaevalia, Vol. 26: 977983.Google Scholar
Blanchette, Olivia. 1992. The Perfection of the Universe According to Aquinas: A Teleological Cosmology. University Park: Penn State University Press.Google Scholar
Blanchette, Olivia. 1994. “The Logic of Perfection in Aquinas.” In Gallagher, D. M. (ed.), Thomas Aquinas and His Legacy. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Bobik, Joseph. 1986. “Aquinas on Friendship with God.” New Scholasticism, Vol. 60: 257271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boethius, . 1934. Consolatio philosophiae. In Weinberger, W. (ed.), Corpus scriptorum ecclesiasticorum latinorum (Vol. 67). Vienna.Google Scholar
Boland, Vivian. 2008. St. Thomas Aquinas. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Boler, John. 1999. “Aquinas on Exceptions in Natural Law.” In MacDonald, Scott and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), Aquinas’s Moral Theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press: 161204.Google Scholar
Bonaventure, . 1882–1902. Opera omnia. Quaracchi: Editiones Collegii S. Bonaventurae.Google Scholar
Bond, Leo. 1941. “A Comparison between Human and Divine Friendship.” Thomist, Vol. 3: 5494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bouillard, Henri. 1944. Conversion et grâce chez S. Thomas d’Aquin: Étude historique. Paris: Aubier.Google Scholar
Bourke, Vernon J. 1974. “Is Thomas Aquinas a Natural Law Ethicist?The Monist, Vol. 58: 5266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourke, Vernon J. 1975. “Right Reason in Contemporary Ethics.” The Thomist, Vol. 38, No. 1: 106124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowlin, John. 1999. Contingency and Fortune in Aquinas’s Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bradford, Gwen. 2016. “Perfectionism.” In Fletcher, Guy (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bradley, Denis. 1997. Aquinas on the Twofold Human Good: Reason and Human Happiness in Aquinas’s Moral Science. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Brenet, Jean-Baptiste. 2011. “S’unir à l’intellect, voir Dieu: Averroès et la Doctrine de la Jonction au Coeur du Thomisme.” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy, Vol. 2: 215247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brock, Stephen. 2010. “The Primacy of the Common Good and the Foundations of Natural Law in St. Thomas.” In Hütter, Reinhard and Levering, Matthew (eds.), Ressourcement Thomism. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press: 234255.Google Scholar
Brock, Stephen. 2020. The Light That Binds: A Study in Thomas Aquinas’s Metaphysics of Natural Law. Eugene, OR: Pickwick.Google Scholar
Brown, Christopher. 2009. “Friendship in Heaven: Aquinas on Supremely Perfect Happiness and the Communion of the Saints.” In Timpe, Kevin (ed.), Metaphysics and God: Essays in Honor of Eleonore Stump. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Brown, Christopher. 2021. Eternal Life and Human Happiness in Heaven: Philosophical Problems, Thomistic Solutions. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Oscar. 1981. Natural Rectitude and Divine Law in Aquinas. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies.Google Scholar
Brown, Stephen. 2002. “The Theological Virtue of Faith: An Invitation to an Ecclesial Life of Truth (IIa IIae, qq. 1–16).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Budziszewski, J. 2017. Commentary on Thomas Aquinas’s Virtue Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Buffon, Valeria. 2004. “Happiness and Knowledge in Some Masters of Arts Before 1250: An Analysis of Some Commentaries on the Book I of Nicomachean Ethics.” Patristica Et Mediaevalia, Vol. 25: 111115.Google Scholar
Buffon, Valeria. 2008. “The Structure of the Soul, Intellectual Virtues, and the Ethical Ideal of Masters of Arts in Early Commentaries on the Nicomachean Ethics.” In Bejczy, István (ed.), Virtue Ethics in the Middle Ages: Commentaries on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, 1200–1500. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Burroughs, Joseph Alvin. 1955. Prudence Integrating the Moral Virtues According to Saint Thomas Aquinas. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Butera, Giuseppe. 2007. “The Moral Status of the First Principle of Practical Reason in Thomas’s Natural-Law Theory.” The Thomist, Vol. 71: 609631.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byerly, T. Ryan, and Silverman, Eric (eds.). 2017. Paradise Understood: New Philosophical Essays About Heaven. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carl, Maria. 1997. “Law, Virtue, and Happiness in Aquinas’s Moral Theory.” The Thomist, Vol. 61, No. 3: 425447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cates, Diana Fritz. 2002. “The Virtue of Temperance (IIa IIae, qq. 141–170).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Celano, Anthony. 1987. “The Concept of Worldly Beatitude in the Writings of Thomas Aquinas.” Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. 25 (April): 215226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Celano, Anthony. 1995. “The End of Practical Wisdom: Ethics as Science in the Thirteenth Century.” Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. 33, No. 2 (April): 225243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Celano, Anthony. 2011. “Happiness.” In Lagerlund, Henrik (ed.), Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy: Philosophy Between 500 and 1500. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.Google Scholar
Celano, Anthony. 2012. “The Relation of Prudence and Synderesis to Happiness in the Medieval Commentaries on Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Miller, Jon (ed.), The Reception of Aristotle’s Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cessario, Romanus. 2002. “The Theological Virtue of Hope (IIa IIae, qq. 17–22).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Chenu, M.-D. 1964. Toward Understanding St. Thomas. A.-M. Landry and D. Hughes (trans.). Chicago: Henry Regnery.Google Scholar
Cleveland, W. Scott, and Dahm, Brandon. 2019. “The Virtual Presence of Acquired Virtues in the Christian.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 93, No. 1 (Winter): 75100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cockayne, Joshua. 2018. “Communal Knowledge and the Beatific Vision.” TheoLogica, Vol. 2, No. 2: 2746.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coimbra Commentators. 1957–. Curso Conimbricense, I: Pe. Manuel de Góis: Moral a Nicómaco de Aristóteles. de Andrade, António Alberto (ed.). Lisboa.Google Scholar
Connolly, John. 2014. Living Without Why: Meister Eckhart’s Critique of the Medieval Concept of Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, John. 1985. “Aristotle on the Goods of Fortune,” Philosophical Review, Vol. 94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copleston, Frederick. 1955. Aquinas. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Copleston, Frederick. 1962. A History of Philosophy: Vol. 2, Medieval Philosophy, Part 2: Albert the Great to Duns Scotus. Garden City, NY: Image Books.Google Scholar
Costa, Iacopo. 2024. “Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas on Charity and the Common Good.” In Haara, Heikki and Toivanen, Juhana (eds.), Common Good and Self-Interest in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Crofts, Richard. 1973. “The Common Good in the Political Theory of Thomas Aquinas.” The Thomist, Vol. 37: 155173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cunningham, S. B. 2008. Reclaiming Moral Agency: The Moral Philosophy of Albert the Great. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Dahm, Brandon. 2015. “Distinguishing Desire and Parts of Happiness.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 89, No. 1: 97114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daly, Daniel. 2010. “The Relationship of Virtues and Norms in the Summa theologiae.” Heythrop Journal, Vol. 51, No. 2: 214229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dauphinais, Michael, and Levering, Matthew. 2002. Knowing the Love of Christ: An Introduction to the Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Davies, Brian. 1992. The Thought of Thomas Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davies, Brian. 2012a. “Happiness.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, Brian. 2012b. “Prayer.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Decosimo, David. 2014. Ethics as a Work of Charity: Thomas and Pagan Virtue. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Dedek, John. 1979. “Intrinsically Evil Acts: An Historical Study of the Mind of St. Thomas.” The Thomist, Vol. 43, No. 3: 385413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Kirchner, B. Bossi. 1986. “Aquinas as an Interpreter of Aristotle on the End of Human Life.” Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 40: 4154.Google Scholar
De Koninck, Charles. 1943. De la primauté du bien commun contre les personnalistes: Le principe de l’ordre nouveau. Montreal: Fides/Éditions de l’Université Laval, 1943.Google Scholar
De Koninck, Charles. 2009. The Writings of Charles De Koninck. Vol. 2. McInerny, Ralph (ed. and trans.). Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press.Google Scholar
Dell’Olio, Andrew J. 2003. Foundations of Moral Selfhood: Aquinas on Divine Goodness and the Connection of the Virtues. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
De Lubac, Henri. 1946. Surnaturel: Études historiques. Paris: Aubier.Google Scholar
De Lubac, Henri. 2008. “Duplex Hominis Beatitudo (Saint Thomas, 1a 2ae, q. 62, a. 1).” Aaron Riches and Peter Candler, Jr. (trans.). Communio: International Catholic Review, Vol. 35: 599612.Google Scholar
Dewan, Lawrence. 1993. “Truth and Happiness.” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, Vol. 67: 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewan, Lawrence. 2007. Wisdom, Law, and Virtue: Essays in Thomistic Ethics. New York: Fordham University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewart, Leslie. 1966. The Future of Belief: Theism in a World Come of Age. New York: Herder and Herder.Google Scholar
DeYoung, Rebecca Konyndyk, McCluskey, Colleen, and Van Dyke, Christina. 2009. Aquinas’s Ethics: Metaphysical Foundations, Moral Theory, and Theological Context. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Di Blasi, Fulvio. 2021. From Aristotle to Thomas Aquinas: Natural Law, Practical Knowledge, and the Person. South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press.Google Scholar
Di Blasi, Fulvio, Hochschild, Joshua P., and Langan, Jeffrey (eds.). 2008. Virtue’s End: God in the Moral Philosophy of Aristotle and Aquinas. South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press.Google Scholar
Donato, Antonio. 2006. “Aquinas’ Theory of Happiness and Its Greek, Byzantine, Latin, and Arabic Sources.” Al-Masaq: Journal of the Medieval Mediterranean, Vol. 18 (September): 161189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donato, Antonio. 2008. “Contemplation as the End of Human Nature in Aquinas’s Sententia libri Ethicorum” In Di Blasi, Fulvio, Hochschild, Joshua P., and Langan, Jeffrey (eds.), Virtue’s End: God in the Moral Philosophy of Aristotle and Aquinas. South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press.Google Scholar
Doyle, Dominic. 2016. “Is Charity the Holy Spirit? The Development of Aquinas’s Disagreement with Peter Lombard.” In Miner, Robert (ed. and trans.), Questions on Love and Charity: Summa theologiae secunda secundae, Questions 23–46. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press: 313335.Google Scholar
Duba, William Owen. 2006. “Seeing God: Theology, Beatitude and Cognition in the Thirteenth Century.” PhD dissertation, University of Iowa.Google Scholar
Dyson, R. W. 2003. Normative Theories of Society and Government in Five Medieval Thinkers. Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen Press.Google Scholar
Eardley, P. S. 2006. “Conceptions of Happiness and Human Destiny in the Late Thirteenth Century.” Vivarium, Vol. 44, Nos. 2–3: 276304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eilan, Naomi, Hoerl, Christoph, McCormack, Teresa, and Roessler, Johannes. 2005. Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elders, Leo. 2005. The Ethics of St. Thomas Aquinas: Happiness, Natural Law and the Virtues. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Emery, Gilles. 2012. “The Trinity.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Emery, Gilles, and Levering, Matthew (eds.). 2015. Aristotle in Aquinas’s Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, C. Stephen, and Baggett, David. 2022. “Moral Arguments for the Existence of God.” In Edward N. Zalta and Uri Nodelman (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2022 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2022/entries/moral-arguments-god/.Google Scholar
Farrell, Dominic. 2012. The Ends of the Moral Virtues and the First Principles of Practical Reason in Thomas Aquinas. Rome: Gregorian and Biblical Press.Google Scholar
Farrell, Dominic. 2018. “Wanting the Common Good: Aquinas on General Justice.” Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 71, No. 3: 517549.Google Scholar
Feingold, Lawerence. 2010. The Natural Desire to See God According to St. Thomas and His Interpreters (2nd ed.). Ave Maria, FL: Sapientia Press of Ave Maria University.Google Scholar
Feldman, Fred. 2006. Pleasure and the Good Life: Concerning the Nature, Varieties, and Plausibility of Hedonism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Feldman, Fred. 2012. What Is This Thing Called Happiness? Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ferree, William. 1943. The Act of Social Justice: An Analysis of the Thomistic Concept of Legal Justice. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1943.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1983. Fundamentals of Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1998a. Aquinas: Moral, Political and Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, John. 1998b. “Public Good: The Specifically Political Common Good in Aquinas.” In George, Robert P. (ed.), Natural Law and Moral Inquiry: Ethics, Metaphysics, and Politics in the Thought of Germain Grisez. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press: 174209.Google Scholar
Flannery, Kevin L. 2001. Acts amid Precepts: The Aristotelian Logical Structure of Thomas Aquinas’s Moral Theory. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Flannery, Kevin L. 2003. “The Multifarious Moral Object of Thomas Aquinas.” The Thomist, Vol. 67, No. 1: 95118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flannery, Kevin L. 2008. “Can an Aristotelian Consider Himself a Friend of God?” In Di Blasi, Fulvio, Hochschild, Joshua P., and Langan, Jeffrey (eds.), Virtue’s End: God in the Moral Philosophy of Aristotle and Aquinas. South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press.Google Scholar
Fletcher, Guy. 2013. “A Fresh Start for the Objective List Theory of Well-Being.” Utilitas, Vol. 25: 206220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flood, Anthony. 2014. The Root of Friendship: Self-Love and Self-Governance in Aquinas. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flood, Anthony. 2018. The Metaphysical Foundations of Love: Aquinas on Participation, Unity, and Union. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, Phillipa. 1978. “Virtues and Vices.” In Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy. Berkeley: University of California Press: 118.Google Scholar
Foot, Phillipa. 2001. Natural Goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forschner, Maximilian. 1994. Über das Glück des Menschen. Aristoteles. Epikur. Stoa. Thomas von Aquin. Kant. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.Google Scholar
Franks, Christopher. 2009. He Became Poor: The Poverty of Christ and Aquinas’s Economic Teachings. Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Franks, Christopher. 2015. “Aristotelian Doctrines in Aquinas’s Treatment of Justice.” In Emery, Gilles and Levering, Matthew (eds.), Aristotle in Aquinas’s Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frey, Jennifer. 2019a. “Happiness as Constitutive Principle of Action in Thomas Aquinas.” Philosophical Explorations, Vol. 22, No. 2: 208221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frey, Jennifer. 2019b. “Aquinas on Sin, Self-Love, and Self-Transcendence.” In Frey, Jennifer and Vogler, Candace (eds.), Self-Transcendence and Virtue: Perspective from Philosophy, Psychology, and Theology. New York: Routledge: 6283.Google Scholar
Froelich, Gregory. 1989. “The Equivocal Status of Bonum commune.” New Scholasticism, Vol. 63: 3857.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Froelich, Gregory. 1993. “Ultimate End and Common Good.” The Thomist, Vol. 57: 609619.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuchs, Marko. 2013. Philia and Caritas: Some Aspects of Aquinas’s Reception of Aristotle’s Theory of Friendship.” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fuchs, Marko. 2017. Gerechtigkeit als allgemeine Tugend: Die Rezeption der aristotelischen Gerechtigkeitstheorie im Mittelalter und das Problem des ethischen Universalismus. Veröffentlichungen des Grabmann-Institutes zur Erforschung der Mittelalterlichen Theologie und Philosophie, Band 61. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Gaine, Simon Francis. 2015. “Aristotle’s Philosophy in Aquinas’s Theology of Grace in the Summa theologiae.” In Emery, Gilles and Levering, Matthew (eds.), Aristotle in Aquinas’s Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gallagher, David M. 1996. “Desire for Beatitude and Love of Friendship in Thomas Aquinas.” Medieval Studies, Vol. 58: 147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallagher, David M. 1999. “Thomas Aquinas on Self-Love as the Basis for Love of Others.” Acta Philosophica, Vol. 8: 2344.Google Scholar
Gallagher, David M. 2002. “The Will and Its Acts (Ia IIae, qq. 6–17).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Gallagher, David M. 2018. “Aquinas on Goodness and Moral Goodness.” In Gallagher, David (ed.), Thomas Aquinas and His Legacy. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press: 3760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, Patrick M. 2011. “Thomas and Dante on duo ultima hominis.” The Thomist, Vol. 75, No. 3: 415459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geiger, Louis-Bertrand. 1952. Le problème de l’amour chez Saint Thomas d’Aquin. Montreal: Institute d’Études Médiévales.Google Scholar
Gilson, Etienne. 1956. The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas. L. K. Shook (trans.). New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Godfrey of Fontaines. 1904. Les quatres premiers Quodlibets de Godefroid de Fontaines. M. De Wulf and A. Pelzer (eds.).Google Scholar
Godfrey of Fontaines. 1914. Les quodlibets cinq, six et sept. M. De Wulf and J. Hoffmans (eds.).Google Scholar
Godfrey of Fontaines. 1958. “Utrum visio sit principalior in beatitudine.” In Neumann, B. (ed.), Der mensch und die himmlische Seligkeit nach der Lehre Gottfrieds von Fontaines. Limburg/Lahn.Google Scholar
Goodman, Lenn. 2010. “Happiness.” In Pasnau, Robert and Van Dyke, Christina (eds.), The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 457471.Google Scholar
Goodnight, Audra. 2018. “The Confucian Puzzle: Justice and Care in Aquinas.” Comparative Philosophy, Vol. 9, No. 1: 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goyette, John. 2013. “On the Transcendence of the Political Common Good: Aquinas Versus the New Natural Law Theory.” Catholic Bioethics Quarterly, Vol. 13, No. 1 (Spring): 133155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grisez, Germain. 1965. “The First Principle of Practical Reason: A Commentary on the Summa theologiae, 1–2, Question 94, Article 2.” Natural Law Forum, Vol. 10: 168201.Google Scholar
Grisez, Germain. 2001. “Natural Law, God, Religion, and Human Fulfillment.” American Journal of Jurisprudence, Vol. 46: 336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grisez, Germain. 2008. “The True Ultimate End of Human Beings: The Kingdom, Not God Alone.” Theological Studies, Vol. 69: 3861.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grisez, Germain, and Finnis, John. 1981. “The Basic Principles of Natural Law: A Reply to Ralph McInerny.” American Journal of Jurisprudence, Vol. 26: 2131.Google Scholar
Haara, Heikki, and Toivanen, Juhana (eds.). 2024. Common Good and Self-Interest in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hagedorn, Eric. 2019. “From Thomas Aquinas to the 1350s.” In Williams, Thomas (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hain, Raymond. 2015. “Aquinas and Aristotelian Hylomorphism.” In Emery, Gilles and Levering, Matthew (eds.), Aristotle in Aquinas’s Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hall, Pamela. 2002. “The Old Law and the New Law (Ia IIae, qq. 98–108).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, John. 2001. “Scotus on Morality and Nature.” Medieval Philosophy and Theology, Vol. 9: 1538.Google Scholar
Hare, John. 2013. “A Kantian Response to Jean Porter.” Studies in Christian Ethics, Vol. 26, No. 2: 174175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, John. 2015. God’s Command. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, John. 2016. “Kant on Practical and Pathological Love.” In Simmons, Frederick V. and Sorrells, Brian C. (eds.), Love and Christian Ethics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press: 7590.Google Scholar
Hare, John. 2019. “The Merits of Eudaimonism.” Journal of Religious Ethics, Vol. 47, No. 1: 1522.20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harmon, Thomas. 2010. “The Sacramental Consummation of the Moral Life According to St. Thomas Aquinas.” New Blackfriars, Vol. 91, No. 1034 (July): 465480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harms, Arielle. 2014. “Acquired and Infused Moral Virtue: A Distinction of Ends.” New Blackfriars, Vol. 95, No. 1055 (January): 7187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, John C. 1982. “Morality and the Theory of Rational Behavior.” In Sen, Amartya and Williams, Bernard (eds.), Utilitarianism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hause, Jeffery. 2007. “Aquinas on the Function of Moral Virtue.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 81, No. 1: 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hause, Jeffery. 2010. “Introduction.” In Huase, Jeffrey and Murphy, Claudia Eisen (trans.), Disputed Questions on the Virtues. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett .Google Scholar
Hause, Jeffery. 2013. “Aquinas on Aristotelian Justice: Defender, Destroyer, Subverter, or Surveyor?” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Haybron, Dan. 2020. “Happiness.” In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/happiness/.Google Scholar
Healy, Nicholas. 2016. “Redemption.” In McCosker, Philip and Turner, Denys (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to the Summa theologiae. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heathwood, Chris. 2005. “The Problem of Defective Desires.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 4 (December): 487504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heathwood, Chris. 2021. Happiness and Well-Being. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henle, R. J. 1956. Saint Thomas and Platonism: A Study of the Plato and Platonic Texts in the Writings of Saint Thomas. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herdt, Jennifer A. 2013. “Aquinas’s Aristotelian Defense of Martyr Courage.” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hergan, Jeffrey. 2002. St Albert the Great’s Theory of the Beatific Vision. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Hering, Hyazinth. 1944. De iustitia legali. Friburg: Typis Consociationis Sancti Pauli.Google Scholar
Hibbs, Thomas. 2002. “Interpretations of Aquinas’s Ethics Since Vatican II.” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Hoenen, Maarten J. F. M. 2002. “Tranzendenz der Einheit: Thomas von Aquin über Liebe und Freundschaft.” In Wieland, Georg, Dietl, Cora, and Helschinger, Dörte (eds.), Ars und Scientia im Mittelalter und in der Frühen Neuzeit. Tübingen: Francke.Google Scholar
Hoffmann, Tobias. 2003. “Moral Action as Human Action: End and Object in Aquinas in Comparison with Abelard, Lombard, Albert, and Scotus.” The Thomist, Vol. 67, No. 1: 7394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmann, Tobias. 2012a. “Conscience and Synderesis.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hoffmann, Tobias. 2012b. “The Intellectual Virtues.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hoffmann, Tobias. 2013. “Prudence and Practical Principles.” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias. 2013. “Introduction.” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoipkemier, Mark. 2016. “Law and Friendship: Aquinas and Aristotle on the Virtue of the Common Good.” Archivio di Filosofia, Vol. 84, Nos. 1–2: 4354.Google Scholar
Holtz, Dominic. 2012. “Sacraments.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Homiak, Marcia. 2007. “An Aristotelian Life.” In Antony, Louise M. (ed.), Philosophers Without Gods: Meditations on Atheism and the Secular Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Horner, David A. 2006. “Is Aquinas an Act-Ethicist or an Agent-Ethicist?The Thomist, Vol. 70, No. 2: 237265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Houser, R.E. 2002. “The Virtue of Courage (IIa IIae, qq. 123–140.” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Hoye, W. J. 1975. Actualitas Omnium Actuum. Man’s Beatific Vision of God as Apprehended by Thomas Aquinas. Monographien zur philosophischen Forschung 116. Meisenheim am Glan: Anton Hain Verlag.Google Scholar
Huber, S. 1893. Die Glückseligkeitslehre des Aristoteles und hl. Thomas v. A. Ein historisch-kritischer Vergleich. Freising: Dr. Franz Paul Datterer, Buchdruckerei.Google Scholar
Hughes, Julie Lund. 2004. “The Role of Happiness in Kant’s Ethics.” Aporia, Vol. 14, No. 1: 6172.Google Scholar
Hughes, Louis. 1975. “Charity as Friendship in the Theology of Saint Thomas.” Angelicum, Vol. 52: 164178.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 1993. Perfectionism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2006. “Virtuous Act, Virtuous Dispositions.” Analysis, Vol. 66, No. 289: 6976.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hursthouse, Rosalind, and Pettigrove, Glen. 2023. “Virtue Ethics.” In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2023 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2023/entries/ethics-virtue/.Google Scholar
Inglis, John. 1999. “Aquinas’s Replication of the Acquired Moral Virtues: Rethinking the Standard Philosophical Interpretation of Moral Virtue in Aquinas.” Journal of Religious Ethics, Vol. 27, No. 1: 327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, Terence. 2007. The Development of Ethics: A Historical and Critical Study, Vol. 1: From Socrates to the Reformation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. H. 1985. “Permanent Happiness: Aristotle and Solon.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 3: 89124.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. H. 2005. “Do Virtues Conflict? Aquinas’s Answer.” In Gardiner, Stephen Mark (ed.), Virtue Ethics, Old and New. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. H. 2013. “Historical Accuracy in Aquinas’s Commentary on the Ethics.” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Janssens, Louis. 1982. “Saint Thomas Aquinas and the Question of Proportionality.” Louvain Studies, Vol. 9, No. 1: 2646.Google Scholar
Jenkins, John I. 1997. Knowledge and Faith in Thomas Aquinas. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jensen, Steve. 2010. Good and Evil Actions: A Journey Through Saint Thomas Aquinas. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Jensen, Steve. 2015. Knowing the Natural Law: From Precepts and Inclinations to Deriving Oughts. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scotus, John Duns. 1891–95. Opera omnia. Paris: Vivès.Google Scholar
Scotus, John Duns. 1950–. Opera omnia. Balic, C. et al. (eds.). Vatican City: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis.Google Scholar
Pecham, John. 1989. Quodlibeta quatuor. Etzkorn, G. J. and Delorme, F. M. (eds.). Grottaferrata: Editiones Collegii S. Bonaventurae.Google Scholar
Johnson, Robert, and Cureton, Adam. 2022. “Kant’s Moral Philosophy.” In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2022 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2022/entries/kant-moral/.Google Scholar
Jones, L. Gregory. 1987. “The Theological Transformation of Aristotelian Friendship in the Thought of St. Thomas Aquinas.” New Scholasticism, Vol. 61: 373399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, Mark. 1999. “Ideals of Scientia moralis and the Invention of the Summa theologiae.” In MacDonald, Scott and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), Aquinas’s Moral Theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press: 7997.Google Scholar
de Salas, Juan. 1607. Disputationum in primam secundae Divi Thomae, Vol. 1. Barcelona: Ex Officina Gabrielis Graelis, et Gerardi Dotil.Google Scholar
Kaczor, C., and Sherman, T.. 2009. Thomas Aquinas on the Cardinal Virtues. Naples, FL: Saptientia Press of Ave Maria University.Google Scholar
Kagan, Shelly. 2009. “Well-Being as Enjoying the Good.” Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 23, No. 1: 253272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keenan, James. 2002. “The Virtue of Prudence (IIa IIae, qq. 47–56)” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Keenan, James. 2016. “Virtues.” In McCloskey, Philip and Turner, Denys (eds.), Cambridge Companion to the Summa theologiae. New York: Cambridge University Press: 194205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, M.-Joseph, and Lavaud, M.-Benoît. 1929. “La charité comme amitié d’après saint Thomas.” Revue thomiste, Vol. 34: 445475.Google Scholar
Kempshall, M. S. 1999. The Common Good in Late Medieval Political Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenny, Anthony. 1999. “Aquinas on Aristotelian Happiness.” In MacDonald, Scott and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), Aquinas’s Moral Theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press: 1527.Google Scholar
Kent, Bonnie. 1989. “Transitory Vice: Thomas Aquinas on Incontinence.” Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. 27 (April): 199223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kent, Bonnie. 1994. “Moral Provincialism.” Religious Studies, Vol. 30: 269285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kent, Bonnie. 1995. Virtues of the Will: The Transformation of Ethics in the Late Thirteenth Century. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Kent, Bonnie. 2002. “Habits and Virtues.” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press: 116130.Google Scholar
Kent, Bonnie. 2003. “The Moral Life.” In McGrade, A. S. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press: 231253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kent, Bonnie. 2012. “Dispositions and Moral Fallibility: The UnAristotelian Aquinas.” History of Philosophy Quarterly, Vol. 29, No. 2: 141157.Google Scholar
Kent, Bonnie. 2013. “Losable Virtue: Aquinas on Character and Will.” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 91109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kerr, Fergus. 1987. “Charity as Friendship.” In Davies, Brian (ed.), Language, Meaning, and God. London: Geoffrey Chapman: 123.Google Scholar
Kerr, Fergus. 2002. After Aquinas: Versions of Thomism. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keys, Mary. 1995. “Personal Dignity and the Common Good: A Twentieth-Century Thomistic Dialogue.” In Grasso, Kenneth, Bradley, Gerard, and Hunt, Robert (eds.), Catholicism, Liberalism, and Communitarianism: The Catholic Intellectual Tradition and the Moral Foundations of Democracy. London: Rowman & Littlefield: 173195.Google Scholar
Keys, Mary. 2008. Aquinas, Aristotle, and the Promise of the Common Good. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kim, Andrew James. 2013. “Thomas Aquinas on the Connection of the Virtues.” Catholic University of America. http://hdl.handle.net/1961/14397.Google Scholar
King, Peter. 1999. “Aquinas on the Passions.” In MacDonald, Scott and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), Aquinas’s Moral Theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press: 101132.Google Scholar
King, Peter. 2012. “Aquinas on the Emotions.” In Davis, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 209226.Google Scholar
Kitanov, Severin Valentinov. 2014. Beatific Enjoyment in Medieval Scholastic Debates: The Complex Legacy of Saint Augustine and Peter Lombard. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Kleber, Hermann. 1988. Glück als Lebensziel. Untersuchungen zur Philosophie des Glücks bei Thomas von Aquin (2nd ed.). Münster: Aschendort.Google Scholar
Kluxen, Wolfgang. 1978. “Glück und Glücksteilhabe: Zur Rezeption der Aristotelischen Glückslehre bei Thomas von Aquin.” In Bien, Günther (ed.), Die Frage nach dem Glück. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog.Google Scholar
Knobel, Angela McKay. 2021. Aquinas and the Infused Moral Virtues. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kobusch, Theo. 2002. “Grace (Ia IIae, qq. 109–114).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Koehn, D., and Wilbratte, B.. 2012. “A Defense of a Thomistic Concept of the Just Price.” Business Ethics Quaterly, Vol. 22, No. 3: 501526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kossel, Clifford. 2002. “Natural Law and Human Law (IaIIae, qq. 90–97).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Krause, Katja. 2013. “Albert and Aquinas on the Ultimate End of Humans: Philosophy, Theology, and Beatitude.” Proceedings of the ACPA, Vol. 86: 213229.Google Scholar
Krause, Katja. 2014. “Aquinas’ Philosophy of the Beatific Vision: A Textual Analysis of his Commentary on the Sentences in Light of its Greek, Arabic, and Latin Sources.” PhD dissertation, King’s College London.Google Scholar
Krause, Katja. 2015. “Remodelling Ultimate Human Happiness: Thomas Aquinas’ Commentary on the Sentences and His Sources.” Divus Thomas, Vol. 118: 1556.Google Scholar
Kraut, Richard. 2020. “Altruism.” In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/altruism/.Google Scholar
Kraut, Richard. 1989. Aristotle on the Human Good. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman, and Stump, Eleonore. 1981. “Eternity.” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 78, No. 8 (August): 429458.Google Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman, and Stump, Eleonore. 2018. “Being and Goodness.” In MacDonald, Scott (ed.), Being and Goodness: The Concept of the Good in Metaphysics and Philosophical Theology. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Kries, Douglas. 1990. “Thomas Aquinas and the Politics of Moses.” Review of Politics, Vol. 52: 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lambertini, Roberto. 2008. “Political Prudence in Some Medieval Commentaries on the Sixth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics.” In Bejczy, István Pieter (ed.), Virtue Ethics in the Middle Ages: Commentaries on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, 1200–1500. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Langan, J. P. 1977. “Beatitude and Moral Law in St. Thomas.” Journal of Religious Ethics, Vol. 5: 183195.Google Scholar
Langan, John. 1991. “Egoism and Morality in the Theological Teleology of Thomas Aquinas.” Journal of Philosophical Research, Vol. 16: 411426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langholm, O. 1992. Economics in the Medieval Schools: Wealth, Exchange, Value, Money, and Usury According to the Paris Theological Tradition, 1200–1350. New York: E. J. Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lapidus, A. 1994. “Norm, Virtue and Information: The Just Price and Individual Behaviour in Thomas Aquinas’ Summa theologiae.” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, Vol. 1, No. 3: 435473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
LeBar, Mark. 2017. “Eudaimonism.” In Snow, Nancy E. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lee, Patrick. 1981. “Permanence of the Ten Commandments: St Thomas and His Modern Commentators.” Theological Studies, Vol. 42, No. 3: 422443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leonhardt, Rochus. 1998. Glück als Vollendung des Menschseins: Die Beatitudo-Lehre des Thomas von Aquin im Horizont des Eudämonismus-Problems. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lerner, Robert E. 1972. The Heresy of the Free Spirit in the Later Middle Ages. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levering, Matthew. 2015. “Aristotle and the Mosaic Law.” In Emery, Gilles and Levering, Matthew (eds.), Aristotle in Aquinas’s Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lisska, Anthony J. 1998. Aquinas’s Theory of Natural Law: An Analytic Reconstruction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Long, Steven. 2000. “On the Possibility of a Purely Natural End for Man.” The Thomist, Vol. 64: 211237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
López, T. J. 2012. “Trichotomizing the Standard Twofold Model of Thomistic Eudaimonism.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 86, No. 1: 2346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
López, T. J. 2015. “Aquinas on the Infused Virtues and Human Happiness: A Preliminary Study.” In Goris, Harm, Hendriks, Lambert, and Schoot, Henk (eds.), Faith, Hope and Love: Thomas Aquinas on Living by the Theological Virtues. Leuven: Peeters: 91105.Google Scholar
Lottin, Odon. 1948. “La loi en general: La definition thomiste et ses antécédents.” In Pscyhologie et morale aux XIIe et XIIIe siècles, Vol. 2: Problèmes de morale, 1e partie. Louvain: Abbaye du Mont César: 1147.Google Scholar
Lottin, Odon. 1950. “La valeur des formules de Saint Thomas d’Aquin concernant la loi naturelle.” In Mélanges Joseph Maréchal, Vol. 2. Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1950: 345377.Google Scholar
Lynch, Reginald. 2017. The Cleansing of the Heart: The Sacraments as Instrumental Causes in the Thomistic Tradition. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacDonald, Scott. 1990. “Egoistic Rationalism: Aquinas’s Basis for Christian Morality.” In Beaty, Michael (ed.), Christian Theism and the Problems of Philosophy. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
MacDonald, Scott. 1991. “Ultimate Ends in Practical Reasoning.” Philosophical Review, Vol. 100: 3166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacDonald, Scott. 1992. “Goodness as Transcendental: The Early Thirteenth-Century Recovery of an Aristotelian Idea.” Topoi: An International Review of Philosophy, Vol. 11, No. 2 (September): 173186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacDonald, Scott. 1999. “Practical Reasoning and Reasons-Explanations: Aquinas’s Account of Reason’s Role in Action.” In MacDonald, Scott and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), Aquinas’s Moral Theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press: 133159.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1984. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (2nd ed.). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1988. Whose Justice? Which Rationality? Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Mansini, Guy. 2015. “Aristotle and Aquinas’s Theology of Charity in the Summa theologiae.” In Emery, Gilles and Levering, Matthew (eds.), Aristotle in Aquinas’s Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Maritain, Jacques. 1940. Science and Wisdom. Bernard Wall (trans.). London: Geoffrey Bles.Google Scholar
Maritain, Jacques. 1947a. Le Personne et le bien commun. Paris: Desclée de Brouwer.Google Scholar
Maritain, Jacques. 1947b. The Person and the Common Good. John Fitzgerald (trans.). New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.Google Scholar
Maritain, Jacques. 1955. An Essay on Christian Philosophy. Edward H. Flannery (trans.). New York: Philosophical Library.Google Scholar
Maritain, Jacques. 1956. The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas. L. K. Shook (trans.). New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Maritain, Jacques. 1964. Moral Philosophy: An Historical and Critical Survey of the Great Systems. Evans, Joseph W. (ed.). London: Geoffrey Bles.Google Scholar
Martins, António Rocha. 2023. “The Secretum secretorum and the Idea of Political Happiness in the Latin Middle Ages.” In Brinzei, Monica, Curut, Ioana, Coman, Daniel, and Marinca, Andrei (eds.), Pseudo-Aristotelian Texts in Medieval Thought. Turnhout: Brepols.Google Scholar
Marty, F. 1962. La perfection de l’homme selon saint Thomas d’Aquin: Ses fondaments ontologiques et leur verification dans l’ordre actuel. Rome: Gregorian University Press.Google Scholar
Mattison, William C., III. 2010. “Thomas’s Categorizations of Virtue: Historical Background and Contemporary Significance.” The Thomist, Vol. 74, No. 2: 189235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
May, William 1984. “Aquinas and Janssens on the Moral Meaning of Human Acts.” The Thomist, Vol. 48, No. 4: 566606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCabe, Herbert. 2008. On Aquinas. Davies, Brian (ed.). London: Burns & Oates.Google Scholar
McCluskey, Colleen. 2000. “Happiness and Freedom in Aquinas’s Theory of Action.” Medieval Philosophy and Theology, Vol. 9, No. 1: 6990.Google Scholar
McCluskey, Colleen. 2016. Thomas Aquinas on Moral Wrongdoing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCosker, Philip. 2016. “Grace.” In McCosker, Philip and Turner, Denys (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to the Summa theologiae. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 206221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McInerny, Daniel. 2006. The Difficult Good: A Thomistic Approach to Moral Conflict and Human Happiness. New York: Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
McInerny, Ralph. 1980. “The Principles of Natural Law.” American Journal of Jurisprudence, Vol. 25: 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McInerny, Ralph. 1992. Aquinas on Human Action: A Theory of Practice. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
McInerny, Ralph. 1997. Ethica Thomistica: The Moral Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas (revised ed.). Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
McInerny, Ralph. 2003. Aquinas. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.Google Scholar
McInerny, Ralph, and O’Callaghan, John. 2005. “Saint Thomas Aquinas.” In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2005 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2005/entries/aquinas/.Google Scholar
Milhaven, John. 1968. “Moral Absolutes in Thomas Aquinas.” In Curran, Charles (ed.), Absolutes in Moral Theology? Washington, DC: Corpus: 154185.Google Scholar
Miner, Robert. 2000. “Non-Aristotelian Prudence in the Prima secundae.” The Thomist, Vol. 64, No. 3: 401422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miner, Robert. 2009. Thomas Aquinas on the Passions: A Study of Summa theologiae 1a2ae, 22–48. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miner, Robert. 2016. “Disagreeing in Charity: Learning from Thomas Aquinas.” In Miner, Robert (ed. and trans.), Questions on Love and Charity: Summa theologiae secunda secundae Questions 23–46. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press: 299312.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Timothy. 1983. Hedonism and Eudemonism in Aquinas – Not the Same as Happiness. Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press.Google Scholar
Müller, Jörn. 2001. Natürliche Moral und philosophische Ethik bei Albertus Magnus. Münster: Aschendorff.Google Scholar
Müller, Jörn. 2008. “In War and Peace: The Virtue of Courage in the Writings of Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas.” In Bejczy, István (ed.), Virtue Ethics in the Middle Ages: Commentaries on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, 1200–1500. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Müller, Jörn. 2013. “Duplex Beatitudo: Aristotle’s Legacy and Aquinas’s Conception of Human Happiness.” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 5271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muñoz Cuenca, J.-M. 1974. “Doctrina de santo Tomás sobre los Dones del Espíritu Santo en la Suma teológica.” Ephemerides carmeliticae, Vol. 25: 157243.Google Scholar
Murphy, Mark. 1997. “Consent, Custom, and the Common Good in Aquinas’s Account of Political Authority.” Review of Politics, Vol. 59: 323350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, Mark. 2001. Natural Law and Practical Rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Murphy, Mark. 2005. “The Common Good.” Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 59, No. 1 (September): 133164.Google Scholar
Nederman, Cary J. 1996. “The Meaning of Aristotelianism in Medieval Moral and Political Thought.” Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 57, No. 4 (October): 563586.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, Daniel Mark. 1992. The Priority of Prudence: Virtue and Natural Law in Thomas Aquinas and the Implications for Modern Ethics. University Park: Penn State University Press.Google Scholar
Newman, Jeremiah. 1954. Foundations of Justice: A Historico-Critical Study of Thomism. Cork: Cork University Press.Google Scholar
Normore, Calvin. 2024. “Honestum to Goodness.” In Haara, Heikki and Toivanen, Juhana (eds.), Common Good and Self-Interest in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Novak, Joseph. 1995. “Aquinas on Aristotle: Ethical Eudaimonism or Biblical Blessedness?” In Andujar, E., Bazan, B. C., and Sbrocchi, L. G. (eds.), Les Philosophes Morales et Politiques au Moyen Âge: actes du IXe Congrès international de Philosophie Médiévale, Vol. 1. New York: Legas: 429442.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2001. The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy (revised ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nygren, Anders. 1953. Agape and Eros. Philip Watson (trans.). London: SPCK.Google Scholar
O’Connor, D. J. 1967. Aquinas and Natural Law. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Connor, Edward. 1973. “The Evolution of St. Thomas’ Thought on the Gifts.” In O’Connor, Edward (ed. and trans.), Summa theologiae, Vol. 24. New York: McGraw-Hill: Appendix 4: 110130.Google Scholar
Oliva, Adriano. 2012. “La Contemplation des Philosophes selon Thomas d’Aquin.” Revue des sciences philosophiques et théologiques, Vol. 96: 585662.Google Scholar
Olver, Jordan. 2017. Bonum nostrum: Thomas Aquinas and Love of Others for Τheir Οwn Sake.” Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 70 (June): 663694.Google Scholar
O’Neil, Charles J. 1955. Imprudence in St. Thomas Aquinas. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Osborne, Thomas, Jr. 2003. “The Augustinianism of Thomas Aquinas’s Moral Theory.” The Thomist, Vol. 67, No. 2: 279305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Osborne, Thomas, 2005. Love of Self and Love of God: In Thirteenth-Century Ethics. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Osborne, Thomas, 2008. “The Threefold Referral of Acts to the Ultimate End in Thomas Aquinas and His Commentators.” Angelicum, Vol. 85, No. 3: 715736.Google Scholar
Osborne, Thomas, 2011. “Thomas Aquinas and John Duns Scotus on Individual Acts and the Ultimate End.” In Emery, Kent, Jr., Friedman, Russell L. and Speer, Andreas (eds.), Philosophy and Theology in the Long Middle Ages: A Tribute to Stephen F. Brown. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Osborne, Thomas, 2014. Human Action in Thomas Aquinas, John Duns Scotus, and William of Ockham. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Osborne, Thomas, 2019. “Virtue.” In Williams, Thomas (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Osborne, Thomas, 2020. Aquinas’s Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Osborne, Thomas, 2022. Thomas Aquinas on Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owens, Joseph. 1974. “Aquinas as Aristotelian Commentator.” In Maurer, A. (ed.), St. Thomas Aquinas, 1274–1974: Commemorative Studies. Toronto: PIMS: 213238.Google Scholar
Pakaluk, Michael. 2001. “Is the Common Good of Political Society Limited and Instrumental?Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 55, No. 1: 5794.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Pasnau, Robert. 2002. Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature: A Philosophical Study of Summa theologiae Ia 75–89. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pasnau, Robert. 2017. After Certainty: A History of Our Epistemic Ideals and Illusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pasnau, Robert, and Shields, Christopher. 2016. The Philosophy of Aquinas (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pegis, Anton. 1949. “Nature and Spirit: Some Reflections on the Problem of the End of Man.” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, Vol. 23: 6279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perkams, Matthias. 2008. “Aquinas’s Interpretation of the Aristotelian Virtue of Justice and His Doctrine of Natural Law.” In Bejczy, István (ed.), Virtue Ethics in the Middle Ages: Commentaries on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, 1200–1500. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Peter, C. J. 1964. Participated Eternity in the Vision of God: A Study of the Opinion of St. Thomas Aquinas and His Commentators on the Duration of the Acts of Glory. Rome: Gregorian University Press.Google Scholar
Pickavé, Martin. 2013. “Aquinas on Incontinence and Psychological Weakness.” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 184202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pilsner, Joseph. 2006. The Specification of Human Actions in St. Thomas Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinckaers, Servais. 1963a. “Der Sinn für die Freundschaftsliebe als Urtatsache der thomistischen Ethik.” In Engelhardt, Paulus (ed.), Sein und Ethos: Untersuchungen zur Grundlegung der Ethik. Mainz: Matthias-Grünwald-Verlag: 228235.Google Scholar
Pinckaers, Servais. 1963b. “Eudämonismus und sittliche Verbindlichkeit in der Ethik des heiligen Thomas: Stellungnahme zum Beitrag Hans Reiners.” In Engelhardt, Paulus (ed.), Sein und Ethos: Untersuchungen zur Grundlegung der Ethik. Mainz: Matthias-Grünwald-Verlag: 267305.Google Scholar
Pinckaers, Servais. 1991. “L’instinct et l’esprit au coeur de l’éthique chrétienne.” In Pinto de Oliveira, Carlos-Josaphat (ed.), Novitas et veritas vitae: Aux sources du renouveau de la morale chrétienne, mélanges offerts au professeur Servais Pinckaers à l’occasion de son 65e anniversaire. Fribourg: Editions universitaires Fribourg: 216223.Google Scholar
Pinckaers, Servais. 2002. “The Sources of the Ethics of St. Thomas Aquinas.” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Pinckaers, Servais. 2005a. “Aquinas’s Pursuit of Beatitude: From the Commentary on the Sentences to the Summa theologiae.” In The Pinckaers Reader: Renewing Thomistic Moral Theology, Berkman, John and Titus, Craig Steven (eds.), Mary Thomas Noble, Craig Steven Titus, Michael Sherwin, and Hugh Connolly (trans.). Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Pinckaers, Servais. 2005b. “Beatitude and the Beatitudes in Aquinas’s Summa theologiae.” In The Pinckaers Reader: Renewing Thomistic Moral Theology, Berkman, John and Titus, Craig Steven (eds.), Mary Thomas Noble, Craig Steven Titus, Michael Sherwin, and Hugh Connolly (trans.). Washington DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Pini, Giorgio. 2012. “The Development of Aquinas’s Thought.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 491510.Google Scholar
Pinsent, Andrew. 2012a. “The Gifts and the Fruits of the Holy Spirit.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 475490.Google Scholar
Pinsent, Andrew. 2012b. The Second-Person Perspective in Aquinas’s Ethics: Virtues and Gifts. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 1990. The Recovery of Virtue: The Relevance of Aquinas for Christian Ethics. Louisville, KY: John Knox Press.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 1993. “The Unity of the Virtues and the Ambiguity of Goodness: A Reappraisal of Aquinas’s Theory of Virtues.” Journal of Religious Ethics, Vol. 21, No. 1: 137163.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 1999. Natural and Divine Law: Reclaiming the Tradition for Christian Ethics. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2002. “The Virtue of Justice (IIa IIae, qq. 58–122).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2005a. Nature as Reason: A Thomistic Theory of the Natural Law. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2005b. “The Common Good in Thomas Aquinas.” In Miller, Patrick and McCann, Dennis (eds.), In Search of the Common Good. London: T&T Clark: 94120.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2009. “Does the Natural Law Provide a Universally Valid Morality?” In Cunningham, Lawrence (ed.), Intractable Disputes About the Natural Law. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2012. “Virtues and Vices.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2013. “The Natural Law and the Normative Significance of Nature.” Studies in Christian Ethics, Vol. 26, No. 2: 166173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2014. “The Desire for Happiness and the Virtues of the Will.” Journal of Moral Theology, Vol. 3, No. 1: 1838.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2016a. “Happiness.” In Turner, Denys and McCosker, Philip (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to the Summa theologiae. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2016b. Justice as a Virtue: A Thomistic Perspective. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2019a. “Law.” In Williams, Thomas (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Porter, Jean. 2019b. “Eudaimonism and Christian Ethics: A Scriptural Perspective.” Journal of Religious Ethics. Vol. 47, No. 1: 2342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, Peter. 2003. Facts, Values, and Norms: Essays Toward a Morality of Consequence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ramírez, Jacobus M. 1936. “De philosophia morali Christiani.” Divus Thomas, Vol. 14: 87204.Google Scholar
Ramírez, Jacobus M. 1972. De hominis beatitudine: In I–II Summae theologiae divi Thomae commentaria (qq. I–v). Vol. 3 of Opera omnia. Rodriguez, Victorino (ed.). Madrid: Consejo Suerior de Investigaciones Cientificas.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice (revised ed.). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichberg, Gregory. 2002. “The Intellectual Virtues (Ia IIae, qq. 57–58). In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Reiner, Hans. 1963. “Beatitudo und obligatio bei Thomas von Aquin: Antwort an P. Pinckaers.” In Engelhardt, Paulus (ed.), Sein und Ethos: Untersuchungen zur Grundlegung der Ethik. Mainz: Matthias-Grünwald-Verlag: 306328.Google Scholar
Rhonheimer, Martin. 2002. “Sins Against Justice (IIa IIae, qq. 59–78).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Rhonheimer, Martin. 2013. The Perspective of Morality: Philosophical Foundations of Thomistic Virtue Ethics. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richard of Middleton. 1591. Super IV libros Sententiarum Petri Lombardi quaestiones subtillissimae. Brescia. (Reprint, Frankfurt: Minerva, 1963.)Google Scholar
Roniger, Scott. 2018. “Do Friends Need Justice or Do They Just Need Friendship? Natural Law as the Foundation for Justice and Friendship.” Lex Naturalis, Vol. 3: 5784.Google Scholar
Roniger, Scott. 2019. “Natural Law and Friendship with God.” The Thomist, Vol. 83: 237276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roniger, Scott. 2020. “Is There a Punishment for Violating the Natural Law?American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 94: 273304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rousselot, Pierre. 1908. Pour l’histoire du probleme de l’amour au Moyen Age. Münster.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1945. A History of Western Philosophy. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Rziha, John. 2009. Perfecting Human Actions: St. Thomas Aquinas on Human Participation in Eternal Law. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Saarinen, Risto. 2003. “The Parts of Prudence: Buridan, Odonis, Aquinas.” Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review/Revue Canadienne de Philosophie, Vol. 42, No. 4 (October): 749766.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saccenti, Riccardo. 2016. Debating Medieval Natural Law: A Survey. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saemi, Amir. 2018. “The Morally Difficult Notion of Heaven: A Critique of the Faith-Based Ethics of Avicenna and Aquinas.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 92, No. 3 (Summer): 429444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Santori, Paolo. 2020. “Donum, Exchange and Common Good in Aquinas: The Dawn of Civil Economy.” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, Vol. 27, No. 2: 276297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Santurri, Edmund. 1991. “Response to Langan’s ‘Egoism and Morality in the Theological Teleology of Thomas Aquinas.’” Journal of Philosophical Research, Vol. 16: 427430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schneewind, J. B. 1984. “The Divine Corporation and the History of Ethics.” In Rorty, Richard, Schneewind, J. B., and Skinner, Quentin (eds.), Philosophy in History: Essays on the Historiography of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984.Google Scholar
Schockenhoff, Eberhard. 2002. “The Theological Virtue of Charity (IIa IIae, qq. 23–46).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Schwartz, Daniel. 2007. Aquinas on Friendship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seipel, Peter. 2015. “Aquinas and the Natural Law.” Journal of Religious Ethics. Vol. 43, No. 1: 2850.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shanley, Brian. 1999. “Aquinas on Pagan Virtue.” The Thomist, Vol. 63: 553577.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sherwin, Michael. 1993. “St. Thomas Aquinas and the Common Good: The Theological Perspective: An Invitation to Dialogue,” Angelicum, Vol. 70: 307328.Google Scholar
Sherwin, Michael. 2010. “Happiness and Its Discontents.” Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture, Vol. 13, No. 14 (Fall): 3559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sherwin, Michael. 2011. By Knowledge and by Love: Charity and Knowledge in the Moral Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Shields, Christopher, and Pasnau, Robert. 2016. The Philosophy of Aquinas (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, Daniel. 2014. “On Ultimate Ends: Aquinas’s Thesis That Loving God Is Better than Knowing Him.” The Thomist, Vol. 78: 581607.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, Daniel. 2016. “St. Bonaventure, St. Thomas, and Eudaimonism.” In Dumsday, Travis (ed.), The Wisdom of Youth: Essays Inspired by the Early Work of Jacques and Raïssa Maritain. Washington, DC: American Maritain Association: 329343.Google Scholar
Shields, Daniel. 2017. “Aquinas on Will, Happiness, and God: The Problem of Love and Aristotle’s Liber de Bona Fortuna.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 91: 113142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommers, Mary Catherine. 2015. “Contemplation and Action in Aristotle and Aquinas.” In Emery, Gilles and Levering, Matthew (eds.), Aristotle in Aquinas’s Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Spezzano, Daria. 2015. The Glory of God’s Grace: Deification According to St. Thomas Aquinas. Ave Maria, FL: Sapientia Press.Google Scholar
Staley, Kevin. 1989. “Happiness: The Natural End of Man?The Thomist, Vol. 53, No. 2: 215234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stancato, Gianmarco. 2011. Le concept de désir dans l’oeuvre de Thomas d’Aquin. Paris: J.Vrin.Google Scholar
Steele, Jeff. 2019. “Happiness.” In Williams, Thomas (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stenberg, Joseph. 2016a. “Aquinas on the Relationship between the Vision and Delight in Perfect Happiness.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 90, No. 4 (Fall): 665680.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stenberg, Joseph. 2016b. “Considerandum est quid sit beatitudo”: Aquinas on What Happiness Really Is.” Res philosophica, Vol. 93, No. 1: 161184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stenberg, Joseph. 2017. “Entirely Necessary, but not a Part: Aquinas on Virtue and Perfect Happiness.” Recherches de théologie et philosophie médiévales, Vol. 84, No. 1: 75105.Google Scholar
Stenberg, Joseph. 2024. “Buridan on Happiness and the Good Life.” In Lagerlund, Henrik and Johnston, Spencer (eds.), Interpreting Buridan: Critical Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stöpfgeschoff, Alexander. 2018. “The Structure of the Virtues: A Study of Thomas Aquinas’s and Godfrey of Fontaines’s Accounts of Moral Goodness.” PhD dissertation, Uppsala University.Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore. 1999. “Wisdom: Will, Belief, and Moral Goodness.” In MacDonald, Scott and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), Aquinas’s Moral Theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press: 2862.Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore. 2004. “Aquinas’s Virtue Ethics and Its Metaphysical Foundation.” In Szaif, Jan and Lutz-Bachmann, Matthias (eds.), Was ist das für den Menschen Gute? Menschliche Natur and Güterlehre/What Is Good for a Human Being? Human Nature and Values. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter: 209228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, Eleonore. 2005. Aquinas. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore. 2010. Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, Eleonore. 2011. “The Non-Aristotelian Character of Aquinas’s Ethics: Aquinas on the Passions.” Faith and Philosophy, Vol. 28, No. 1: 2943.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, Eleonore. 2018. Atonement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, Eleonore. 2019. “Aquinas’s Ethics: The Infused Virtues and the Indwelling of the Holy Spirit.” Ephemerides theologicae lovanienses, Vol. 95, No. 2: 269281.Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore. 2022. The Image of God: The Problem of Evil and the Problem of Mourning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suárez, Francisco. 1856. Opera omnia, Vol. 4. André, D. M. (ed.). Paris: Apud Ludovicum Vivès.Google Scholar
Taylor, Richard. 2012. “Aquinas and ‘the Arabs’: Arabic/Islamic Philosophy in Thomas Aquinas’ Conception of the Beatific Vision in His Commentary on the Sentences IV, 49, 2, 1.” The Thomist, Vol. 76: 509550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Timpe, Kevin, and Stump, Eleonore (eds.). 2009. Metaphysics and God: Essays in Honor of Eleonore Stump. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toivanen, Juhana. 2024. “Is Socrates Permitted to Kill Plato?” In Haara, Heikki and Toivanen, Juhana (eds.), Common Good and Self-Interest in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Toner, Christopher. 2006. “The Self-Centredness Objection to Virtue Ethics.” Philosophy, Vol. 81, No. 318 (October): 595617.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toner, Christopher. 2007. “Was Aquinas an Egoist?The Thomist, Vol. 71, No. 4: 577608.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Torrell, Jean-Pierre. 2005. Saint Thomas Aquinas: The Person and His Work. Vol. 1. Robert Royal (trans.). Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Trabbic, Joseph. 2011. “The Human Body and Human Happiness in Aquinas’s ‘Summa theologiae.’” New Blackfriars, Vol. 92, No. 1041: 552564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, Denys. 2013. Thomas Aquinas: A Portrait. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Vander Marck, William. 1976. “Ethics as a Key to Aquinas’s Theology.” Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review, Vol. 40 (October): 535554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Dyke, Christina. 2014a. “Aquinas’s Shiny Happy People: Perfect Happiness and the Limits of Human Nature.” Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 6: 269291.Google Scholar
Van Dyke, Christina. 2014b. “I See Dead People: Disembodied Souls and Aquinas’s ‘Two-Person’ Problem.” Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy, Vol. 2: 2545.Google Scholar
Van Nieuwenhove, Rik. 2012. “The Saving Work of Christ.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Van Nieuwenhove, Rik. 2017. “Contemplation, intellectus, and simplex intuitus in Aquinas: Recovering a Neoplatonic Theme.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 91, No. 2 (Spring): 199225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Nieuwenhove, Rik. 2021. Thomas Aquinas and Contemplation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vásquez, Gabriel. 1614. Commentariorum, ac disputationum in primam secundae S. Thomae (2nd ed.), Vol. 1. Alcalá de Henares: Ex officina Ioannis Gratiani apud viduam.Google Scholar
Velde, Rudi te. 2006. Aquinas on God: The “Divine Science” of the Summa theologiae. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Venard, Olivier-Thomas. 2016. “Sacraments.” In McCosker, Philip and Turner, Denys (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to the Summa theologiae. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Verner, Dominic. 2023. “For the Sake of Ourself: Eudaimonism, Friendship, and the Problem of Proprietary Beatitude.” Studies in Christian Ethics. Vol. 36, No. 3: 582603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogler, Candace. 2013. “Aristotle, Aquinas, Anscombe, and the New Virtue Ethics.” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wadell, Paul. 1991. Friends of God: Virtues and Gifts in Aquinas. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Wadell, Paul. 2009. The Primacy of Love: An Introduction to the Ethics of Thomas Aquinas (reprint ed.). Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock.Google Scholar
Wang, Stephen. 2009. Aquinas and Sartre on Freedom, Personal Identity, and the Possibility of Happiness. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Wawrykow, Joseph. 1995. God’s Grace and Human Action: “Merit” in the Theology of Thomas Aquinas. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Wawrykow, Joseph. 2005. “Grace.” In van Nieuwenhove, Rik and Wawrykow, Joseph (eds.), The Theology of Thomas Aquinas. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press: 192221.Google Scholar
Wawrykow, Joseph. 2012. “The Theological Virtues.” In Davies, Brian and Stump, Eleonore (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Westberg, Daniel. 1994. Right Practical Reason: Aristotle, Action, and Prudence in Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westberg, Daniel. 2002. “Good and Evil in Human Acts (Ia IIae, qq. 18–21).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
White, Kevin. 2013. “Pleasure, a Supervenient End.” In Hoffmann, Tobias, Müller, Jörn, and Perkams, Matthias (eds.), Aquinas and the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wieland, Georg. 1988. “Happiness: The Perfection of Man.” In Kretzmann, Norman, Kenny, Anthony, and Pinborg, Jan (eds.), The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wieland, Georg. 2002. “Happiness (Ia IIae, qq. 1–5).” In Pope, Stephen (ed.), The Ethics of Aquinas. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1973. “The Makropulos Case: Reflections on the Tedium of Immortality.” In Problems of the Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 82100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Thomas. 1995. “How Scotus Separates Morality from Happiness.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 69, No. 3: 425445.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Thomas. 2005. “Introduction.” In Atkins, E. M. and Williams, Thomas (eds.), Thomas Aquinas, Disputed Questions on the Virtues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Thomas. (ed.). 2019. The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Thomas. 2022. “John Duns Scotus.” In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2022 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2022/entries/duns-scotus.Google Scholar
Wippel, John. 1987. “Thomas Aquinas and Participation.” In Wippel, John (ed.), Studies in Medieval Philosophy. Catholic University of America Press: 117158.Google Scholar
Wohlman, Avital. 1981. “Amour du bien propre et amour de soi dans la doctrine Thomiste de l’amour.” Revue Thomiste, Vol. 81: 203234.Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan. 2010. Meaning in Life and Why It Matters. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wood, Jacob. 2018. “The Study of Theology as a Foretaste of Heaven: The Influence of Albert the Great on Aquinas’s Understanding of Beatitudo Imperfecta.” Nova et vetera, Vol. 16, No. 4 (Fall): 11031134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wood, William. 2013. “Thomas Aquinas on the Claim that God Is Truth.” Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. 51, No. 1 (January): 2147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodard, Christopher. 2015. “Hybrid Theories.” In Fletcher, Guy (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being. New York: Routledge: 161174.Google Scholar
Yartz, Frank. 1975. “Order and Right Reason in Aquinas’s Ethics.” Mediaeval Studies, Vol. 37, No. 1: 407418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, J. T., and Gordon, B.. 1992. “Economic Justice in the Natural Law Tradition: Thomas Aquinas to Francis Hutcheson.” Journal of the History of Economic Thought, Vol. 14, No. 1: 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Accessibility standard: WCAG 2.0 A

The PDF of this book conforms to version 2.0 of the Web Content Accessibility Guidelines (WCAG), ensuring core accessibility principles are addressed and meets the basic (A) level of WCAG compliance, addressing essential accessibility barriers.

Content Navigation

Table of contents navigation
Allows you to navigate directly to chapters, sections, or non‐text items through a linked table of contents, reducing the need for extensive scrolling.
Index navigation
Provides an interactive index, letting you go straight to where a term or subject appears in the text without manual searching.

Reading Order & Textual Equivalents

Single logical reading order
You will encounter all content (including footnotes, captions, etc.) in a clear, sequential flow, making it easier to follow with assistive tools like screen readers.
Short alternative textual descriptions
You get concise descriptions (for images, charts, or media clips), ensuring you do not miss crucial information when visual or audio elements are not accessible.
Full alternative textual descriptions
You get more than just short alt text: you have comprehensive text equivalents, transcripts, captions, or audio descriptions for substantial non‐text content, which is especially helpful for complex visuals or multimedia.

Visual Accessibility

Use of colour is not sole means of conveying information
You will still understand key ideas or prompts without relying solely on colour, which is especially helpful if you have colour vision deficiencies.
Use of high contrast between text and background colour
You benefit from high‐contrast text, which improves legibility if you have low vision or if you are reading in less‐than‐ideal lighting conditions.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge-org.demo.remotlog.com is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • General Bibliography
  • Joseph Stenberg, Colgate University, New York
  • Book: Aquinas and the Ethics of Happiness
  • Online publication: 07 August 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108777728.014
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • General Bibliography
  • Joseph Stenberg, Colgate University, New York
  • Book: Aquinas and the Ethics of Happiness
  • Online publication: 07 August 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108777728.014
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • General Bibliography
  • Joseph Stenberg, Colgate University, New York
  • Book: Aquinas and the Ethics of Happiness
  • Online publication: 07 August 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108777728.014
Available formats
×