Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-6bb9c88b65-6vlrh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-07-22T07:47:16.237Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Darwin’s Reinach

from Part I - Reinach and His Method

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 July 2025

Marietta Auer
Affiliation:
Max Planck Institute for Legal History and Legal Theory
Paul B. Miller
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Indiana
Henry E. Smith
Affiliation:
Harvard Law School, Massachusetts
James Toomey
Affiliation:
University of Iowa

Summary

Reinach believed that basic legal concepts exist, that their existence is independent of the positive law, and their existence is independent of moral obligation. In this idiosyncratic juxtaposition of positions, Reinach is joined by contemporary theorists drawing on evolutionary psychology and cognitive science in jurisprudence. But Reinach emphatically insisted that his claims were ontological, not psychological. This chapter explains why. For Reinach himself, the ontological status of legal concepts was one front in a broader debate over whether basic mathematical and logical concepts were true a priori or features of human psychology; a demonstrative project in the breadth of the a priori. But it is suggested that today’s theorists need not be as preoccupied with this distinction as Reinach was. Not only is the practical difference between ontological and evolutionary theories not as wide as Reinach seems to have assumed, but arguments for metaphysical reality in other domains are substantially less persuasive as applied to Reinach’s legal concepts.

Information

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NC
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

2 Darwin’s Reinach

2.1 Introduction

Adolf Reinach believed three controversial things – that basic legal concepts exist outside of the law; that their existence is conceptually independent of moral obligation; and that their existence entails nothing about positive law.Footnote 1 The juxtaposition of these beliefs is almost unheard of in jurisprudence. Those who argue for the extralegal reality of legal concepts tend to think they are inherently ethical, with entailments for both law and moral behavior.Footnote 2 And those who are skeptical that the law draws upon external concepts rather than constructs its own tend also to be skeptical of morality – or at least morality beyond ontologically parsimonious utilitarianism.Footnote 3

In his idiosyncratic position, however, Reinach is joined by today’s theorists drawing on evolutionary psychology and cognitive science in an account of legal concepts.Footnote 4 Like Reinach, these theorists believe that basic legal concepts have a genuine life outside of the law, as universal features of a human mind shaped by natural selection.Footnote 5 They too don’t think the existence of these concepts entails moral conclusions.Footnote 6 And, just like Reinach, evolutionary theorists tend to argue that the positive law can vary as it likes from basic concepts of human cognition and whatever morality may be or demand.Footnote 7

And yet Reinach himself could not have been clearer that his claims were not to be associated with the inchoate psychology of his day.Footnote 8 He insists that the kind of reality he ascribes to legal concepts is not about human psychology – ‘claims and obligations arise in the angels, devils, and gods – as long as they can really promise and can really hear promises.’Footnote 9 Fair enough – Reinach’s theory is different from cognitive theories – it holds legal concepts to be metaphysical truths for all conceivable intelligence, not evolved partially contingent human universals. But since we are theorizing about law by and for human beings, you might wonder what is really at stake in this distinction.Footnote 10

This chapter explains why – in intellectual context – Reinach took such pains to distinguish his account of the a priori realism of legal concepts from what might facially be thought of as close psychological equivalents. And I argue that, notwithstanding Reinach’s commitment to the distinction, it is perhaps not as essential to his legal theory as he believed. In other words, it may be possible to accept the insights of Reinach’s conclusions without fully subscribing to his metaphysics – if you happen to find evolutionary theory, cognitive science, or some similar account more plausible (though these fields are, of course, controversial in their own right).Footnote 11

For Reinach personally, the question of whether legal concepts ‘really’ exist or are ‘just’ psychological characteristics was one front in a broader dispute preoccupying German-language philosophy of his time – the firestorm over so-called ‘psychologism’; or whether (primarily) logical and mathematical principles are True-with-a-capital-T or generalizations about human thought. For Reinach, the ontological status of legal concepts was a case study in a broader account of ontology and epistemology.

But in fighting this broader battle, Reinach appears to have overestimated how much the outcome of the Psychologismus-Streit matters for legal theory. This is so for two reasons. First, the difference between metaphysical and evolutionary-cognitive theories of legal concepts is narrower than Reinach and his progenitors seem to have appreciated. Taking natural selection as the mechanism by which psychological proclivities arise means that there is a necessary relationship between psychology and ontology. It’s not necessarily correspondence, true, but neither is it arbitrary or wholly contingent.

Moreover, the arguments Reinach’s progenitors made for the metaphysical reality of logical and mathematical concepts are less persuasive as applied to Reinach’s legal concepts.Footnote 12 Where logic and math appear to apply to reality generally, law is for Reinach (at least at present, so far as we know), a peculiarly human phenomenon. Distinguishing between psychology and ontology is particularly difficult, maybe impossible, in that context. And in the end, Reinach and his allies stipulate rather than purport to prove the metaphysical reality of the concepts they discuss. In logic and math, this stipulation might be necessary – Reinach’s progenitors sought to make claims not merely about our logical concepts, but about how we ought to think with them. But writing in law, Reinach is different. Reinach doesn’t derive conclusions about how the positive law ought to be from the ontological existence of his concepts.

This chapter proceeds in five parts. First, I summarize Reinach’s legal philosophy, with its three idiosyncratic commitments. Next, I relate these views to theories of legal concepts grounded in evolutionary psychology – noting that, although Reinach predeceased scientific and theoretical developments that have made these theories more plausible, he took a crude sketch of what such theories might look like as a foil. In Section 2.4, I relate Reinach’s legal theory to his place in the psychologism dispute, while in Section 2.5 I argue that he overestimated the difference between his account and evolutionary theories. Finally, I argue that arguments in favor of metaphysical reality in other contexts of the psychologism dispute – logic and math in particular – hold less force as applied to Reinach’s legal concepts.

2.2 Reinach’s Three Commitments

In The A Priori Foundations of the Civil Law, Reinach sketches three contestable positions about the nature of legal concepts, morality, law, and the relationship between these domains. First, he argues that legal concepts – such as promise, claim, and ownership – have a real existence outside of the law. Second, he argues that these concepts are distinct from morality – according to Reinach, an immoral promise, like any other, generates an obligation but, ethically, one ought not comply with it. And neither of these domains, for Reinach, has any necessary implications for the positive law, which he apparently took to be a matter of descriptive social fact.

The central thesis of the Foundations is that basic legal concepts really exist, independent of their recognition or creation in positive law. ‘We shall show that the structures which one has generally called specifically legal have a being of their own just as much as numbers, trees, or houses, that this being is independent of its being grasped by men, that it is in particular independent of all positive law…. We really do find what one has emphatically denied: the positive law finds the legal concepts which enter into it; in absolutely no way does it produce them.’Footnote 13

Thus, Reinach believes that we can engage in a priori conceptual reasoning about such ideas as ‘promise’ and ‘ownership’ without invoking or referencing the positive law at all.Footnote 14 And indeed, his efforts at reasoning in this vein make up most of the Foundations – he argues, for example, that it inheres in the nature of a promise to create an obligation in the promisor;Footnote 15 and that ‘[i]t lies in the essence of owning that the owner has the absolute right to deal in any way he likes with the thing which belongs to him.’Footnote 16

As for how these concepts exist, Reinach was a metaphysical realist.Footnote 17 He argued that social acts like promises, and relations like ownership, have a distinctive mode of existence, as states-of-affairs.Footnote 18 These states-of-affairs exist (technically, ‘obtain’) for Reinach in a real, mind-independent way – constituents of the universe just as the physical facts that constitute them in particular instances.Footnote 19 Because general, fundamental, and abstract, states-of-affairs are, on Reinach’s account, governed by a priori laws to be grasped by insight – accessible to intelligence, in principle independent of any experience.Footnote 20 So, for example, Reinach holds that property is a state-of-affairs.Footnote 21 Given certain sets of physical and relational facts, an instance of property may obtain.Footnote 22 But any intelligence can reason to some truths about property – including the sets of facts that would qualify and which would not – without experience of any particular instance of property, because property itself is a fundamental constituent of the universe.Footnote 23 Or so goes Reinach’s account.

This central thesis of the Foundations is its most controversial. Indeed, even at the time he wrote, Reinach was well aware that he was arguing against the jurisprudential grain – noting that there was ‘general agreement’ that ‘all legal propositions and concepts are creations of the lawmaking factors,’ but that his inquiry would ‘really … find what one has so emphatically denied.’Footnote 24 And the century in legal philosophy since Reinach has not been kind to metaphysical realism about legal concepts, with Critical Theory and Law and Economics carrying forward Legal Realism’s nominalism about legal concepts to the present.Footnote 25

But while Reinach held these basic legal concepts to exist, he maintained that their existence is conceptually independent of how morally we ought to interact with them.Footnote 26 A promise, as a matter of its essential character, generates an obligation, but it might be an obligation morally wrong to fulfill.Footnote 27 In this insistence that basic legal concepts are morally inert, Reinach departs from most fellow travelers in legal conceptualism. Consider Scott Hershovitz, who, with Reinach and contra nominalism, accepts the extralegal reality of promises.Footnote 28 But for Hershovitz, promise is an irreducibly normative concept, and its boundaries are coterminous with its moral implications – an immoral promise simply isn’t a promise at all, and gives rise to no obligation.Footnote 29

Finally, Reinach refused to infer anything about the necessary characteristics of positive law from either the concepts on which it draws or (apparently) morality – Reinach was a positivist about positive law. For example, analyzing the positive law’s concept of causality in his doctoral thesis, Reinach insisted that the question is not whether the law’s causal theory is ‘correct’ as a moral or even philosophical matter.Footnote 30 The task instead is to investigate the positive law’s theory of causality – with no necessary connection to the philosophically correct account.Footnote 31 Thus, Reinach insisted that, although states-of-affairs like promise and obligation exist outside of the law and are governed by essential, descriptive laws, ‘[t]he positive law can incorporate them into its sphere, it can also deviate from them.’Footnote 32 A ‘jurist,’ he argued ‘need not establish what the law should mean according to logical or ethical or other norms, but rather what it in fact means.’Footnote 33

Reinach’s theory of the positive law is perhaps his least controversial commitment. His view is one recognizable, still popular position in debates about the nature of positive law – broadly within the ‘positivist’ umbrella.Footnote 34 But when this view is coupled with his insistence on the extralegal reality of legal concepts, as well as their morally inert character, we can see Reinach as the singular legal philosopher he was.

2.3 Evolutionary Legal Conceptualism’s Three Commitments

In 1859, Charles Darwin published The Origin of Species, arguing that natural selection explains the diversity and complexity of biology.Footnote 35 Darwin argued that organisms vary in random but heritable ways as to traits that correlate with reproductive success.Footnote 36 Assuming that, in our resource-constrained world, in each generation more organisms are born than can live to reproductive maturity, over time traits beneficial for survival will proliferate, and deleterious mutations will die without reproducing – explaining the gradual evolution of complexity, in diverse forms.Footnote 37

‘Evolutionary psychology’ argues that natural selection has shaped our minds as much as our other organs.Footnote 38 So it holds that many basic mechanisms and proclivities of the human mind, both conscious and unconscious, are biological adaptations governed by natural selection and heritably encoded in our genes; heuristics that helped our ancestors better survive in their environment than did their competitors, operationalized in each of us by genetic inheritance.Footnote 39

Methodologically, evolutionary psychology and cognitive science often take the cross-cultural universality of a given psychological fact as prima facie evidence of its genetic basis.Footnote 40 It is then a question of evolutionary theory whether such a trait could have arisen by natural selection – whether it could have contributed to the individual reproductive success of those with it, even if in complex and indirect ways.Footnote 41 And it is ultimately an empirical matter whether in fact the traits in question developed in the hypothesized way – for which evidence of a direct genetic basis is strong evidence.Footnote 42 Theorists have applied these methods to argue that a wide range of complex psychological universals – from language to the moralized emotion of disgust and separation anxiety – are genetically mediated products of natural selection.Footnote 43

Legal theorists drawing on evolutionary psychology have argued that many basic legal concepts could similarly be evolved, genetically grounded features of human cognition.Footnote 44 For example, the basic concept of ownership that organizes property law appears to be universal,Footnote 45 and could plausibly have evolved as an adaptation to ensure access to and dominion over resources.Footnote 46 Similar observations have been made, for instance, with respect to other basic legal concepts like promise.Footnote 47

Just like Reinach, these evolutionary psychologists and the legal theorists who follow them hold that basic legal concepts have a real existence outside of the law. Granted, these theorists ground the existence of these concepts in a different way – citing evolution and a modular mind. But their conclusions are importantly similar – legal concepts (at least the most basic ones on which both Reinach and evolutionary theorists focus) are not nominalistic legal constructions designed for normative purposes; they are real concepts that exist outside of any legal system and can be analyzed descriptively.

Moreover, perhaps even more emphatically than Reinach, theorists in evolutionary psychology refuse to infer anything moral from the innate existence of concepts in our psychology. The ‘naturalistic fallacy’ is an oft-repeated dogma – to state a fact about our psychology is not to imply anything about ethics.Footnote 48 So the innate existence of, say, the concept of ‘family’ doesn’t suggest anything about its moral significance; and it might be that we intuitively understand that the social act of promise gives rise to a ‘binding’ ‘obligation,’ but that these intuitions are morally wrong.

Finally, like Reinach, evolutionary theories of legal concepts tend to travel with a positivistic conception of the positive law. Owen Jones and Timothy Goldsmith, for example, argue that the positive law can in principle do whatever it wants, and often that it ought to – pursuing policy goals orthogonal or contrary to the basic concepts evolution has given us.Footnote 49 For Jones and Goldsmith (and other theorists in this vein) the positive law is presumed a historical artifact fully determined by social fact – not a concept with any necessary connection to facts about human psychology or morality.Footnote 50

In short, although they ground the existence of legal concepts in different places, and draw on different evidence, evolutionary theorists and Reinach see these concepts and their relation to morality and positive law in similar ways – they agree that legal concepts exist outside the law; they agree these concepts can plausibly be the subject of determinate, descriptive reasoning; and they agree that these concepts have no necessary connection to either moral duty or positive law.

Today’s evolutionary psychology, on which contemporary theorists draw, of course, did not exist in Reinach’s time. Indeed, the origin of modern evolutionary psychology is often attributed to Edward O. Wilson’s Sociobiology in 1975,Footnote 51 and today’s work draws on universal grammar in linguistics in the 1960s,Footnote 52 the ‘Modern Synthesis’ of Darwinian natural selection with Mendelian inheritance of the 1950s and 1960s,Footnote 53 the development of game theory in the 1950s,Footnote 54 and Fisher’s work on sexual selection in the 1930s.Footnote 55 Indeed, Darwinian evolution writ large has become vastly more plausible since Reinach’s death if for no other reason than the 1953 discovery of DNA as the physical mechanism of inheritance – a famous handwave by Darwin himself.Footnote 56

That being said, though less plausible, less sophisticated, and less empirically grounded, Reinach encountered and engaged with a basic sketch of the idea. After all, in Origin, Darwin himself suggested that ‘[p]sychology will be securely based on [a new] foundation … that of the necessary acquirement of each mental power and capacity by gradation.’Footnote 57 Perhaps most prominently in Reinach’s lifetime, the American Pragmatists – especially William James – drew on Darwin’s theory in suggesting that human psychological ‘instincts’ might have evolved.Footnote 58 Reinach was familiar with this work, having written an obituary for James after his 1910 death.Footnote 59 And Reinach’s mentor Husserl spent a chapter in his Prolegomena responding to the quasi-evolutionary logical theories of Ernst Mach and Richard Avenarius.Footnote 60

Thus, when Reinach insisted that his theory is not psychological – ‘independent of human knowledge, independent of the organization of human nature’Footnote 61 – and not an evolutionary account of human cognition – ‘not only for our world but for any conceivable world’Footnote 62 – it was not out of ignorance of what a theory of legal concepts grounded in evolutionary psychology could look like. Granted, and importantly (about which more below),Footnote 63 the proto-evolutionary psychology in vogue at the time – that of the Pragmatists – was substantively quite different from today’s in its theory of mind. James, Mach, and Avenarius happened to be empiricists about concepts – from their perspective, the human mind and its capacity for subjective experience may have evolved, but our conceptual schema emerge from experience and social linguistic partitioning, not genetics.Footnote 64 Today, evolutionary psychologists overwhelmingly posit a modular, computational mind ready built with innate concepts.Footnote 65 Still, it is not as though the basic idea were not out there in Reinach’s time.

To understand Reinach’s efforts to distinguish his theory from psychological ones – notwithstanding their superficial compatibility – then, we have to go deeper and take seriously what was at stake for him in grounding legal concepts in metaphysics rather than an evolutionary account of human psychology.

2.4 Reinach, Legal Concepts, and the Psychologismus-Streit

The proto-evolutionary psychology of the belle époque was missing many important theoretical and empirical pieces. But it was wildly fashionable – a ‘psychologically obsessed age.’Footnote 66 And in the increasingly naturalist intellectual climate after Darwin, psychology aspired to be descriptive and empirical. During this period, foundational psychologists like Sigmund Freud, William James, Wilhelm Wundt, and Reinach’s PhD advisor Theodor Lipps hoped to ground a new science of mind-as-brain in empirical study, seeking laws of human thought as universal and empirical as the laws of physics.Footnote 67

One intellectual movement during this time was an effort to situate intuitions about logic and mathematics in psychology – to argue that they were laws of human thought, not truths of our universe.Footnote 68 It was against this view that Gottlob Frege inveighed when he launched the Psychologismus-Streit in 1884. In his Foundations of Arithmetic and a series of works that followed, Frege argued against what he called ‘psychologism’ about math in particular, arguing that mathematical and logical rules are a priori, nonempirically true.Footnote 69 And thus was joined the Psychologismus-Streit that dominated German-language philosophy until the War.Footnote 70

Frege’s arguments against psychologism were suggestive and question-begging rather than dispositive – math, for example, is the most exact of all sciences; psychology perhaps the least.Footnote 71 Psychologism conflates ‘true’ with ‘taken-to-be-true’;Footnote 72 (but isn’t that the point?). Perhaps most powerfully, Frege argued that psychologism assumes or leads to solipsism – if numbers are just subject-specific ideas, how could we communicate?Footnote 73 ‘[A] hitherto unknown kind of madness.’Footnote 74 But, regardless of their validity, Frege’s arguments against psychologism were enough to convince that other titan of fin-de-siècle German philosophy, and one importantly closer to Reinach – Edmund Husserl.Footnote 75

Arguing against psychologism – and grounding his new method of phenomenology as an alternative – became one of Husserl’s primary pre-War projects – ‘Husserl’s Prolegomena has long been regarded as the pre-eminent statement of logical anti-psychologism.’Footnote 76 Husserl’s arguments on this score were largely of the same flavor as Frege’s – logical rules are more determinate than psychological rules, logical rules are phenomenologically a priori, etc.Footnote 77 And they are vulnerable to the same charges of circularity – presuming the reality of strict laws of logic when that is what the dispute is about.Footnote 78 But Husserl argued perhaps most forcefully against psychologism as entailing relativism. Psychologism, he says, amounts to ‘species relativism’ or ‘anthropologism’ – the hypothesis that principles of logic could be true for us but different for some other species.Footnote 79 ‘Absurd,’ says Husserl.Footnote 80

While this controversy was kicking into gear, Reinach was a graduate student under Theodor Lipps, who was rather a bogeyman to Husserl for suggesting that ‘logic is a psychological discipline.’Footnote 81 With his fellow students, Reinach read Husserl, found himself convinced, and decamped to Göttingen where he took a position as Husserl’s assistant and ‘worked closely with Husserl in the preparation of the second edition of the Logical Investigations.’Footnote 82 Reinach’s break with Lipps and his affiliation with Husserl, then, was largely the result of the latter’s convincing him that the psychologism of the former was in error.Footnote 83

With this intellectual context, Reinach’s efforts to distance himself from a psychological quasi-realism of legal concepts is hardly puzzling. The Psychologismus-Streit was a general debate over the relationship between metaphysics and psychology that he had very much joined – so was persuaded by the anti-pyschologist side to uproot his life and help fight Husserl’s war against his old mentor. And transcripts of Reinach’s seminars show that he ‘was perhaps the only philosopher in Germany at this time lecturing on the work of Frege.’Footnote 84 The question of whether the basic structures of our reason reflect timeless, a priori, metaphysically real truths or psychological facts was among the primary intellectual occupations of Reinach’s life.

Through this lens, Reinach’s metaphysical realism about legal concepts was another front in the war over psychologism – in law rather than logic or mathematics. Reinach insisted that truths about legal concepts – for example, that a claim dissolves once waived – have the same ontological status as the law of noncontradiction or 1 + 1 = 2; that they were essentially, mind-independently true.Footnote 85 Indeed, throughout Foundations, Reinach analogizes reasoning about the essence of legal concepts to the philosophy of mathematics – ‘[i]n immersing ourselves in the essence of these entities … we grasp connections in a manner analogous to the way in which we know when we immerse ourselves in the nature of numbers and geometrical forms’;Footnote 86 ‘there are eternal laws governing these legal entities and structures, laws which are independent of our grasp of them, just as are the laws of mathematics.’Footnote 87

Moreover, in trying to show that legal concepts have the same kind of reality as mathematical concepts, part of Reinach’s project was to show the breadth of the a priori – its usefulness and applicability not just to the suite of basic mathematical and logical principles long considered a priori in any event. Indeed, as far as Reinach was concerned, Husserl’s arguments against logical psychologism were not merely effective against logical psychologism, but in fact convincingly demonstrated the existence of a vast range of really existent a priori states-of-affairs that philosophy had long failed to appreciate.Footnote 88

We can reason about certain legal concepts in the same way that we can reason about numbers, Reinach is saying in Foundations, and the same arguments against psychologism apply – we have discovered the realm of the ‘pure essential laws of right.’Footnote 89 And this legal case study, then, might help us see that the realm of the a priori ‘extends absolutely everywhere’ – ‘one of the most important things in philosophy, and if one thinks it through completely, one of the most important things in the world.’Footnote 90 Perhaps Reinach’s deepest personal philosophical commitment.

2.5 Natural Selection and Ontology

But we are not Adolf Reinach, and with presumably less personal investment in Husserl’s vindication, it is fair to wonder whether indeed the sharp distinction he drew between phenomenological and psychological accounts of law amounts to all that much for legal theory. I argue that for at least two interrelated reasons legal theorists need not be as preoccupied as Reinach with the ontological status of concepts, at least between evolutionary theories and his own phenomenological realism. First, the difference between evolutionary psychological accounts and metaphysical realism is less wide than Reinach, Husserl, and Frege appear to have realized. Second, closely considered, Husserl’s and Frege’s arguments against psychologism are substantially more persuasive in their own fields of logic and mathematics than they are in law.

Recall one of Husserl’s strongest arguments against psychologism – it entails the possibility of ‘species relativism’; of the law of noncontradiction’s being true as a matter of human psychology but false for some intelligent alien species.Footnote 91 In other words, psychologism suggests ontologically arbitrary variation across different species’ ‘laws of thought.’ From this perspective, it is an argument against psychologism to point out that it doesn’t appear that such variation exists – we haven’t encountered species that seem to behave as though they have radically different understandings of the basic fabric of the universe than our own.

And consider Reinach:

Apriori connections find application … in the events of nature. If these connections are conceived of as thought-laws, then the question of how this is possible arises. How does it happen that nature complies with the laws of our thought? Are we to assume here an enigmatic pre-established harmony? … The reason why nature should accommodate itself to the laws of our thinking is not susceptible to insight.Footnote 92

If the principles of logic, mathematics, and private law are just laws of thought, the argument goes, what keeps them from being arbitrary? And as an actual empirical matter, it doesn’t look like they are – the basic ways in which we think do seem to largely track reality. If we have one rock and another, we really do have two; we have yet to encounter in the macro world circumstances under which the proposition ‘there is now a hungry lion at the cave entrance’ is both true and false at the same time.

This is an entirely fair argument against psychologism per se – strongly suggestive if not logically dispositive. As against the suggestion that our concepts are rules of thought full stop, it is fair to wonder why they wouldn’t vary arbitrarily as across individuals, species, or between individuals and the world around them. But it is not a particularly powerful argument against evolutionary psychologism. Indeed, if we assume that it is natural selection that has given rise to innate psychological concepts – as opposed to, say, random brain development or Humean empiricism – psychologism and metaphysical realism look, from a practical, emergent perspective, much more similar.

Say what you will about natural selection, but it is not arbitrary. Indeed, it is thoroughly dependent on and necessarily reflects ontology. From this perspective, basic legal concepts might be both metaphysical truths and laws of thought; or they may only be laws of thought, but which approximate in some nonarbitrary way whatever the truths of metaphysics are.

We can start with the observation that the kind of cognitive concepts and processes at issue – from, say, the law of noncontradiction to intuitions about the nature of ‘promise’ – are highly energy intensive. For starters, they require a brain, and a fairly complex one – and all of the energy and long and vulnerable childhood that requires.Footnote 93 Beyond that minimum, each additional complex informational faculty – like the capacity for language – requires further energy; more calories to sustain neurons rather than, say, physical defenses or the ability to fly.Footnote 94 Granting the premises of evolutionary psychology, we can assume that, unless these concepts were fitness enhancing in some way, we presumably would not have them – ancestors who had evolved them would have been outcompeted by organisms with more efficient energy allocation.Footnote 95 ‘According to evolutionary biology, the structural complexity of a given [trait] can provide evidence that the [trait] is an adaptation, even if nothing is known about [its] causal role.’Footnote 96

So how might concepts like noncontradiction or the relationship between claim and waiver be fitness enhancing? Well, one obvious answer is because the universe really is governed by these laws.Footnote 97 Suppose that we actually do live in a universe in which the law of noncontradiction is true – that it genuinely cannot be that a proposition is both true and false at the same time. An embedded cognitive shortcut to that effect would be fitness enhancing. Indeed, it is strictly fitter than its alternatives. If we know ‘there is now a hungry lion outside of the cave,’ we know to wait, because it simply cannot be that there is not a lion outside the cave. This is less energy intensive than some kind of freewheeling general intelligence that must deduce noncontradiction ex nihilo, and is much safer than not understanding noncontradiction at all. If 1 + 1 really does = 2, and knowing that has any implications for reproductive success, it is at least marginally fitness enhancing to understand that innately.

The same could be true of the concepts of private law – maybe we’ve evolved to intuitively understand that promise gives rise to obligation because that really is true – just as Reinach believes. You might wonder how such a thing is possible, how it could be that the concept of ‘promise’ actually exists in a universe that has been around, as far as we know, for billions of years before the first promising entity. Which is, of course, entirely fair. But I don’t know how or why the law of noncontradiction might exist either; or math or the laws of physics or any of the truths that we may have been the first to understand but apparently long preexisted us.Footnote 98

Granted, some philosophers have argued that although this line of reasoning might work for descriptive constituents of the universe, it could not account for the evolution of true moral intuitions or evaluative attitudes.Footnote 99 But even if this is right,Footnote 100 recall that for Reinach these basic legal concepts are descriptive – they exist in the same way that logic and math do, and are conceptually independent of our moral intuitions about them and the nature of moral reality.Footnote 101 If you reject that, your disagreement with Reinach goes deeper than the concepts’ mode of existence, to the nature of the thing – a defensible view, but no response to an evolutionary grounding of something like Reinach’s jurisprudence. After all, proponents of this ‘Darwinian Debunking’ argument are perfectly happy to concede that natural selection can give rise to psychological concepts that descriptively reflect ontology, and argue rather against inferring moral obligation from that, entirely consistent with Reinach’s picture.Footnote 102

In any event, if this all is right – and we’ve evolved basic legal concepts as a matter of innate psychology because they really exist – Reinach’s theory of the realism of concepts and a kind of evolutionary psychologism could be effectively coterminous. The concepts would exist both as an ontological matter – as Reinach would have it – and as a matter of innate psychology – as the evolutionary psychologists would have it. And indeed, the latter would be true because of the former.

Of course, there are other possibilities – natural selection hardly demands that our innate concepts are a one-to-one map of ontology (and obviously they are not – there is a vast range of electromagnetic radiation we are incapable of seeing, and our intuitions of motion are relative to the earth’s surface, and so on). But although natural selection does not compel a relationship of correspondence between ontology and innate psychology, it does entail some relationship – no options of which are arbitrary in the way Reinach, Husserl, and Frege were really worried about.

Suppose that in fact all that exists is a sea of particles. And even suppose arguendo that quantum mechanics is right that in the end these particles behave according to probability, not law – a particle actually can be in two places at once; the cat can be both dead and alive.Footnote 103 How might the law of noncontradiction as a cognitive heuristic be fitness enhancing in such a universe? Presumably it could only have evolved if it at least roughly reflected ontology as relevant to us – a kind of innate nominalism.Footnote 104 So long as a law of noncontradiction sufficiently approximates the reality within which the intelligence has to operate, an innate noncontradiction principle could evolve.

There is, indeed, suggestive evidence that this is precisely the relationship between evolved minds and the universe in which they exist. For example, our lay, intuitive physics much more closely approximates the Newtonian mechanics of the world we must navigate than the underlying quantum structure that might really constitute the universe.Footnote 105 But while it is fitness enhancing to intuitively grasp how to evade falling objects, our ability to mate evidently almost never turns on the off chance that all our electrons are in the wrong place or whatever. Intuitive, quasi-Newtonian mechanics is a pretty good approximation of how objects behave in macro space.Footnote 106 Nominalists of all kinds recognize that categories can be efficient mechanisms to bundle, use, and exchange pertinent information, even if those categories don’t themselves exist metaphysically and are fuzzy at the margins.Footnote 107 This account might be equally applicable to the anterior level of natural selection rather than posterior social or linguistic construction.

The important point is that, while this kind of innate nominalism does not faithfully replicate the deep structure of reality, it is hardly arbitrary. It only works if it packages reality in ways that really are useful. And that is nothing but a question of ontology. The objects that reflect light at 700 nm really are physically more similar to those that reflect light at 701 nm than those that reflect at 400 nm – and innate psychology does not draw a line between 700 and 701, but somewhere between 400 and 700 most languages will demarcate something like ‘blue’ from something like ‘red.’Footnote 108 Even if our evolved concepts are rough approximations of reality, then, or nominalistic but useful categories that do not really exist, they necessarily bear some relationship to metaphysical reality.Footnote 109

Husserl, at least, appears to have been willing to accept all this. After a hundred pages of polemic against psychologism, he is more favorable in his treatment of the ‘attempt to provide a biological basis for logical intuitions,’ conceding that ‘[s]urvival requires a certain adaption to external nature … the capacity to judge things more or less rightly, to foresee the course of events, to assess causal consequences, etc.,’ and that ‘[i]f the natural origin of the machinery which economizes thought is not to remain a miracle, … we shall have to … show … how a procedure which has had such success could and must have issued spontaneously out of purely natural causes.’Footnote 110

But Husserl rejected this hypothesis for failing to ‘consider how mental processes preserve truth.’Footnote 111 The problem was that Husserl did not see how natural selection might give rise to a computational, conceptual mind of the sort he envisioned.Footnote 112 And his foils in quasi-evolutionary theories of mind – Ernst Mach and Richard Avenarius – were hardly any help, being associationists about thought and radical empiricists about concepts.Footnote 113 But it is today’s evolutionary theorists who are perhaps the strongest exponents of a modular, computational theory of mind – who argue that in fact natural selection is the best explanation for a computational mind; that evolutionary psychology has defeated associationism and vindicated something more like an innate a priori.Footnote 114 If Husserl had this evolutionary theory of mind available, perhaps he would have been more receptive.Footnote 115

In short, if we accept that indeed it is because of natural selection that we have certain ‘laws of thought,’ we must accept certain ontological claims.Footnote 116 With this perspective on the interaction between natural selection and metaphysics, it isn’t surprising that we don’t observe species behaving as though they had radically different ontological perspectives than us – they would have had to have evolved in radically different metaphysical conditions. Nor is it surprising that our concepts map reality as we perceive it. Of course they do, that is how natural selection works. If they didn’t (radically, regularly, etc.) we would die and organisms with more useful concepts would flourish in our stead.

In the end, of course, Husserl and Reinach are right that metaphysical realism is a different commitment than evolutionary psychologism. These theories could be coterminous, but there is obviously daylight between them. Natural selection is not a perfect designer. We have vestigial organs.Footnote 117 Most agree that at least some traits are spandrels – byproducts of the evolution of some other adaptation.Footnote 118 And some argue that sexual selection can result in the development of arbitrary expensive traits.Footnote 119 But all that is controversial, and natural selection remains a brutal constraint – when vestigial organs become too energy intensive, or spandrels too far from the purposes for which they were adaptive, or mating rituals too over-the-top, organisms will start dying before reproducing.

So, yes, while Reinach was right that his theory is different from one grounded in evolutionary psychology, he was wrong about how different, and in what sense. We might have evolved concepts that do not ‘really’ exist. They might mis-map reality, and it’s possible that an intelligent species of angels with a different evolutionary history might have slightly different ones. But they are not arbitrary and cannot possibly be too far off. From this perspective, then, evolutionary theories of legal concepts look much closer to Reinach’s.

2.6 Reinach’s Legal Anti-psychologism

In short, Reinach – and his mentors against psychologism – appear to have overestimated the differences between evolutionary accounts of concepts and metaphysical ones. But it is still worth taking seriously these thinkers’ affirmative arguments for metaphysical realism. After all, if Reinach or his intellectual progenitors had managed to demonstrate the metaphysical realism of legal concepts, or show some reason that metaphysical reality, and only metaphysical reality, could do the necessary work, whether evolutionary accounts overlap significantly might be beside the point. Reinach himself did not spend all that much time making affirmative arguments for metaphysical realism – rather, he largely assumed it was right; psychologism wrong. Presumably he thought the work had already been done – that Husserl and Frege had won. From this perspective, it seems fair to attribute to Reinach Husserl and Frege’s arguments against psychologism. The problem for Reinach is that those arguments are much stronger in mathematics and logic than in private law.

To analyze whether any of Reinach, Husserl, and Frege have given us substantial affirmative reason to accept that metaphysical realism, and not evolutionary accounts of human psychology, is the mode of existence of basic concepts they are talking about, let us take their beliefs about psychologism (whether in logic, math, or law) as making the following two claims –

(1)

there exist, metaphysically, certain basic concepts (of logic, math, or law) (a metaphysical claim);

(2)

about which insight or intuition can reveal essential truths (an epistemic one).Footnote 120

And what we are trying to figure out is whether any of these thinkers have given us a basis on which to reject –

(1a)

the relevant concepts exist as features of human psychology

as a substitute for (1).

What are the arguments, then, for (1)? Most of them, as already alluded to, are hardly slam dunks. Frege and Husserl say that logical and mathematical laws cannot be derived from psychological laws because psychological laws are vague where logic is precise – but why not? Surely clarity can sometimes emerge on less-predictable forms – as Newtonian from quantum mechanics. They say that logic by its nature is True-out-there and psychologism requires it to be true in some relativistic sense, but this begs the question. It is circular to assume the necessity of Truth-out-there when that is precisely what the dispute is about – the psychologistic camp simply denies that logic, or anything, is True-out-there, or denies the possibility that we could know.Footnote 121 These sorts of arguments aren’t going to cut it – if this were all we had to insist on (1) over (1a), I wouldn’t bet the farm.Footnote 122

One stronger argument, already discussed in Section 2.5, is inductive – (2) is true, which suggests something like (1) must be.Footnote 123 This is how Reinach proceeds, his clearest argument for (1) in the Foundations is that he is showing it by doing (2) – ‘[w]e shall show that the structures which one has generally called specifically legal have a being of their own ….’Footnote 124 And for Frege and Husserl, we can after all do math and use logic; it must have some kind of existence.

This argument is fair, as far as it goes. It is inductive, and not logically conclusive.Footnote 125 But, as discussed, it is obviously on to something. Natural selection depends on ontology, and our evolved concepts necessarily bear some nonarbitrary relationship to metaphysics. Indeed, if (1) is true, (1a) likely would be as well, because of (1). And if (1a) is true, something like (1) must be. But if we are trying to show (1) over (1a) where they come apart – if we are trying to show that some concept exists metaphysically as opposed to just as a matter of human psychology, or both – this inductive approach is much more persuasive for Frege and Husserl in math and logic than it is in law.

This is because law and the social acts that, on Reinach’s account, constitute it, are different from math and logic in precisely the relevant respect – even if legal concepts exist as a matter of metaphysics, at least at present truths about them are only accessible to, and visible among, human beings. That makes it impossible to inductively distinguish between (1) and (1a) – Reinach’s phenomenology can do (2), which can show that something like (1a) must be true, and maybe (1a) is because of (1), but maybe it is because of something like (1), and maybe it is not (for example, it might be the result of sexual selection).Footnote 126

Consider the grounds on which Frege and Husserl can suggest (1). They can start by doing (2) themselves – reasoning, apparently a priori, to apparently true conclusions. But they might be crazy. So, like Socrates in the Meno, they can find random people and do (2) together.Footnote 127 But those people might be crazy. So, they talk to everyone, and together everyone does (2). (1) is looking more and more likely. But everyone might be crazy. That is just another way of saying that (1a), or some psychologism less correlated with ontology than an evolutionary account, might be true, and could account for our ability to collectively (2).

But Frege and Husserl can do more than merely (2) with all human beings – they can look at the structure of the world around them. They can see, as we saw above, that animals appear to cogitate according to similar logical rules to the ones they have relied on at (2). Of course that doesn’t prove (1), rather than convergent evolution (which might well be because of (1), but could be for other reasons)Footnote 128 but it is something. And Frege and Husserl can go even further, and point out that it appears that the conclusions we reach while (2)ing are true about everything – that the world does behave according to our a priori logical structure, and our a priori mathematical conclusions account for innumerable phenomena.Footnote 129

Reinach cannot do this. Social acts don’t happen without social entities.Footnote 130 And, for Reinach, human beings are the only entities of which we are currently aware that can participate in or reason about legal concepts. ‘[A]nimals too can be bearers of experience, but never of claims or obligations.’Footnote 131 He claims that his conclusions apply to angels, gods, and devils, but, as empirical verification of this might be the best way to inductively distinguish between something more like (1) and something more like (1a), forgive me for waiting.Footnote 132

Finally, this brings us to what seems to be the crux of the issue for Frege and Husserl. It is not really an argument at all. It is a stipulation. Frege, for example, admits that ‘[t]here appears such a world of difference between me and the psychological logicians that there is no prospect of influencing them through my book.’Footnote 133 But he inveighs –

When will an end be put to this once and for all! Everything is eventually dragged into the realm of psychology; the boundary between the objective and the subjective disappears more and more, and even actual objects are treated psychologically as ideas…. Thus everything leads to idealism and with perfect logical consistency into solipsism.Footnote 134

If we want to emerge from the subjective at all, then we must conceive of knowledge as an activity that does not create what is known but grasps what already exists.’Footnote 135

And Husserl – ‘I … find myself at a point which I have either to recognize as the Archimedean point from which the world of doubt and unreason may be levered on its hinges, or which I may sacrifice at the peril of sacrificing all reason and knowledge’;Footnote 136 ‘One cannot persuade the subjectivist any more than one can the open sceptic, a man simply lacking the ability to see that laws … have their roots in the mere meaning of truth … must [embrace a position] count[ed] as the purest nonsense.’Footnote 137

In other words, Frege and Husserl hold that (1) must be true. Must (1) be true, though? Of course not, not literally; not logically.Footnote 138 Hence the stipulation, and its insistence. It could, ‘in principle,’ be that there are some species for which the concept of equality ‘exists’ and those it does not. The universe could be fundamentally disordered; I could be a brain-in-a-vat – ‘a dream about being a person.’Footnote 139 It’s not possible for a concept like equality to exist or not exist metaphysically across species, and, if the law of noncontradiction is metaphysically true, then it couldn’t be true and false for different species,Footnote 140 but that takes us right back to the circularity. Confining ourselves to strict possibility, we face the specter of an incoherent, disordered, meaningless universe that has only to this point appeared to each of us coherent and ordered and contemplative of meaning. We always have; we always will.Footnote 141

Frege and Husserl’s ‘must,’ in ‘(1) must be true,’ then, is not the ‘must’ of logical entailment. It is, rather, a certain kind of ‘must if’ – (1) must be true if anything matters. Granted, (1) might not be true. But perhaps then it’d be time to throw in the towel – at least for their project, presumably for projects, period. Why is this? Stipulating the metaphysical existence of one’s concepts of investigation hardly seems demanded by conceptual analysis as such. The language philosophers of the mid-century, for instance (to whom Reinach bears a striking resemblance)Footnote 142 were perfectly happy to parse the conceptual structure of speech while disclaiming any views on its metaphysical correspondence.Footnote 143 Plenty of people, also like Reinach, analyze the descriptive entailments of legal concepts without stipulating anything like (1), and certainly without the high melodrama of Frege and Husserl on the point.Footnote 144

But this kind of ontologically detached analysis is not a possibility for Frege and Husserl, precisely because of what they are analyzing. The difference is that a language or legal philosopher need not tell us anything about how we ought to interact with a social concept they are analyzing – we might be better off without it at all, and still learn something useful from the project. But in theorizing about the foundations of logic and mathematics, Frege and Husserl are hoping to tell us how we ought to think – in formal logic and, well, everywhere.

It is, after all, implicit in their project that we ought to be persuaded by their logic; on the presumption that we ought to think logically. As Husserl puts it, ‘[t]his being bound is not meant psychologically in the sense of a thought-compulsion, but in the ideal sense of a norm: whoever judges differently, judges quite wrongly.’Footnote 145 Without some theory of how we ought to think – what counts as thinking, what we ought to recognize as thinking and accord appropriate respect – we do confront radical skepticism or solipsism. Frege and Husserl are, in other words, deriving normative claims about how we ought to think from their descriptive claims about the ontological foundations of logic and mathematics.

For deriving oughts about thought, we need (1), not (1a). If we stipulate (1), we take it that there is a genuine logical structure of truth in the universe. For this fact to ground an ought, all we now need is perhaps the most unobjectionable epistemic norm of all time – (n) we ought to think truly. That is, we ought to think according to what is actually true; we do something normatively objectionable when we think incorrectly. If we accept (n), and (1) is true, we get an ought about logic. We can follow, and be persuaded by, Husserl and Frege’s emergent analysis of logical and mathematical concepts. Indeed, we can hear each other out in all contexts, without worrying about that defiant rejoinder of the radical skeptic – ‘That all sounds right. But even if it is, why should I care?’ That is what Frege and Husserl stipulate (1) (and (n), more implicitly) against.

(1a) simply does not have the same normative force. You might wonder why this is. After all, even with (1), we face the tried-and-true difficulty of deriving an ought from an is.Footnote 146 Indeed, we had to stipulate that we ought to think truly. Why couldn’t we rather stipulate (na) – we ought to think according to our evolved cognitive proclivities – rather than (n)?

All I can say here is that (na) is plainly false, and (n) plainly true. If we have evolved to think a certain way, but doing so is incorrect, and does not track reality, and is wrong, we ought not think that way. I take this to be uncontroversial, at least outside of the kind of nihilist circles that so agitate Husserl and Frege. As Husserl puts it, ‘[t]he constitution of a species is a fact: from a fact it is only possible to derive other facts.’Footnote 147 Today’s evolutionary psychologists, famously, agree.Footnote 148 (na) is precisely the species relativism of Husserl’s worries; adjacent to perhaps even more nihilistic (nb) – we ought to think however we do (individually; Frege’s solipsism). Either of these is a straightforward rejection of the possibility of meaning, of standing to demand that some other’s thinking track the same reality as mine. Husserl and Frege are right, then, on their own terms, about the domain in which they are writing. In logic, at least, and probably math, if we are to have a theory about how we ought to think and speak, we must accept (1) (or something like it)Footnote 149 over (1a).

But what does this all have to do with jurisprudence? Maybe nothing, and that’s the point. Reinach’s own peculiar, descriptive approach to thinking about legal concepts lets us avoid this whole mess. Because Reinach, unlike Husserl, does not ground normative claims in the existence of the legal concepts he is analyzing.Footnote 150 In other words, where Husserl makes claims about how we ought to think, grounded in claims about, metaphysically, how things are, Reinach makes claims about how things, metaphysically, are (there exist these basic legal concepts) but does not draw from this claims about how the positive law ought to be. The positive law, he insists, unlike Husserlian logical thinking, is normatively free to vary from the a priori, and sometimes ought to.Footnote 151 Reinach sets aside questions about what we ought to do with the concepts he describes.

So insofar as all Reinach is doing, ultimately, is describing his concepts, he loses Husserl’s reasons for insisting on (1) over (1a). As already emphasized, (1) and (1a) are similar for many purposes. If one’s project is merely to describe specified concepts, they might be identical. But they differ in normative force. (n) is banal. (1) plus (n) is a straightforward foundation for epistemic normativity; maybe necessary for normativity writ large. (na), by contrast, is facially preposterous, and (1a) plus (na) flirts with nihilism. In other words (1) and (1a) might be quite similar, but n and na are not. If Husserl wants to write about how we ought to think and speak and communicate with one another, he needs (1). But Reinach’s project is different on its own terms. By setting aside the normative implications of the legal concepts he analyzes, Reinach doesn’t need (n) over (na). He doesn’t need any kind of n at all. And if he doesn’t need (na) over (n), he doesn’t need (1a) over (1), either.

In short, it is true that the ontological status of concepts might matter normatively. Frege and Husserl recognize this, and to the extent they want to derive claims about how we ought to think in math or logic, their concepts might have to exist ontologically rather than psychologically. But Reinach is different. His analysis is descriptive, not normative. It illuminates the positive law, rather than tells us how it ought to be. And for that project, (1) and (1a) are more closely equivalent. If evolutionary psychology (or any other theory), offers an alternative, relevantly equivalent mode of existence for legal concepts – namely, holds them to exist in a descriptive way that has no necessary connection to either morality or the positive law, accessible to human intuition, as both metaphysics and evolutionary psychology do – it seems that Reinach has no real grounds to reject it.

2.7 Conclusion

In insisting that the basic concepts of private law exist outside of their legal construction, but that this fact has no conceptual implications for moral obligations or positive law, Adolf Reinach may be a nearly unique figure in the history of legal philosophy. Perhaps closest to his perspective are those contemporary theorists who have applied evolutionary psychology to a theory of legal concepts – and who agree that basic concepts really do exist in some sense outside of legal construction, but that positive law is free to deviate from them, and often ought to. On its face, it is something of a puzzle, then, that Reinach makes so clear that he is not one of them – prepared to stake everything on his claims being ontological, not psychological.

As a matter of Reinach’s personal intellectual history, this commitment makes perfect sense – he saw it as one exemplary application of perhaps the most important philosophical position of his life, a commitment to a thick, epistemically accessible fundamental ontology, shared and hashed out by the leading figures of pre-War German philosophy.

But the Psychologismus-Streit ended with the outbreak of actual war in 1914. And post-War philosophers have largely found the stakes of whether the laws and concepts of logic and mathematics are metaphysically real or ‘laws of thought’ lower than did Frege, early Husserl, and Reinach. I’ve argued that this is particularly so in jurisprudence. Indeed, the difference between evolutionary theories of legal concepts and metaphysical ones is smaller than Reinach appears to have assumed, and Husserl’s and Frege’s arguments are more convincing in their own domains than in Reinach’s. In short, whatever Reinach himself would have to say (and as several contributions to this volume have argued on different grounds)Footnote 152 his insights remain relevant even for many of those who might struggle with his metaphysics.

Footnotes

* Associate Professor of Law, University of Iowa College of Law. Thanks to the conference audience at the Max Planck Institute in Frankfurt, the other contributors to this volume, in particular the insights of my co-editors Marietta Auer, Paul Miller, and Henry Smith, and the research assistance of Brooke Wood. Thanks also to Olivier Massin and Kimberly Baltzer-Jaray, my guides in Reinach.

2 Scott Hershovitz, ‘The End of Jurisprudence’ (2015) 124 Yale LJ 1160; Steven Schaus, ‘A Simple Model of Torts and Moral Wrongs’ (2022) 97 Notre Dame L Rev 1029; Ian McLeod, Legal Theory (6th edn, Red Globe Press 2012) 18; Michael S Moore, ‘Moral Reality Revisited’ (1992) 90 Michigan L Rev 2424, 2425.

3 Joseph William Singer, ‘The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and Legal Theory’ (1984) 94 Yale LJ 1; Richard Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (7th edn, Aspen 2007); Felix S Cohen, ‘Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach’ (1935) 35 Columbia L Rev 809.

4 Owen D Jones and Timothy H Goldsmith, ‘Law and Behavioral Biology’ (2005) 105 Columbia L Rev 405; Bart J Wilson, The Property Species: Mind, Yours, and the Human Mind (Oxford University Press 2020).

5 Wilson (Footnote n 4) 19.

6 Steven Pinker, The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature (Penguin 2002) 151.

7 Jones and Goldsmith (Footnote n 4) 484.

8 Adolf Reinach, ‘The Apriori Foundations of the Civil Law’ (John F Crosby tr, 1983) 3 Aletheia 1, 72, reprinted in Adolf Reinach, The Apriori Foundations of the Civil Law Along with the Lecture ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (John F Crosby ed, Ontos Verlag 2012), originally published as Adolf Reinach, ‘Die apriorischen Grundlagen des bürgerlichen Rechtes’ 1(2) Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung (Max Niemeyer 1913) 685847.

10 James Toomey, ‘Property’s Boundaries’ (2023) 109 Virginia L Rev 131, 160.

11 Linda Gannon, ‘A Critique of Evolutionary Psychology’ (2010) 4 Psychology, Evolution and Gender 173; Steven Rose and Hilary Rose, Alas Poor Darwin: Arguments Against Evolutionary Psychology (Crown 2001).

12 Reinach, ‘Foundations’ (Footnote n 8) 45.

13 Reinach, ‘Foundations’ (Footnote n 8) 4.

17 Kimberly Baltzer-Jaray, ‘Bogged Down in Ontologism and Realism’ in Rodney KB Parker (ed), The Idealism-Realism Debate among Edmund Husserl’s Early Followers and Critics (Springer Cham 2021) 151, 161–162.

18 Adolf Reinach, ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (Dallas Willard tr), in John Crosby (ed), The Apriori Foundation of the Civil Law: Along with the Lecture Concerning Phenomenology (De Gruyter 2013) 145, 158.

19 Footnote ibid 146–147.

20 Reinach, ‘Foundations’ (Footnote n 8) 6.

21 Footnote ibid 70–74.

24 Reinach, ‘Foundations’ (Footnote n 8) 4.

25 See Footnote n 3.

26 Reinach, ‘Foundations’ (Footnote n 8) 45.

28 Hershovitz (Footnote n 2) 1180.

29 Footnote ibid; John Gardner, From Personal Life to Private Law (Oxford University Press 2018) 12.

30 Adolf Reinach, ‘On the Concept of Causality in the Criminal Law’ (2009) 1 Libertarian Papers 1, 40 (Berit Brogaard, tr).

32 Reinach, ‘Foundations’ (Footnote n 8) 6.

33 Reinach, ‘Causality’ (Footnote n 30) 40.

34 Jules L Coleman, ‘The Architecture of Jurisprudence’ (2011) 121 Yale LJ, 5; Scott J Shapiro, ‘The Hart-Dworkin Debate: A Short Guide for the Perplexed’ in Arthur Ripstein (ed), Ronald Dworkin (Cambridge University Press 2007) 22.

35 Charles Darwin, The Origin of Species (First Signet 2003).

38 John Tooby and Leda Cosmides, ‘Conceptual Foundations of Evolutionary Psychology’ in David M Buss (ed), The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (Wiley 2021) 5, 5.

40 Livia Beccacece and others, ‘Human Genomics and the Biocultural Origin of Music’ (2021) 22 International J Molecular Sciences 5397, 5398; David M Buss, Evolutionary Psychology (5th edn, Pearson 2011); Daniel L Schacter, Daniel T Gilbert, and Daniel M Wegner, Psychology (5th edn, Worth 2007) 2627; RR McCrae and PT Costa Jr., ‘Personality Trait Structure as a Human Universal’ (1997) 52 American Psychologist 509, 509.

41 There is a great deal of theoretical dispute about the comparative role of traditional natural selection in this process as compared to the related mechanisms of sexual selection, Richard O Prum, The Evolution of Beauty: How Darwin’s Forgotten Theory of Mate Choice Shapes the Animal World – And Us (Doubleday 2017), contingency, Stephen J Gould and Richard C Lewontin, ‘The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme’ (1979) 205 Proceedings of the Royal Society B 581, and whether so-called ‘group selection’ is ever possible, Egbert Giles Leigh Jr, ‘The Group Selection Controversy’ (2009) 23 J Evolutionary Biology 6. The details of these disputes aside, evolutionary psychology holds that psychological traits arose by whatever mechanisms in fact contributed to our evolution.

42 Alessandra Mozzi and others, ‘The Evolutionary History of Genes Involved in Spoken and Written Language: Beyond FOXP2’ (2016) 6 Scientific Rep 22157, 22157; Faraneh Vargha-Khadem and others, ‘FOXP2 and the Neuroanatomy of Speech and Language’ (2005) 6 Nature Rev Neuroscience 131, 131.

43 Footnote ibid; James M Sherlock and others, ‘The Quantitative Genetics of Disgust Sensitivity’ (2016) 16 Emotion 43, 43; L Sloman, P Gilbert, and G Hasey, ‘Evolved Mechanisms in Depression: The Role and Interaction of Attachment and Social Rank in Depression’ (2003) 74 J Affective Disorders 107, 107.

44 Jones and Goldsmith, (Footnote n 4); Carlton J Patrick, ‘The Long-Term Promise of Evolutionary Psychology for the Law’ (2016) 48 Arizona State LJ 995; Owen D Jones and Robert Kurzban, ‘Intuitions of Punishment’ (2010) 77 U Chicago L Rev 1633.

45 Wilson (Footnote n 4) 3; Pascal Boyer, ‘How Natural Selection Shapes Conceptual Structure: Human Intuitions and Concepts of Ownership’ in Eric Margolis and Stephen Laurence (eds), The Conceptual Mind: New Directions in the Study of Concepts (MIT 2015) 185, 186; Julia W Van der Vondervoort, Paul Meinz, and Ori Friedman, ‘Children’s Judgments About Ownership Rights and Body Rights: Evidence for a Common Basis’ (2017) 155 J Experimental Child Psychology 1, 2.

46 Wilson (Footnote n 4) 17; Miyashita Haruki, ‘On a Trade-Off in the Evolution of Ownership’ (2018) 38 Economics Bulletin 1257.

47 Leda Cosmides and John Tooby, ‘Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, Part II: Case Study: A Computational Theory of Social Exchange’ (1989) 10 Ethology and Sociobiology 51.

48 Pinker, ‘Blank Slate’ (Footnote n 6) 151; David Sloan Wilson, Eric Dietrich, and Anne B Clark, ‘On the Inappropriate Use of the Naturalistic Fallacy in Evolutionary Psychology’ (2003) 18 Biology and Philosophy 669; Neil Levy, ‘Evolutionary Psychology, Human Universals, and the Standard Social Science Model’ (2004) 19 Biology and Philosophy 459.

49 Jones and Goldsmith (Footnote n 4) 432–435.

50 Footnote ibid 431–433.

51 Edward O Wilson, Sociobiology: The New Synthesis (Harvard University Press 1975).

52 Noam Chomsky, Aspects of the Theory of Syntax (MIT 1965).

53 Nicholas H Barton, ‘The “New Synthesis”’ (2022) 119 Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences e2122147119.

54 John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern, Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (Princeton University Press 1944).

55 M Anderson and LW Simmons, ‘Sexual Selection and Mate Choice’ (2006) 21 Trends in Ecology and Evolution 296.

56 James D Watson and Francis H Crick, ‘Molecular Structure of Nucleic Acids: A Structure for Deoxyribose Nucleic Acid’ (1953) 171 Nature 737.

57 Darwin (Footnote n 35) 506.

58 William James, Principles of Psychology (originally published 1890, Harvard University Press 1981) 274285; Susan Haack, ‘The Pragmatist Tradition: Lessons for Legal Theorists’ (2018) 95 Washington U L Rev 1049, 1055, n 38.

59 Adolf Reinach, ‘William James and Pragmatism’ in Barry Smith (tr and ed), Speech Act and Sachverhalt (Springer 1987) 291.

60 Edmund Husserl, Logical Investigations, Vol. I (JN Findlay tr, Routledge 2001) 123.

61 Reinach (Footnote n 8) 139.

63 Infra, Footnote nn 113Footnote 115 and accompanying text.

64 James, ‘Principles’ (Footnote n 58) 274–285; William James, Essays in Radical Empiricism (Harvard University Press 1912); infra Footnote nn 113Footnote 115 and accompanying text.

65 Steven Pinker, How the Mind Works (Norton 1997); Daniel C Dennett, Consciousness Explained (Back Bay 1992); Henry Plotkin, Evolution in Mind: An Introduction to Evolutionary Psychology (Harvard University Press 2000).

66 Husserl (Footnote n 60) 64.

67 James, ‘Principles’ (Footnote n 58); Wilhelm Wundt, ‘On Psychological Methods’ (1883) 1 Philosophische Studien 1; Sigmund Freud, The Interpretation of Dreams (Basic 2010).

68 John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive (first published in 1843; Cambridge University Press 2011); Benno Erdmann, Logik, Logische Elementarlehre (Max Niemeyer 1892).

69 Gottlob Frege, ‘The Foundations of Arithmetic’ in Michael Beaney (ed and tr), The Frege Reader (Blackwell 1997) 84; Gottlob Frege, ‘Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Volume I’ in Michael Beaney (ed and tr), The Frege Reader (Blackwell 1997) 194; Gottlob Frege, ‘Book Review of Husserl 1891’ (1894) 103 Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 313.

70 Martin Kusch, ‘Psychologism’ in Edward N Zalta (ed), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (online 2020).

71 Frege, ‘Foundations’ (Footnote n 69) 87.

72 Frege, ‘Grundgesetze (Footnote n 69) 202.

75 There is some historical dispute as to whether it really was Frege’s criticism that dissuaded Husserl from psychologism (and indeed whether Husserl had ever really endorsed psychologism), but regardless it was after Frege that Husserl took up the mantle of anti-psychologism. Martin Kusch, Psychologism: A Case Study in the Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge (Routledge 1995) 1213.

76 Robert Hanna, ‘Husserl’s Prolegomena and the Truth in Psychologism’ (1993) 53 Philosophy Phenomenological Res 251, 252.

77 Husserl (Footnote n 60) 46–55.

78 Paul Natorp, ‘On the Question of Logical Method in Relation to Edmund Husserl’s Prolegomena to Pure Logic’ in JN Mohanty (ed), Readings on Edmund Husserl’s Logical Investigations (Springer 1977) 55, 57.

79 Husserl (Footnote n 60) 78–79.

81 Quoted in Dale Jacquette, Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychologism: Critical and Historical Readings on the Psychological Turn in Philosophy (Springer 2006) 88, 89.

82 John F Crosby, ‘A Brief Biography of Adolf Reinach’ in John F Crosby (ed), The Apriori Foundations of the Civil Law: Along with the Lecture ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (De Gruyter 2013) viii.

83 Florian Gödel, ‘An Introduction to Moritz Geiger’s Psychological Contribution on Empathy’ (2015) 8 Dialogues in Philosophy, Mental and Neuro Sciences 161.

84 Karl Schuhmann and Barry Smith, ‘Adolf Reinach: An Intellectual Biography’ in Kevin Mulligan (ed), Speech Act and Sachverhalt: Reinach and the Foundations of Realist Phenomenology (Springer 1987).

85 Kimberly Baltzer-Jaray, ‘Phenomenological Jurisprudence: A Reinterpretation of Adolf Reinach’s Jarhrbuch Essay’ in JA Simmons and JE Hackett (eds), Phenomenology for the Twenty-First Century (Palgrave Macmillan 2016) 118, 118.

86 Reinach, ‘Foundations’ (Footnote n 8) 4.

88 Reinach, ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (Footnote n 18) 15; Barry Smith, ‘On the Austrianness of Austrian Economics’ (1990) 4 Critical Review 212.

89 Reinach, ‘Foundations’ (Footnote n 8) 139.

90 Reinach, ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (Footnote n 18) 156.

91 Husserl (Footnote n 60) 78–79.

92 Reinach, ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (Footnote n 18) 159.

93 Michael A Hofman, ‘Evolution of the Human Brain: When Bigger Is Better’ (2014) 8 Frontiers in Neuroscience 1; Stephen C Cunnane, Laurence S Harbige, and Michael A Crawford, ‘The Importance of Energy and Nutrient Supply in Human Brain Evolution’ (1993) 9 Nutrition and Health 219; Ana Navarrete, Carel P van Schaik, and Karin Isler, ‘Energetics and the Evolution of Human Brain Size’ (2011) 480 Nature 91.

94 Chet C Sherwood and others, ‘Evolution of Increased Glia-Neuron Ratios in the Human Frontal Cortex’ (2006) 103 Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 13606.

95 Matt Ridley, The Red Queen: Sex and the Evolution of Human Nature (2nd edn, Harper 1993); Steven Pinker and Paul Bloom, ‘Natural Language and Natural Selection’ (1990) 13 Behavioral Brain Sciences 707, 709.

96 Shaun Nichols and Todd Grantham, ‘Adaptive Complexity and Phenomenal Consciousness’ (2000) 67 Philosophy Science 648, 648.

97 James Toomey, ‘Evolutionary Anamnesis’ (2022) 37 Biology and Philosophy 55, 56; S Lehar, ‘Gestalt Isomorphism and the Primacy of Subjective Conscious Experience: A Gestalt Bubble Model’ (2003) 26 Behavioral Brain Sciences 375; WS Geisler and RL Diehl, ‘A Bayesian Approach to the Evolution of Perceptual and Cognitive Systems’ (2003) 27 Cognitive Science 379.

98 Martin Heidegger, An Introduction to Metaphysics (Ralph Manheim tr, Yale University Press 1959) 67; James Ladyman, ‘The Foundations of Structuralism and the Metaphysics of Relations’ in Anna Marmodoro and David Yates (eds), The Metaphysics of Relations (Oxford University Press 2015) 177, 179–80.

99 Sharon Street, ‘A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value’ (2006) 127 Philosophical Studies 109; Michael Ruse, Taking Darwin Seriously: A Naturalistic Approach to Philosophy (2nd edn, Prometheus 1986).

100 And it is hardly without controversy. William J Fitzpatrick, ‘Why There is No Darwinian Dilemma for Ethical Realism’ in Michael Bergmann and Patrick Kain (eds), Challenges to Moral and Religious Belief: Disagreement and Evolution (Oxford University Press 2014) 237; Knut Olav Skarsaune, ‘Darwin and Moral Realism: Survival of the Iffiest’ (2011) 152 Philosophical Studies 229; David Enoch, ‘The Epistemological Challenge to Metanormative Realism: How Best to Understand It, and How to Cope with It’ (2010) 148 Philosophical Studies 413.

102 Street (Footnote n 99) 112–113.

103 David J Griffiths and Darrell F Schroeter, Introduction to Quantum Mechanics (3rd edn, Cambridge University Press 2018).

104 Toomey, ‘Evolutionary Anamnesis’ (Footnote n 97) 55–56.

105 James R Kubricht, Keith J Holyoak, and Hongjing Lu, ‘Intuitive Physics: Current Research and Controversies’ (2017) 21 Trends in Cognitive Sciences 749.

106 HC Corben and Philip Stehle, Classical Mechanics (2nd edn, Dover 1994).

107 Henry E Smith, ‘On the Economy of Concepts in Property’ (2012) 160 U Penn L Rev 2097.

108 Ara Norenzayan and Steven J Heine, ‘Psychological Universals: What Are They and How Can We Know?’ (2005) 131 Psychological Bulletin 763, 764; DH Sliney, ‘What Is Light? The Visible Spectrum and Beyond’ (2016) 30 Eye 222, 225–226; CL Hardin, ‘A Spectral Reflectance Doth Not a Color Make’ (2003) 100 J Philosophy 191, 196–199.

109 An obligatory caveat – evolutionary psychologists frequently emphasize that our cognitive faculties presumptively evolved to solve survival problems in the so-called Environment of Evolutionary Adaptedness (some 2.6 million to 12,000 years ago) and that they may therefore be out of step with the structure of contemporary society. But we’re talking about metaphysics and the basic structure of the universe here, which presumably has not changed radically since then, and if it had, I imagine we would be, to put it mildly, feeling the selection pressure.

110 Husserl (Footnote n 60) 123, 128.

111 Jesse D Lopes, ‘Phenomenology as Proto-Computationalism: Do the Prolegomena Indicate a Computational Reading of the Logical Investigations?’ (2023) 39 Husserl Studies 47, 60.

113 Iulian D Toader, ‘Talking Past Each Other: Mach and Husserl on Thought Economy’ in F Stadler (ed), Ernest Mach – Life, Work, Influence (Springer Cham 2019) 213, 217; Colin McGinn, ‘Mach & Husserl’ (1972) 3 J British Society Phenomenology 146, 148; Milič Čapek, ‘Ernst Mach’s Biological Theory of Knowledge’ (1968) 18 Synthese 171; Paul Pojman, Ernst Mach’s Biological Theory of Knowledge (Dissertation, Department of History and Philosophy of Science, Indiana University, 15 June 2000).

114 Zenon W Pylyshyn, Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science (MIT 1986); Konrad Lorenz, ‘Kant’s Doctrine of the A Priori in the Light of Contemporary Biology’ in Michael Ruse (ed), Philosophy after Darwin (Princeton University Press 2010) 231.

115 Husserl (Footnote n 60) 129–30.

116 I am indebted to my former colleague John Humbach for this point.

117 Biswanath Mukhopadhyay and others, ‘Spectrum of Human Tails: A Report of Six Cases’ (2012) 17 J Indian Association Pediatric Surgeons 23.

118 Gould and Lewontin (Footnote n 41) 581.

119 Prum (Footnote n 41).

121 E Pivcevic, Husserl and Phenomenology (Routledge 1970) 3840; GJ Massey, ‘Some Reflections on Psychologism’ in T Seebohm, D Føllesdal, and J Mohanty (eds), Phenomenology and the Formal Sciences (Springer 1991) 186.

122 GP Baker and PMS Hacker, ‘Frege’s Anti-Psychologism’ in MA Notturno (ed), Perspectives on Psychologism (Brill 1989) 74; Massey (Footnote n 121) 183; D Føllesdal, Husserl und Frege: Ein Beitrag zur Beleuchtung der Entstehung der phänomenologischen Philosophie (H Aschehoug and Co 1958).

123 See Section 2.5.

124 Reinach (Footnote n 8) 4 (emphasis added).

125 Bertrand Russell, Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits (George Allen and Unwin 1948) 450.

126 Prum (Footnote n 41).

127 Plato, ‘Meno’ (WKC Guthrie tr) in Edith Hamilton and Huntington Carnes (eds), Plato: The Collected Dialogues (Princeton University Press 1961) 353384.

128 See Section 2.5.

129 Reinach, ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (Footnote n 18) 159.

130 Reinach, ‘Foundations’ (Footnote n 8) 11.

133 Frege, ‘Grundgesetze’ (Footnote n 69) 207.

134 Footnote ibid 205–206.

135 Footnote ibid 206 (emphasis added).

136 Husserl (Footnote n 60) 94.

138 Hanna (Footnote n 76) 270–274.

139 Nic Pizzolatto, ‘The Locked Room,’ True Detective (HBO January 16, 2014).

140 Husserl (Footnote n 60) 78–79.

141 Robert Nozick, Philosophical Investigations (Harvard University Press 1981) 201.

142 Marietta Auer, ‘Promising, Owning, Enacting: Adolf Reinach’s Phenomenology of Legal Speech Acts’ (Chapter 1, this volume).

143 JL Austin, How to Do Things with Words (JO Urmson and Marina Sibsà, eds Harvard University Press 1975) 164.

144 Bill Watson, ‘The Decline of Natural Law and the Rise of Exclusive Positivism’ (2022) 75 SMU Law Review Forum 174.

145 Husserl (Footnote n 60) 93.

146 David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (John Noon 1739) 335.

148 See Footnote n 48.

149 See Section 2.5. Concluding that we ought to think according to the certain mathematical entities does not demand Platonism about them, but it does demand that they bear some sort of genuine, nonarbitrary relationship to ontology.

150 See Section 2.2.

152 Auer (Chapter 1, this volume); Andrew S Gold and Henry E Smith, ‘Legal Concepts as a Deep Structure of the Law: Reinach’s A Priori in Action’ (Chapter 5, this volume).

References

Anderson, M and Simmons, LW, ‘Sexual Selection and Mate Choice’ (2006) 21 Trends Ecology and Evolution 296CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Auer, M, ‘Promising, Owning, Enacting: Adolf Reinach’s Phenomenology of Legal Speech Acts’ (Chapter 1, this volume)Google Scholar
Austin, JL, How to Do Things with Words (Urmson, JO and Sibsà, Marina, eds Harvard University Press 1975)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, GP and Hacker, PMS, ‘Frege’s Anti-psychologism’ in Notturno, MA (ed), Perspectives on Psychologism (Brill 1989) 74Google Scholar
Baltzer-Jaray, K, ‘Bogged Down in Ontologism and Realism’ in Parker, RKB (ed), The Idealism-Realism Debate among Edmund Husserl’s Early Followers and Critics (Springer Cham 2021) 151CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baltzer-Jaray, K, ‘Phenomenological Jurisprudence: A Reinterpretation of Adolf Reinach’s Jarhrbuch Essay’ in Simmons, JA and Hackett, JE (eds), Phenomenology for the Twenty-First Century (Palgrave Macmillan 2016) 118Google Scholar
Barton, NH, ‘The “New Synthesis”’ (2022) 119 Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences e2122147119CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beccacece, L, Abondio, P, Cilli, E, Restani, D, and Luiselli, D, ‘Human Genomics and the Biocultural Origin of Music’ (2021) 22 International J Molecular Sciences 5397, 5398CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boyer, P, ‘How Natural Selection Shapes Conceptual Structure: Human Intuitions and Concepts of Ownership’ in Margolis, E and Laurence, S (eds), The Conceptual Mind: New Directions in the Study of Concepts (MIT 2015) 185CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, DM, Evolutionary Psychology (5th edn, Pearson 2011)Google Scholar
Čapek, M, ‘Ernst Mach’s Biological Theory of Knowledge’ (1968) 18 Synthese 171CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N, Aspects of the Theory of Syntax (MIT 1965)Google Scholar
Chow, DCK, ‘Trashing Nihilism’ (1990) 65 Tulane Law Review 221Google Scholar
Cohen, FS, ‘Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach’ (1935) 35 Columbia L Rev 809CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coleman, JL, ‘The Architecture of Jurisprudence’ (2011) 121 Yale LJ 5Google Scholar
Corben, HC and Stehle, P, Classical Mechanics (2nd edn, Dover 1994)Google Scholar
Cosmides, L and Tooby, J, ‘Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, Part II: Case Study: A Computational Theory of Social Exchange’ (1989) 10 Ethology and Sociobiology 51CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crosby, JF, ‘A Brief Biography of Adolf Reinach’ in Crosby, JF (ed), The Apriori Foundations of the Civil Law: Along with the Lecture ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (De Gruyter 2012) viiiGoogle Scholar
Cunnane, SC, Harbige, LS and Crawford, MA, ‘The Importance of Energy and Nutrient Supply in Human Brain Evolution’ (1993) 9 Nutrition and Health 219CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Darwin, C, The Origin of Species (First Signet 2003)Google Scholar
Dennett, DC, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life (Penguin 1996)Google Scholar
Dennett, DC, Consciousness Explained (Back Bay 1992)Google Scholar
Dworkin, R, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press 1978)Google Scholar
Enoch, D, ‘The Epistemological Challenge to Metanormative Realism: How Best to Understand It, and How to Cope with It’ (2010) 148 Philosophical Studies 413CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erdmann, B, Logik, Logische Elementarlehre (Max Niemeyer 1892)Google Scholar
Finnis, J, Natural Law and Natural Rights (2nd edn, Oxford University Press 2011)Google Scholar
Fitzpatrick, WJ, ‘Why There Is No Darwinian Dilemma for Ethical Realism’ in Bergmann, M and Kain, P (eds), Challenges to Moral and Religious Belief: Disagreement and Evolution (Oxford University Press 2014) 237CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Føllesdal, D, Husserl und Frege: Ein Beitrag zur Beleuchtung der Entstehung der phänomenologischen Philosophie (H Aschehoug und Co 1958)Google Scholar
Frege, G, ‘The Foundations of Arithmetic’, in Beaney, M (ed and tr), The Frege Reader (Blackwell 1997)Google Scholar
Frege, G, ‘Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Volume I’ in Beaney, M (ed and tr), The Frege Reader (Blackwell 1997) 194Google Scholar
Frege, G, ‘Book Review of Husserl 1891’ (1894) 103 Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 313Google Scholar
Freud, S, The Interpretation of Dreams (Basic 2010)Google Scholar
Gannon, G, ‘A Critique of Evolutionary Psychology’ (2010) 4 Psychology, Evolution and Gender 173CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, J, From Personal Life to Private Law (Oxford University Press 2018)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geisler, WS and Diehl, RL, ‘A Bayesian Approach to the Evolution of Perceptual and Cognitive Systems’ (2003) 27 Cognitive Science 379CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gödel, F, ‘An Introduction to Moritz Geiger’s Psychological Contribution on Empathy’ (2015) 8 Dialogues Philosophy, Mental Neuro Sciences 161Google Scholar
Gold, AS and Smith, HE, ‘Legal Concepts as a Deep Structure of Law: Reinach’s A Priori in Action’ (Chapter 5, this volume)Google Scholar
Gould, SJ and Lewontin, RC, ‘The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme’ (1979) 205 Proceedings of the Royal Society Biology 581Google Scholar
Griffiths, DJ and Schroeter, DF, Introduction to Quantum Mechanics (3rd edn, Cambridge University Press 2018)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haack, S, ‘The Pragmatist Tradition: Lessons for Legal Theorists’ (2018) 95 Washington U L Rev 1049Google Scholar
Hanna, R, ‘Husserl’s Prolegomena and the Truth in Psychologism’ (1993) 53 Philosophy Phenomenological Res 251CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, CL, ‘A Spectral Reflectance Doth Not a Color Make’ (2003) 100 J Philosophy 191CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haruki, M, ‘On a Trade-Off in the Evolution of Ownership’ (2018) 38 Economics Bulletin 1257Google Scholar
Heidegger, M, An Introduction to Metaphysics 6–7 (R Manheim tr, Yale University Press 1959)Google Scholar
Hershovitz, S, ‘The End of Jurisprudence’ (2015) 124 Yale LJ 1160Google Scholar
Hofman, MA, ‘Evolution of the Human Brain: When Bigger Is Better’ (2014) 8 Frontiers Neuroscience 1Google Scholar
Hume, D, A Treatise of Human Nature (John Noon 1739)Google Scholar
Husserl, E, Logical Investigations, Vol. I (JN Findlay tr, Routledge 2001)Google Scholar
Jacquette, D, Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychologism: Critical and Historical Readings on the Psychological Turn in Philosophy (Springer 2006)Google Scholar
James, W, Principles of Psychology (originally published 1890, Harvard University Press 1981)Google Scholar
James, W, Essays in Radical Empiricism (Harvard University Press 1912)Google Scholar
Jones, OD and Kurzban, R, ‘Intuitions of Punishment’ (2010) 77 U Chicago L Rev 1633Google Scholar
Jones, OD and Goldsmith, TH, ‘Law and Behavioral Biology’ (2005) 105 Columbia L Rev 405Google Scholar
Kubricht, JR, Holyoak, KJ, and Lu, H, ‘Intuitive Physics: Current Research and Controversies’ (2017) 21 Trends Cognitive Sciences 749CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kusch, M, ‘Psychologism’ in EN Zalta (ed), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (online 2020)Google Scholar
Kusch, M, Psychologism: A Case Study in the Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge (Routledge 1995)Google Scholar
Ladyman, J, ‘The Foundations of Structuralism and the Metaphysics of Relations’ in Marmodoro, A and Yates, D (eds), The Metaphysics of Relations 177, 179–180 (Oxford University Press 2015)Google Scholar
Lehar, S, ‘Gestalt Isomorphism and the Primacy of Subjective Conscious Experience: A Gestalt Bubble Model’ (2003) 26 Behavioral Brain Sciences 375CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leigh, EG Jr, ‘The Group Selection Controversy’ (2009) 23 J Evolutionary Biology 6CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levy, N, ‘Evolutionary Psychology, Human Universals, and the Standard Social Science Model’ (2004) 19 Biology and Philosophy 459CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lopes, JD, ‘Phenomenology as Proto-Computationalism: Do the Prolegomena Indicate a Computational Reading of the Logical Investigations?’ (2023) 39 Husserl Studies 47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lorenz, K, ‘Kant’s Doctrine of the A Priori in the Light of Contemporary Biology’ in Ruse, M (ed), Philosophy after Darwin (Princeton University Press 2010) 231CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Massey, GJ, ‘Some Reflections on Psychologism’ in Seebohm, T, Føllesdal, D, and Mohanty, J (eds), Phenomenology and the Formal Sciences (Springer 1991) 183CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCrae, RR and Costa, PT Jr., ‘Personality Trait Structure as a Human Universal’ (1997) 52 American Psychologist 509, 509CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McGinn, C, ‘Mach & Husserl’ (1972) 3 J British Society Phenomenology 146CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLeod, I, Legal Theory (6th edn, Red Globe Press 2012)Google Scholar
Mill, JS, A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive (first published in 1843; Cambridge University Press 2011)Google Scholar
Moore, MS, ‘Moral Reality Revisited’ (1992) 90 Michigan L Rev 2424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, MS, ‘The Interpretive Turn in Modern Theory: A Turn for the Worse?’ (1989) 40 Stanford L Rev 871CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, MS, ‘Metaphysics, Epistemology, and Legal Theory’ (1987) 60 Southern California L Rev 453Google Scholar
Mozzi, A, Forni, D, Clerici, M, Pozzoli, U, Mascheretti, S, Guerini, FR, Riva, S, Bresolin, N, Cagliani, R, and Sironi, M, ‘The Evolutionary History of Genes Involved in Spoken and Written Language: Beyond FOXP2’ (2016) 6 Scientific Rep 22157, 22157CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mukhopadhyay, B, Shukla, RM, Mukhopadhyay, M, Mandal, KC, Haldar, P, and Benare, A, ‘Spectrum of Human Tails: A Report of Six Cases’ (2012) 17 J Indian Association Pediatric Surgeons 23CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Natorp, P, ‘On the Question of Logical Method in Relation to Edmund Husserl’s Prolegomena to Pure Logic’ in Mohanty, JN (ed), Readings on Edmund Husserl’s Logical Investigations (Springer 1977)Google Scholar
Navarrete, A, van Schaik, CP and Isler, K, ‘Energetics and the Evolution of Human Brain Size’ (2011) 480 Nature 91CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Neumann, JV and Morgenstern, O, Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (Princeton University Press 1944)Google Scholar
Nichols, S and Grantham, T, ‘Adaptive Complexity and Phenomenal Consciousness’ (2000) 67 Philosophy Science 648CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norenzayan, A and Heine, SJ, ‘Psychological Universals: What Are They and How Can We Know?’ (2005) 131 Psychological Bulletin 763CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nozick, R, Philosophical Explanations (Harvard University Press 1981)Google Scholar
Patrick, CJ, ‘The Long-Term Promise of Evolutionary Psychology for the Law’ (2016) 48 Arizona State LJ 995Google Scholar
Pinker, S, The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature (Penguin 2002)Google Scholar
Pinker, S, How the Mind Works (Norton 1997)Google Scholar
Pinker, S and Bloom, P, ‘Natural Language and Natural Selection’ (1990) 13 Behavioral Brain Sciences 707CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pivcevic, E, Husserl and Phenomenology (Routledge 1970)Google Scholar
Pizzolatto, N, ‘The Locked Room,’ True Detective (HBO January 16, 2014)Google Scholar
Plotkin, H, Evolution in Mind: An Introduction to Evolutionary Psychology (Harvard University Press 2000)Google Scholar
Pojman, P, Ernst Mach’s Biological Theory of Knowledge (Dissertation, Department of History and Philosophy of Science, Indiana University, June 15, 2000)Google Scholar
Posner, R, Economic Analysis of Law (7th edn, Aspen 2007)Google Scholar
Prum, RO, The Evolution of Beauty: How Darwin’s Forgotten Theory of Mate Choice Shapes the Animal World – And Us (Doubleday 2017)Google Scholar
Putnam, P, ‘Realism and Reason’ (1977) 50 Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association 483CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, ZW, Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science (MIT 1986)Google Scholar
Reinach, A, ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (D Willard tr) in Crosby, JF (ed), The Apriori Foundations of the Civil Law: Along with the Lecture ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (Ontos Verlag 2012) 145CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reinach, A, ‘On the Concept of Causality in the Criminal Law’ (B Brogaard, tr) (2009) 1 Libertarian Papers 1Google Scholar
Reinach, A, ‘William James and Pragmatism’ in Smith, B (tr and ed), Speech Act and Sachverhalt (Springer 1987) 291CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reinach, A, ‘The Apriori Foundations of the Civil Law’ (John F Crosby tr, 1983) 3 Aletheia 1142, reprinted in Adolf Reinach, The Apriori Foundations of the Civil Law: Along with the Lecture ‘Concerning Phenomenology’ (John F Crosby ed, Ontos Verlag 2012), originally published as Adolf Reinach, Die apriorischen Grundlagen des bürgerlichen Rechtes, 1(2) Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung (Max Niemeyer 1913), 685–847Google Scholar
Ridley, M, The Red Queen: Sex and the Evolution of Human Nature (2nd edn, Harper 1993)Google Scholar
Rose, S and Rose, H, Alas Poor Darwin: Arguments against Evolutionary Psychology (Crown 2001)Google Scholar
Ruse, M, Taking Darwin Seriously: A Naturalistic Approach to Philosophy (2nd edn, Prometheus 1986)Google Scholar
Russell, B, Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits (George Allen and Unwin 1948)Google Scholar
Schacter, DL, Gilbert, DT, and Wegner, DM, Psychology (5th edn, Worth 2007)Google Scholar
Schaus, S, ‘A Simple Model of Torts and Moral Wrongs’ (2022) 97 Notre Dame L Rev 1029Google Scholar
Schuhman, K and Smith, B, ‘Adolf Reinach: An Intellectual Biography’ in Mulligan, K (ed), Speech Act and Sachverhalt: Reinach and the Foundations of Realist Phenomenology (Springer 1987)Google Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R, ‘The Possibility of Metaethics’ (2010) 90 Boston U L Rev 479Google Scholar
Shapiro, SJ, ‘The Hart-Dworkin Debate: A Short Guide for the Perplexed’ in Ripstein, A (ed), Ronald Dworkin (Cambridge University Press 2007)Google Scholar
Sherlock, JM, Zietsch, BP, Tybur, JM, and Jern, P, ‘The Quantitative Genetics of Disgust Sensitivity’ (2016) 16 Emotion 43CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sherwood, CC, Stimpson, CD, Raghanti, MA, Wildman, DE, Uddin, M, Grossman, LI, Goodman, M, Redmond, JC, Bonar, CJ, Erwin, JM, and Hof, P, ‘Evolution of Increased Glia-Neuron Ratios in the Human Frontal Cortex’ (2006) 103 Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 13606CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Singer, JW, ‘The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and Legal Theory’ (1984) 94 Yale LJ 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skarsaune, KO, ‘Darwin and Moral Realism: Survival of the Iffiest’ (2011) 152 Philosophical Studies 229CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sliney, DH, ‘What Is Light? The Visible Spectrum and Beyond’ (2016) 30 Eye 222CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sloman, L, Gilbert, P, and Hasey, G, ‘Evolved Mechanisms in Depression: The Role and Interaction of Attachment and Social Rank in Depression’ (2003) 74 J Affective Disorders 107CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smith, B, ‘On the Austrianness of Austrian Economics’ (1990) 4 Critical Review 212CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, HE, ‘On the Economy of Concepts in Property’ (2012) 160 U Penn L Rev 2097Google Scholar
Street, S, ‘A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value’ (2006) 127 Philosophical Studies 109CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toader, ID, ‘Talking Past Each Other: Mach and Husserl on Thought Economy’ in Stadler, F (ed), Ernest Mach: Life, Work, Influence (Springer Cham 2019) 213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tooby, J and Cosmides, L, ‘Conceptual Foundations of Evolutionary Psychology’ in Buss, DM (ed), The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (Wiley 2021) 5Google Scholar
Toomey, J, ‘Property’s Boundaries’ (2023) 109 Virginia L Rev 131Google Scholar
Toomey, J, ‘Evolutionary Anamnesis’ (2022) 37 Biology and Philosophy 55CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van de Vondervoort, JW, Meinz, P, and Friedman, O, ‘Children’s Judgments about Ownership Rights and Body Rights: Evidence for a Common Basis’ (2017) 155 J Experimental Child Psychology 1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vargha-Khadem, F, Gadian, DG, Copp, A, and Mishkin, M, ‘FOXP2 and the Neuroanatomy of Speech and Language’ (2005) 6 Nature Rev Neuroscience 131CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Watson, B, ‘The Decline of Natural Law and the Rise of Exclusive Positivism’ (2022) 75 SMU Law Review Form 174CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watson, JD and Crick, FH, ‘Molecular Structure of Nucleic Acids: A Structure for Deoxyribose Nucleic Acid’ (1953) 171 Nature 737CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, BJ, The Property Species: Mind, Yours, and the Human Mind (Oxford University Press 2020)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, DS, Dietrich, E, and Clark, AB, ‘On the Inappropriate Use of the Naturalistic Fallacy in Evolutionary Psychology’ (2003) 18 Biology & Philosophy 669CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, EO, Sociobiology: The New Synthesis (Harvard University Press 1975)Google Scholar
Wundt, W, ‘On Psychological Methods’ (1883) 1 Philosophische Studien 1Google Scholar

Accessibility standard: Unknown

Accessibility compliance for the HTML of this book is currently unknown and may be updated in the future.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge-org.demo.remotlog.com is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×