Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-br6xx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-10-05T15:16:41.227Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Corporate law as public policy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 September 2025

Jonathan Hardman*
Affiliation:
Senior Lecturer in Company and Commercial Law, Edinburgh Law School, University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh, UK Honorary Associate Professor, University of Auckland, Auckland, New Zealand
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Corporate law is a public policy balance. The state creates the corporation and provides its legal features. ‘Micro’ aspects of the corporation, like separate legal personality, limited liability, and perpetual succession, were each provided by the state for public benefits rather than for their evident private benefits. Widespread utilisation of the corporation provides ‘macro’ public benefits. Corporations can also harm third parties, and the state should balance benefits and harms. Yet modern corporate law theory downplays the state’s role. Those who focus on the state also tend to miss the state’s foundational role in setting the contours of the corporation and corporate law and encouraging certain behaviour. Identifying that corporate law is, descriptively, best seen as a public policy outcome shows the state is not a benign white knight which can only restrain corporations but instead should be seen as culpable in any perceived social harms caused by corporations.

Information

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Millennium Economics Ltd

Introduction

This article reconceptualises modern corporate law by identifying the state’s core role. The state sets the institutional environment of corporate law, the formal rules of the corporate game which allow for individual institutional arrangements of specific companies (Williamson, Reference Williamson2000).Footnote 1 Whilst industry bodies set some corporate law rules, the state sets most (Chan and Lim, Reference Chan and Lim2024). All institutional arrangements (individual companies) are set up under and governed by corporate law as part of the institutional environment. Yet modern corporate law theory often misses the state. Companies cannot exist without, and obtain beneficial legal features from, the state. State provision of the corporate form is said to lower transaction costs for certain parties (Williamson, Reference Williamson1991). This argument usually means the state should only use corporate law to lower transaction costs (Easterbrook and Fischel, Reference Easterbrook and Fischel1989). I argue the state is much more foundational than such an argumentation allows, but even on its own terms such argument must mean some business activity only occurs because state provision of the corporate form lowers transaction costs: at the margin, some otherwise unprofitable ventures become profitable due to the corporation’s lower transaction costs. Even the narrowest conception of the state in corporate law, then, means that it makes such ventures viable, encourages them and others, and provides more private profit for those setting up businesses than they would have without the corporate form.

Corporate law provides corporations and connected parties with legal benefits not available to other business forms. State rules provide companies with separate legal personality, perpetuity, and limited liability for connected parties. These features are legal deviations from background rules, bestowed by the state for particular public policy reasons. This article argues that dominant modern legal conceptualisations of the company – as purely the sum of its parts or as something autonomous created by the sum of its parts – miss the state’s core role when theorising the company and corporate law, as they both focus on private notions of the company and do not cater for the state’s role.

Legally, each individual feature and the sum (corporate law) is the outcome of a tacit public policy decision. This package provides public benefits but is also argued to cause considerable harm. Accordingly, the current terms of corporate law are, descriptively, a public policy balance. The state should set corporate law to maximise its net social benefits.

Non-legal disciplines have grappled with the state’s role in corporate life (Ciepley, Reference Ciepley2013; Singer, Reference Singer2019). This article’s legal analysis can be helpful to advance arguments across various disciplines. Ciepley argues that corporations transcend a public and private divide (2013). Yet the legal analysis outlined in this article demonstrates that the private aspects exist because of, and in response to, the public aspects. Turner identified that features of modern corporate law required legislative changes, which then drove economic growth (Turner, Reference Turner and Wells2018), and this article’s analysis helps demonstrate ongoing state decision-making in such analysis. Ireland, Grigg-Spall, and Kelly argued that the modern corporate form was driven by requirements driven by capital to further capitalism (Reference Ireland, Grigg-Spall and Kelly1987). This article’s analysis unveils the state’s involvement in these developments.

Historical corporate law analysis used to explore the role of the state (e.g., Maitland, Reference Maitland1900 and Reference Maitland1905; Laski, Reference Laski1916; Gierke, Reference Gierke2014, xx–xxx). This article aims to reintroduce such state-centricity into corporate law discourse. Most modern legal scholarship makes mere passing reference to the state. Micheler notes in passing that corporate law is set by the state but argues that it purely facilitates group activity (Micheler, Reference Micheler2021). Hart argued that law sets the background rules of the corporate game but did not unpack the state’s role in setting these rules (Hart, Reference Hart1953). Bruner argues that the corporation is ‘technology’, which the state can alter as it likes (Bruner, Reference Bruner2022), as the state is part of the wider corporate ecosystem (ch. 2). This implies an autonomous corporate form that the state can ‘adjust’ but downplays the state’s role in initially shaping such a form. The state is seen as having a minor role in setting some of the ‘meta-rules’ of corporations (Gindis and Micheler, Reference Gindis and Micheler2024). Even where the state is discussed in modern corporate law discourse, it is done cursorily, without focus on its foundational role.

Some legal scholars portray the state as a passive and background actor. Some emphasise the state’s historical role in setting corporate law (Watson, Reference Watson2022). Some argue the state bounds private decisions – Moore argued private corporate governance decisions take place in the ‘shadow’ of public decisions (Moore, Reference Moore2013) and attacked contractarianism in a ‘prelude’ to a wider focus on the state in corporate law (Moore, Reference Moore2014) that is still lacking. Some focus on the state effecting incorporation (Watson, Reference Watson2019), most recently with Bottomley stating that by doing so, the state provides ‘authorisation’ for certain types of behaviour (Bottomley, Reference Bottomley2024), arguing the state affects private decisions (Hardman, Reference Hardman2023). However, this article shows the state’s foundational and ongoing role in corporate law. The state provides certain legal benefits to, and in respect of, the corporate form alone (Wright, Reference Wright, Irwin and Sylla2010). Associated private benefits encourage the use of the corporate form over alternative legal vehicles. This article adds to the literature by focusing on the state’s ongoing foundational role in corporate law, which is either ignored, briefly noted, or construed as something that can ‘intervene’ in autonomous activity.

Two implications arise from such conceptualisation. First, the state is not passively deciding whether to intervene in a private matter. If one argues that companies operate socially suboptimally, then one should see the state as culpable. The state is not a pure white knight waiting to only beneficently act. Second, this argument is limited to corporate law. It does not mean that the state is the dominant force within any individual company. The decision to establish a company is a voluntary one undertaken by those in business, and a real and autonomous entity can be so created. It does mean that academic lawyers should study the rules that the state provides exclusively to companies and the state’s reasons for providing such rules. As corporate forms arise under, and subject to, the incentives set by corporate law, though, such arguments have knock-on effects in respect of the corporate form. The state solely sets corporate law, which in turn bounds and sets features of the corporate form, including the incentives faced by those who utilise the form, and indeed how attractive the form is for use. Features of corporate law encourage certain behaviours by incentivising certain outcomes (Hardman, Reference Hardman, Wood, Elina and Tribe2025). As such, whilst this article focuses on corporate law, its analysis mostly equally applies to the corporation itself.

I follow usual practice and use the term ‘state’ broadly (Bottomley, Reference Bottomley2024, 5) to draw attention to the public aspects of corporations, which are normally missed as corporate law discourse focuses on private aspects (Wolfe, Reference Wolfe1993). Accordingly, two core assumptions are made about the state until slightly relaxed later. First, that it is a single, monolithic actor. The state is considerably more complex. It has multiple different parts, which adopt the state’s ‘mask’ in different contexts (Runciman, Reference Runciman1997). Individuals have multiple roles (Kantorowicz, Reference Kantorowicz1997). Various parts/roles may conflict. US states (not the federal government) control their individual incorporation processes, leading to tensions between states themselves and between states and the federal government (Hamill, Reference Hamill1999). Evident tensions arise between legislative and judicial branches: trade union rights in the UK experienced a ‘pendulum’ with the UK Parliament increasing rights, only for courts to discover new torts to neuter how such rights operated in practice (Wedderburn, Reference Wedderburn1986, 17). Similar dynamics are underway in Delaware in respect of restraint of controlling shareholders (Bainbridge, Reference Bainbridge2025). Both branches could conflict with the executive and administrative branches, either when the state holds shares (Lim, Reference Lim2021) or with administrating central registries. The combined activities of these different bodies can exceed the sum of their parts (Pettit Reference Pettit2023). The article’s purpose is to argue the foundational role of various parts of the state in corporate law. As such, it matters not which part of the state is present, merely that a part is present. The state can mean any or all of these different aspects; it does not matter for my argument. In the same vein, when I discuss state culpability in this article, I refer to general state culpability rather than exploring nuances between different state actors. This is because it does not matter for my purposes – it is sufficient for my purposes that any part of the state should be perceived as culpable.

Second, I assume a utilitarian state acting for the public benefit (or at least its perception of such benefit). Yet different state organs are open to capture by interested groups, or regulatory capture (Stigler, Reference Stigler1971; Slayton and Clark-Ginsberg, Reference Slayton and Clark-Ginsberg2018; Veldman and Willmott, Reference Veldman and Willmott2020). Similarly, some corrupt officials aim for personal benefit rather than carrying out their functions for the purposes provided (Andriosopoulos and Loncan, Reference Andriosopoulos and Loncan2025). Yet for this article, the key is that state organs can and do decide corporate law. If state actors use powers for improper purposes, then accountability should be demanded. This does not change that the state does control such aspects. How policy balance is concluded by state organs is beyond my scope and different from my core argument – which is that descriptively all corporate law, and by extension the corporate form, arises from a public policy balance, however tacit it may be and however skewed such balance may be by improper interests. Pulling these two assumptions together, then, lets us assume that the state acts singly and deliberately and does what it is meant to.

The rest of this article proceeds as follows. The next part explores the state’s role in corporate law, and the part after that how this is missed in modern corporate legal theory. The following part explores potential social benefits and harms, and that corporate law’s policy balance arises from a balance of the two, however tacit it may be. The final part outlines implications.

Micro corporate legal deviations

First, then, the corporate form, and those who benefit from it, receive individual legal advantages from the state not available elsewhere. Each is a deviation from the background rules (von Mehren, Reference von Mehren1990) which would otherwise apply. Whilst most corporate law rules are longstanding, they also are deviations from the usual legal position, representing a series of legal exceptions created for, and in respect of, corporations. Private law provides rules that govern interactions between persons, and corporate law is a series of deviations from these rules. Such basic rules applied to initial stock market interactions (Banner, Reference Banner1998, ch. 1). These rules, though, frequently were sub-par, which resulted in the market being regulated by rules which deviated from these background rules (Mahoney, Reference Mahoney1999). For example, most private purchases operate on the basis of ‘caveat emptor’, or buyer beware (Buchanan, Reference Buchanan1970). Yet in Derry v Peek ((1889) 14 App. Cas. 337) such background rules were held to mean that shareholders could not receive damages from directors who made false statements in prospectuses which were only negligent but not fraudulent (Lobban Reference Lobban1996; Edelman, Reference Edelman2010). The Directors Liability Act 1890 was passed the following year to change this position, and still today officers are held liable for any misleading statements on share issues which are negligent (Gullifer and Payne, Reference Gullifer and Payne2020, ch 10), a legal deviation from the background rule. I call each particular part of corporate law a ‘micro’ deviation, contrasting with the corporation as a whole (the ‘macro’ discussed later). I focus on three foundational aspects of the corporation – separate legal personality, limited liability (Hansmann and Kraakman, Reference Hansmann and Kraakman2000), and perpetuity. Each is a deviation from background rules, providing private benefits for corporate insiders. However, the UK state provided each for specific overt public policy reasons rather than because of the individual private benefits.

First, the legal nature of separate legal personality is uncertain (Macgregor, Reference Macgregor2020) and can risk circularity – at times the company claims separate legal personality because it can sue, and at times claims it can sue because it has separate legal personality (Cohen, Reference Cohen1935). Modern analysis sees it as a ‘convenient heuristic formula’ for the right to sue, be sued, hold property and contract, and not academically interesting (Kraakman et al., Reference Kraakman2017, 2). Yet, it is important – to treat a company as a person puts it, legally, on the spectrum of law’s array of persons (Naffine, Reference Naffine2003). As such, discourse on whether other non-humans, like animals, should have legal personality inevitably discusses corporate legal personality (Kurki, Reference Kurki2022). Conferring legal personality is a gateway to enjoying other rights, which can amplify private benefits of shareholders. If a company can hold property, that property must be transferred to the company away from, say, a shareholder (a rivalrous right). However, legal personality introduces the possibility of ‘duplicative’ rights which exist in addition to shareholders’ personal rights (Thompson, Reference Thompson, Barnes and Hardman2024), which causes considerable conceptual uncertainty in respect of corporate constitutional rights (Gindis and Singer, Reference Gindis and Singer2022). Giving legal personhood to non-humans causes conceptual difficulties (Buocz and Eisenberger, Reference Buocz and Eisenberger2023) and transcends law – other social sciences need to conceptualise it (Geldart, Reference Geldart1911; Ripken, Reference Ripken2019).

Law rarely provides legal personality to non-humans: many social groupings, for example, unincorporated sports clubs, do not receive it (Laski, Reference Laski1916), despite having a more ‘real claim’ to a social identity than most corporate forms (MacCormick, Reference MacCormick2007). Groups not receiving separate legal personality is the background rule, and corporate law provides a deviation for the corporate form. The state decided to facilitate general incorporation of business corporations with legal personality (Watson, Reference Watson2019; Bottomley, Reference Bottomley2024). In England, this was so they could be sued: partnership (the then-dominant legal vehicle) law provided that on every ‘joint stock company’ partner change, any litigation against the partnership lapsed and needed to be restarted (Bellenden Ker, Reference Bellenden Ker1837; Gladstone et al., Reference Gladstone1844). This obviously caused problems for third parties and was open to opportunistic abuse. It also complicated the administration of the business (Freeman, Pearson, and Taylor, Reference Freeman, Pearson and Taylor2007) and adjudicating internal disputes (Televantos, Reference Televantos2020, 26–31). Granting corporate separate legal personality and mandating its use for larger business vehicles resolved these issues. Corporate legal personality provided private benefits – like rendering shareholder exit irrelevant, thus allowing continuity of form (with advantages of this discussed below) (Ayotte and Hansmann, Reference Ayotte and Hansmann2015). It was, though, justified for English companies due to specific public benefits (the ability to sue larger businesses). It remains bestowed by the state through the state-provided and state-run process of incorporation (Watson, Reference Watson2019).

So is, second, shareholder limited liability, which is quite controversial. Technically, it is a feature of shareholding rather than the corporation itself, but most texts treat it as foundational to the corporation (Kraakman et al., Reference Kraakman2017, ch. 1). Most people have limited liability in respect of each other’s interactions (Easterbrook and Fischel, Reference Easterbrook and Fischel1985), but it is not possible in other UK business forms for every connected party to be able to limit their liability when seeking a good profit (Hardman, Reference Hardman, Wood, Elina and Tribe2025). Limited liability brings many benefits – making shares fungible and priced solely on business performance, allowing accurate capital market pricing (Halpern et al., Reference Halpern, Trebilcock and Turnbull1980; Grundfest, Reference Grundfest1992; Woodward, Reference Woodward1985; Blankenberg et al., Reference Blankenberg, Plesch and Wilkinson2010). Conversely, limited liability arguably encourages shareholders to push risk onto third parties (Hansmann and Kraakman, Reference Hansmann and Kraakman1991; Goodhart and Lastra, Reference Goodhart and Lastra2020). Such concerns predate the statutory introduction of limited liability (Saville, Reference Saville1956). Sometimes, creditors can simply adjust the price of their debt to internalise any increased risk, like any higher risk caused by limited liability (Jackson and Kronman, Reference Jackson and Kronman1979). However, involuntary creditors cannot change their ‘price’ (Hansmann and Kraakman, Reference Hansmann and Kraakman1991). Many voluntary creditors also cannot change the ‘price’ of their ‘debt’, including those without sufficient bargaining power and those lacking knowledge of precise organisational form and/or associated legal risks – such as most customers, suppliers, consumers and employees (Bebchuk and Fried, Reference Bebchuk and Fried1996). This provides a broad category of constituents who cannot charge more to reflect higher risk. Whether these (and others) harms are outweighed by the benefits of limited liability is purely a question of public policy.

Some features of limited liability could be constructed before provision by the state (Getzler and MacNair, Reference Getzler and Macnair2006), but not all (Harris, Reference Harris2020a). Whilst English courts upheld limited liability provisions in express contracts (e.g., Halket v Merchant Traders’ (1849) 13 QB 960), they held unilateral statements ‘nugatory as to strangers’ who had not voluntarily agreed to such limited liability (Walburn v Ingilby (1833) 39 ER 604, 609). The UK state needed to legislate to provide a legal deviation to enable corporate limited liability, which came in 1855, 11 years after general incorporation.

Justifications for such an introduction abound, each of which ultimately argues political pressure drove the legislative change. A push came from accumulated savings in the UK’s affluent Home Counties needing somewhere to invest as an outsider (Cottrell, Reference Cottrell1980, 45). Frustrations with the Crimean War led to a disaffected middle class, who also wanted to financially advance through the same means (Mackie, Reference Mackie2011). Social desire to provide such advantages to lower socio-economic groupings encouraged the change (Loftus, Reference Loftus2002). Christian Socialists encouraged it as an avenue for working-class savings (McQueen, Reference McQueen2016, ch. 3). Lawyers encouraged limited liability to maximise their income (Smith, Reference Smith2020). It was also seen as a general lever to advance economic growth (Griffin, Reference Griffin2004). All of which are strong public policy reasons to provide limited liability to shareholders. Each such reason facilitates private benefit from the corporate form, but for a wider social/political purpose. Private benefits were encouraged because they served a public purpose. Each such argument is predicated upon wider public policy considerations, not because enabling private benefit at all costs is axiomatically corporate law’s role.

Third, companies are perpetual (Schwartz, Reference Schwartz2012). We do not provide perpetuity for other forms of business vehicle. UK law has long restricted perpetuity for trusts (Gallanis, Reference Gallanis2000), as do parts of the US (Horowitz and Sitkoff, Reference Horowitz and Sitkoff2014). This prohibition arose from fear of previous generations’ ‘dead hand’ restricting activity tomorrow – a clear policy reason to regulate private ordering (Simes, Reference Simes1955; Haskins, Reference Haskins1977). Similarly, and as noted above, partnerships end (and restart) on partner change (Hurt, Reference Hurt2019). Corporate perpetuity provides a private benefit by avoiding taxable events occurring on transfer of business assets (conveyance from ‘old’ to ‘new’ vehicle will be taxed). Yet the perpetuity of companies was introduced for the public benefit, namely to facilitate economic growth (Dari-Mattiacci et al., Reference Dari-Mattiacci, Gelderblom, Jonker and Perotti2017).

The above rules are Anglo-American. Islamic states were reticent to provide corporate legal personality (Kuran, Reference Kuran2005; Anello, Arafa, and Gramitto Ricci, Reference Anello, Arafa and Gramitto Ricci2021). The US and the UK differ in the precise detail of certain corporate legal features (Harris and Lamoreaux, Reference Harris and Lamoreaux2019; Gower, Reference Gower1956). Such differences reinforce my argument – different states provide (or do not) different corporate legal deviations for different policy reasons at different times.

Corporate law consists of a series of further deviations from normal background law which provide private benefits for wider public policy reasons. Shareholders cannot withdraw capital, facilitating investment in illiquid assets (Blair, Reference Blair2003), but the UK rule originated to let third parties rely on a company’s publicly disclosed capital (Trevor v Whitworth (1887) 12 App Cas 409). Throughout the history of company law, we see private advantages provided to those who use the corporate form, and the form itself, because of the public advantages perceived by the state. The features were provided because of their public advantage, not because they brought private benefits to corporate insiders.

Policy considerations transcend individual ‘micro’ corporate features and include state provision of the corporation (the ‘macro’). New York introduced general incorporation in 1811 for specific industries to encourage investment (Seavoy, Reference Seavoy1972), balanced against the state’s advantages as an investor in existing corporations with limited competition (Sylla, Legler, and Wallis, Reference Sylla, Legler and Wallis1987), and indeed corruption of officials (Bodenhorn, Reference Bodenhorn, Glaeser and Goldin2006). It was ‘an extremely political matter’ (Sylla, Reference Sylla1985, 112), not purely to facilitate private ordering. General incorporation was traditionally viewed to diminish the state’s role (Butler, Reference Butler1986; Bainbridge and Henderson, Reference Bainbridge and Henderson2016, 68-69), implying a one-way ratchet in which the state provides such legal deviations but can never vary or remove them. This is not the way that states or legislative processes work (Jensen and Meckling, Reference Jensen and Meckling1978). General incorporation contributed to the corporation’s enduring popularity (Grandy, Reference Grandy1989) but still relies on state administration (Watson, Reference Watson2019). The state’s role transcends incorporation, as it continues to provide these legal deviations with private benefits for utilising companies. These features were imbued for public purposes. Should the state ascertain, then, that these features no longer serve such purposes, the state can and should change corporate law and vary/remove them or require companies to provide a greater public benefit. Such legal deviations continuing show the result of an ongoing tacit policy balance.

Corporate law’s missing state

Modern corporate law scholarship ignores this tacit policy balance, as historic baggage emphasises particular argumentation structures/tropes. Around 100 years ago, the nature of the company was a ‘virtual obsession’ amongst corporate law academics (Horwitz, Reference Horwitz1992, 101): whether the company was a concession from the state (Koessler, Reference Koessler1949), something real (Maitland, Reference Maitland1900; Pollock, Reference Pollock1911), or merely the aggregate of its parts (Morawetz, Reference Morawetz1886, 1-2). Concerns that this nature was merely whatever law said it was (Dewey, Reference Dewey1926) and that the truth was more nuanced (Radin, Reference Radin1932) ended the debate (Cheffins, Reference Cheffins2004, 39), and it was dismissed as irrelevant and ‘dead’ (Hart, Reference Hart1953, 17). A famous Dutch professor requested a moratorium on any publications on the topic without evident and clear practical utility (Bouckaert, Reference Bouckaert1991, 156). For overviews of this debate, see Gindis (Reference Gindis2009), Mark (Reference Mark1987), and Hager (Reference Hager1989).

Aggregate approaches (like Easterbrook and Fischel, Reference Easterbrook and Fischel1989) dominate modern Anglo-American scholarship (Gubler, Reference Gubler2024). Alternatives, though, remain (Claassen, Reference Claassen2023). A perennial concern is that the corporation benefits few but damages many (Fairfax, Reference Fairfax2006; Ireland, Reference Ireland2010), particularly the environment (Sjåfjell et al., Reference Sjåfjell, Johnston, Anker-Sørensen, Millon, Sjåfjell and Richardson2015). Corporate social impact discourse increasingly focuses on law (Mayer, Reference Mayer2017) and easily connects to this ancient historical debate. Some utilise ‘real entity’ approaches (Micheler, Reference Micheler2021; Micheler, Reference Micheler2024; Gindis and Micheler, Reference Gindis and Micheler2024), arguing the corporation is more than the sum of its parts: ‘n’ people forming the company makes ‘n + 1’ (Maitland, Reference Maitland1905). Traditional contractarian analysis downplays the legal form’s importance, focusing instead on the individuals behind it (Klein, Reference Klein1982), whilst real entity approaches foreground the corporation’s autonomy (Gindis, Reference Gindis2020). Real entity approaches identify collective choice mechanisms that establish how decisions form an autonomous entity (Micheler, Reference Micheler2021). Both emphasise private aspects of the company and, therefore, corporate law. Neither foregrounds the state. For each, the state’s role is secondary or purely maximises relevant private benefits (Hardman, Reference Hardman2023).

Concession theory was the school of thought which engaged historically with the state. Conventional wisdom, though, is that this approach has been superseded and is no longer relevant. Historically, the state chartered individual companies, evidencing the state’s dominance over the corporate form (Patterson and Reiffen, Reference Patterson and Reiffen1990). General incorporation statutes (Butler, Reference Butler1986) ended such individual chartering, which is perceived to make concession approaches irrelevant (Millon, Reference Millon1990; Bratton, Reference Bratton1989a). Bainbridge and Henderson argued ‘[i]t has been over half-a-century since corporate legal theory, of any political or economic stripe, took the concession theory seriously’ (Bainbridge and Henderson, Reference Bainbridge and Henderson2016, 68-69). Nevertheless, concessionist argumentation tropes (White, Reference White1974) remain relevant. I demonstrated above the need for state intervention to provide core corporate features. Missing the state therefore misses a core part of corporate law. Overt modern concession argumentation tropes fall into three categories. First, they sometimes call for the concession theory’s return generally, without specificity (Padfield, Reference Padfield2014; Hardman, Reference Hardman2024). Second, they sometimes identify the state’s specific role in one aspect of corporate life, mostly incorporation (Watson, Reference Watson2019; Bottomley, Reference Bottomley2024).

Third, they sometimes argue that the state should engage more with corporate life. Bottomley (Reference Bottomley2024) argues that state provision of the corporation authorises certain activity, and so state intervention is justified in certain circumstances (also Moore, Reference Moore2014). These words are too passive. Corporate law actively encourages certain behaviours. Corporations cause harm generated by otherwise good people (Feldman et al., Reference Feldman, Libson and Parchomovsky2021). I noted above that limited liability was argued to actively incentivise certain opportunistic behaviour. Such external incentives can, over time, alter intrinsic motivations (Frey, Reference Frey1994; Bénabou and Tirole, Reference Bénabou and Tirole2003; Kreps, Reference Kreps1997). Corporate law filters those corporate participants into defined capacities (e.g., ‘shareholder’ or ‘director’), with each containing embedded expectations about behaviour (DiMaggio and Powell, Reference DiMaggio and Powell1983), which combine to lower any individual actor’s agency when taking decisions (Heugens and Lander, Reference Heugens and Lander2009). Law’s constitutive role transcends allowing certain activity – it actively incentivises certain behaviours. Accordingly, the state cannot ‘intervene’ in the corporation but sets the status quo. The legal form provided by the state is the ‘glue’ that holds the business form together (Deakin et al., Reference Deakin2017). Features of such legal forms shape behaviour through setting incentives and allowing those incentives to manifest (Hardman, Reference Hardman2023).

There is nothing natural, inherent, or automatic about any corporate feature. Each element of corporate law that deviates from the usual background law is artificial and created by the state. Such artificiality still has a real effect (Machen, Reference Machen1910, 257). Each corporate law component that differs from usual private law rules needs state activity. Even the most fundamental corporate component requires state action. Take a corporate ‘share’, the core unit that connects companies and shareholders. It is incredibly flexible: it may provide a dividend, a vote, or a return on a winding up – but in each case it may not (Pennington Reference Pennington1989; Lalafaryan, Reference Lalafaryan2024). Such flexibility causes conceptual vagueness in understanding a ‘share’ (Ireland, Reference Ireland1999). The UK’s definition is statutory, in the Companies Act 2006 section 540, with the nature of the share provided for in section 541. The state creates and sets the notion of a share through its setting of corporate law. Yet the nature of a share is core to corporate law theory, as it connects (Wolfson, Reference Wolfson1980; Cheffins, Reference Cheffins2021) to the ‘residual claim’ (Alchian and Demestz, Reference Alchian and Demsetz1972; Grossman and Hart, Reference Grossman and Hart1986). Such a connection often justifies shareholders taking major corporate decisions (Easterbrook and Fischel, Reference Easterbrook and Fischel1983) and being the ultimate beneficiaries of directors’ fiduciary duties (Macey, Reference Macey1999). From here, analysis focuses on maximising shareholder needs – whether shareholders should take maximal decisions themselves (Bebchuk, Reference Bebchuk2005) or delegate to others (Bainbridge, Reference Bainbridge2006). Should law not provide shares the full residual claim, these argumentation structures all change, too (Kelly and Parkinson, Reference Kelly, Parkinson, Parkinson, Gamble and Kelly2000). The power to decide whether or not the law does so is held by the state as it sets corporate law.

These changes are above debates between contractarians and real entity theorists. Each makes descriptive claims – that their approach accurately describes corporate law – then extrapolates normative implications (Claassen, Reference Claassen2023). Descriptive accuracy derives from corporate law, which the state sets. The state can, then, adjust comparative strengths of the theories unilaterally. Whether the corporate form seems a mere aggregate, an autonomous actor, or something else entirely is dictated by the state. On a meta-level, then, the state sets argumentation strengths – including whether the company is a state concession. It is artificial to separate these two planes. Private corporate decisions occur because the state allows them (Grantham, Reference Grantham1998), and the state can restrict those decisions. Consider an extreme situation whereby the state provides a company with rights it announces are unchangeable (Romano, Reference Romano1984). At any point, the state can subsequently change such rights – however inviolable corporate rights may appear, they can be changed by the state changing corporate law.

Non-state forces argued to drive corporate law development – like the corporate governance ‘machine’ that shapes corporate practice (Lund and Pollman, Reference Lund and Pollman2021), or corporate political power (Winkler, Reference Winkler2018) – only do so within state-set boundaries: the state has allowed/encouraged such activity (deliberately or tacitly). If corporate law presents as an evolution (Deakin, Reference Deakin, Gagliardi and Gindis2019), follows path dependence (Bebchuk and Roe, Reference Bebchuk and Roe1999), and produces autonomous corporate social actors (Veldman and Willmott, Reference Veldman, Willmott, Meyer, Leixnering and Veldman2022), it is because of state action or inaction. State action could change any of these. Indeed, as Jensen and Meckling argued (Reference Jensen and Meckling1978), the core of state activity is to change pre-existing rights. The decision to not change a deviation, however tacit it may be, therefore is as important as an initial grant of such deviation. There are reasons, noted below, why states may be reticent to do so. Yet an unwillingness to utilise a power is conceptually different from the power’s existence. As corporate legal features arose from public policy, their ongoing provision is equally a public policy concern. Should any feature fail to meet public policy requirements, it can be revoked/withdrawn/amended/kept in exchange for another public policy benefit. Of course, this reflects a wider point. Market mechanics require the state to set and enforce rules (Singer, Reference Singer2019). Accordingly, even ostensibly organic matters like differences in market economies (such as ‘varieties of capitalism’ – Hancké Reference Hancké2009; Feldmann, Reference Feldmann2019) are, in fact, reliant on state action/inaction.

Corporate law’s macro public policy considerations

State power to redesign corporate rules, though, differs from the willingness to utilise such power. Concession theory only focuses on the state’s freedom to change corporate law. It misses that the state must choose whether to. Above, I argued that legal scholarship misses that the state provided specific core corporate features due to perceived public policy needs and can change those features. Now I outline potential, non-exhaustive public policy considerations for states when evaluating whether to change corporate law, ultimately when balancing corporate law’s public benefits against social harms attributable to individual features or their aggregation. Whether individual decision-makers actually evaluate decisions on these grounds is irrelevant – the state sets and can change the rules, and decision-makers should legitimately balance various factors in deciding whether to change corporate law.

Widespread use of the corporation, arising under corporate law, provides numerous public benefits. I utilise the vague term ‘public benefit’ over the more precise term ‘public good’ to avoid any debate about whether public goods exist (Coase, Reference Coase1974; van Zandt, Reference van Zandt1993). By ‘benefits’, I mean that society generally benefits from corporate law and corporations constituted thereunder. Legal deviations provided to, and in respect of, the corporate form do not provide private benefits to corporate insiders axiomatically because that is what corporate law should inherently do, but they follow the perception of a public benefit in providing such rights. Widespread use of corporations (for private benefit) provides, too, a series of public benefits.

There are four categories of potential public benefits. First, corporations directly fund the state. Corporate profit is taxed, in addition to shareholders paying income tax on dividends. The same income is, ultimately, taxed twice (Bank, Reference Bank2010). Corporation taxes were introduced for political purposes (Mehrotra, Reference Mehrotra2010). Partnership vehicles are ‘tax transparent’, meaning that the entity itself pays no tax on profit, thus avoiding such double taxation (Berry, Reference Berry2019). Corporation taxes provide material state income – in 23/24, they contributed £85,282 million to the UK state, 9.72% of total tax receipts.Footnote 2 The state directly benefits, then, from participants utilising corporations for private benefits provided by legal deviations. Yet this is not the only form of public benefit that the corporation provides the state – indeed, Australia provides tax credits to shareholders if corporation tax has been paid (Brown, Lim and Evans, Reference Brown, Lim and Evans2020), to encourage other corporate social benefits (Antioch, Reference Antioch2001).

Second, corporate activities can meet and further states’ aims (Gatti, Reference Gatti2023) or otherwise benefit society (Stout and Gramitto, Reference Stout and Gramitto2018). For example, as of 2023, 1,142,100 UK companies had more than 2 employees, and 20,100 exceeded 100.Footnote 3 The data is banded (e.g., 2–4 employees), but at a minimum, companies employed at least 10,788,800 UK employees, roughly one-third of UK employees.Footnote 4 Employment provides social benefits (Wolfe et al., Reference Wolfe, Lohmann and Böhnke2022), so the state encouraging use of corporations through provision of private benefits furthers public benefits. This is not to argue causation – had companies never existed, then similar employment levels may have occurred. Yet correlation exists – companies are major employers, bringing social benefits. This affects corporate law reform – uncertainty harms employment (Den Haan, Freund and Rendahl, Reference Den Haan, Freund and Rendahl2021), including legal uncertainty (MacNeil, Reference MacNeil2009). Accordingly, protecting (or increasing) such corporate employment matters for law reform. Similarly, most countries utilise private pensions to provide retirement income to their populations (Ireland, Reference Ireland2011). Most private pensions invest in equity securities (Roe, Reference Roe1993). Corporate successes therefore boost retirement funds, in turn furthering state aims. Corporate aggregation of economic power facilitates greater activity than otherwise possible (Morgan and Tumlinson, Reference Morgan and Tumlinson2019) and complements state efforts elsewhere (Kim, Macey and Underhill, Reference Kim, Macey and Underhill2023).

Third, in some areas, it has been argued that the state retreats from certain public benefits, hoping the corporation fills the gap (Macey, Reference Macey2022). Arguably, the Anglo-American environmental, social and governance (ESG) movement arose from state failure to regulate adequately. Similar arguments exist for ESG’s precursor, corporate social responsibility (CSR) (Johnston, Reference Johnston2011). The state outsources activities to corporations. Encouraging corporations by their private benefits can help further these goals. The state need not deliberately outsource. It is not inevitable that corporations fill such gaps. The state can still regulate (Kim, Macey, and Underhill, Reference Kim, Macey and Underhill2023). However, corporations can provide public benefits should the state not do so, which should be factored into state decision-making. Fourth, some corporate law features mitigate others that risk social harms. Capital lock-in was introduced to protect third parties, directly mitigating concerns about corporate law encouraging risk externalisation (Goodhart and Lastra, Reference Goodhart and Lastra2020). Some corporate law rules, then, protect against harms arising from private benefits provided to encourage other public benefits. Individual corporate legal deviations create public benefits but also direct private benefits to corporate insiders, which disproportionately sit with society’s richest (Ireland, Reference Ireland2005). There is a risk that maximising private benefits for indirect social benefits can cause social harms. Any public benefit arising from corporate profit maximisation (e.g., through maximising corporation tax take) will be undermined if generating such profit causes considerable social harms (Hart and Zingales, Reference Hart and Zingales2022) that require mitigation. Some corporate law rules provide public benefits by mitigating public risks arising from maximising private benefits.

Yet in addition to corporate law rules providing social benefits, they can also encourage social harms. Limited liability encourages risk externalisation to third parties (Hansmann and Kraakman, Reference Hansmann and Kraakman1991), above the equilibrium amount (Goodhart and Lastra, Reference Goodhart and Lastra2020). Individual features of corporate law, and its totality, can cause social harms by incentivising certain behaviours by corporate insiders. Corporate law has long (Tillman, Reference Tillman1974) facilitated aggregation of economic power (Parkinson, Reference Parkinson1993; Neocleous, Reference Neocleous2003). This power can benefit a few insiders but harm wider society (Galanis, Reference Galanis2020). Corporate law features, set by the state, encourage such harm. Thus, any harm arising from the corporation’s use, incentivised by corporate law rules, relates to state decisions. Corporations materially contribute to environmental harm (Sjåfjell et al., Reference Sjåfjell, Johnston, Anker-Sørensen, Millon, Sjåfjell and Richardson2015), with corporate law requiring a major revamp to avoid global catastrophe (Bruner, Reference Bruner2020). Dissatisfaction with corporate social effects is widespread (e.g., Mayer, Reference Mayer2017). Any dissatisfaction arises from state action/inaction and should be factored into future public policy equations.

Unpacking this policy balance reveals limitations in corporate law reform to mitigate corporate social harms. Two key restraints may preclude dramatic changes to corporate law. First, major changes could undermine the above benefits: legal changes to restrict private corporate benefits may lower other public benefits. Corporate investment is predicated upon states not frequently changing corporate terms. States can easily fundamentally change the rules, including expropriating corporate assets (Stehr, Reference Stehr2023), but commitment to not do so contributed to the Anglo-Dutch corporate form becoming successful (Zhang and Morley, Reference Zhang and Morley2023; Harris, Reference Harris2020b). Financial instruments are valued by factoring in how likely the state is to change the financial entitlements attached to them (Jensen and Meckling, Reference Jensen and Meckling1978). So, it is perfectly rational for the state to identify a corporate social harm (itself predicated upon state in/action), but not remedy it to maintain other benefits. Second, international competition means dramatically changing corporate law rules could cause outbound corporate migration jurisdictionally (Hansmann and Kraakman, Reference Hansmann and Kraakman2001) or into non-corporate forms (McCahery and Vermeulen, Reference McCahery and Vermeulen2001). Most large entities trade globally (Morgan and Kristensen, Reference Morgan and Kristensen2006), and global markets have relatively homogenised expectations (Veldman and Willmott, Reference Veldman and Willmott2020). This means that a state making a major deviation from corporate laws in place elsewhere risks losing public benefits. Any dramatic change to corporate law could sacrifice current public benefits, but the same problematic activity could still occur elsewhere in another legal form.

Overall, current corporate law yields a range of social benefits. It can also yield social harms, and the state should balance harms and benefits. The state may legitimately decide to not remedy incentivisation social harm because (a) corresponding public benefits outweigh it, (b) the damage to public benefits caused by the remedy outweighs the benefits of the remedy (Bennett and Claassen, Reference Bennett and Claassen2022), or (c) other policy tools, like taxation (Collins, Ruane and Sinfield, Reference Collins, Ruane and Sinfield2020) or regulation of sector/behaviour rather than entity (Sundaram and Inkpen, Reference Sundaram and Inkpen2004), are more attractive despite ultimately treating symptoms, not causes (Hardman, Reference Hardman2023).

Implications of corporate law as public policy

Two main implications arise from seeing corporate law as public policy. First, the state is currently active in corporations and so should be seen as culpable for perceived corporate social harms. Second, this analysis is inherently and exclusively legal.

First, different conceptual approaches to corporate law view the state’s locus to regulate corporate affairs differently (Bratton, Reference Bratton1989b). Any approach allows extremely egregious behaviour to be externally regulated (e.g., environmental laws can mitigate environmental harms), but only concession approaches encourage direct state engagement in internal corporate dynamics (Hardman, Reference Hardman2023). If corporations are merely the sum of their parts, or real, then the state is inherently external, and so requires more to justify ‘intervention’. Concession theory normally argues that the state is ‘justified’ in ‘intervening’ in corporations (Bottomley, Reference Bottomley2024). This connotes a beneficent state poised to rescue society from corporate excesses.

Viewing corporate law as public policy – however tacit – changes this. The state is actively involved in corporations and should be seen as equally culpable for any social harms that are perceived to be caused by them. The state may decide to leave corporate harms unremedied because it deems public benefits worth it. This can be viewed in the inverse – if the state has not remedied a perceived social harm, then either it has tacitly decided that the harm is outweighed by its other public benefits (by not devoting enough state resources for evaluation) or not realised it should. There is an inherent balancing of harms and benefits, but (as with Kaldor-Hicks efficiency) harms and benefits will be uneven. Net social benefit calculus could cause the same constituents repeated harm and others repeated benefits. Law’s allocations of rights are inherently distributive (Hale, Reference Hale1943).

The result is akin to the Epicurean trilemma that because suffering exists in the world, God can only be any two of all-powerful, all-knowing, and all-good (Capitan, Reference Capitan1966), and not all three. If corporate activity is seen as socially harmful, then, as corporate law is an ongoing public policy balance, the state can only be two out of competent, all-knowing, and acting in the public benefit. Either the state is incompetent, ignorant, or not acting in the overall public benefit. Those who analyse the state’s role in corporate law tend to request more state activity (Ripken, Reference Ripken2010). Viewing corporate law and the corporate form as public policy demonstrates this is misguided – the state causes and is unlikely to be able or willing to resolve perceived issues. Regulatory capture (Slayton and Clark-Ginsberg, Reference Slayton and Clark-Ginsberg2018) means the state may benefit particular constituents – those most powerful already (Ireland, Reference Ireland2005). For example, even should employee ownership (Dow, Reference Dow2022) prove socially optimal, the state may not change corporate law if subject to regulatory capture from existing shareholders.

Second, this analysis is limited to corporate law. The state can deploy other tools to encourage or discourage corporate behaviour – like taxes and subsidies. Corporate law is, though, inherently linked to the state. This is a very corporate legal analysis (Hardman, Reference Hardman2024). It therefore helps delineate corporate law analysis from complementary disciplines on two fronts. First, from the study of individual business vehicles. Individual companies are voluntarily formed and can be autonomous entities (Vinogradoff, Reference Vinogradoff1924). The state sets the corporate landscape, though, and features of the corporation incentivise certain behaviours through its setting of corporate law. These state-set features, and only these features, should fall within the remit of corporate law scholarship. Second, the criteria that the state must use in striking this public policy balance are extrinsic to corporate law. Descriptively identifying that corporations and corporate law are the results of public policy balances, however unintentional, and suggesting some potential considerations does not definitively identify how states should balance policy considerations. Many categories of public benefits and harms are unquantifiable, and I provide no claim for which benefits the state should maximise or which harms it should avoid. It is arguable that the state should focus on ensuring strong public markets (Cheffins and Reddy, Reference Cheffins and Reddy2023), or protecting investors from agency costs (Bebchuk, Cohen and Ferrell, Reference Bebchuk, Cohen and Ferrell2009), or minimising environmental harm (Sjåfjell et al., Reference Sjåfjell, Johnston, Anker-Sørensen, Millon, Sjåfjell and Richardson2015), each as a way to maximise public benefits. Moving to considering such evaluative criteria, rather than arguing about whether the state can engage if willing, takes corporate law a step closer to playing the role that it should in a wider, interdisciplinary understanding of the company (Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2022).

This article argues for the need to conceptualise the state’s role in corporate law and corporations. Features of both are provided by the state, for deliberate or tacit public policy reasons. Modern corporate law theory traditionally misses the importance of the state in the corporate form and corporate law. Public policy, however, underpins corporate law and the corporate form. In turn, each aspect of corporate law and each feature of the corporation should exist only and to the extent that public policy continues to justify it. There may well be strong restraints on the state’s willingness to dramatically exercise its powers, but that remains conceptually different from the presence of such powers.

It may be that corporate law as currently constituted, the corporate form that it establishes and the incentives for behaviour that it creates are optimal for society. Equally, it may not be. In either event, understanding the optimality of the status quo and options to change it requires a proper understanding of that status quo. Backgrounding the role of the state does not provide such clarity. Implications that the corporate form is solely private and that features provided to its constituents arise naturally or inherently miss the ongoing role that the state plays in setting corporate law and the rules of the game for corporations. So, too, does talk of the state ‘allowing’ certain behaviours and concepts such as state ‘intervention’ requiring ‘justification’. The state is heavily implicit in the status quo, for good and for bad. This means that the state is more involved in the corporate form than modern corporate law theory allows. It also means that a benign state is not in and of itself the answer to corporate ills as a white knight ready to free us from corporate excesses. Whatever your normative take on what the corporate form and corporate law should do, encourage, or facilitate, understanding that the state is at the heart of such a normative vision is key.

Footnotes

1 I use (a) ‘company’ and ‘corporation’ and (b) ‘company law’ and ‘corporate law’ synonymously. For each, the former reflects UK usage and the latter US usage. Primarily, this article deploys UK sources to illustrate wider points.

References

Alchian, A. A. and Demsetz, H. (1972). Production, information costs and economic organization. American Economic Review 62, 777795.Google Scholar
Andriosopoulos, D. and Loncan, T. (2025). State expropriation risk and ownership structure: evidence from cash holdings around the world. Corporate Governance: An International Review. https://doi.org/10.1111/corg.12656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anello, G., Arafa, M. and Gramitto Ricci, S.A. (2021). Sacred corporate law. Seattle University Law Review 45, 413461.Google Scholar
Antioch, G. (2001). Franking credit trading. Australian Tax Forum 16, 323344.Google Scholar
Ayotte, K. and Hansmann, H. (2015). A nexus of contracts theory of legal entities. International Review of Law and Economics 42, 112.10.1016/j.irle.2014.10.001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bainbridge, S.M (2006). Director primacy and shareholder disempowerment. Harvard Law Review 119, 17351758.Google Scholar
Bainbridge, S.M. (2025). A course correction for controlling shareholder transactions. Delaware Journal of Corporate Law 49, 525603.Google Scholar
Bainbridge, S.M. and Henderson, M.T. (2016 ). Limited Liability: A Legal and Economic Analysis. Cheltenham: Elgar.10.4337/9781783473038CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bank, S.A. (2010). From Sword to Shield: The Transformation of the Corporate Income Tax, 1861 to Present. Oxford: OUP.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195326192.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Banner, S. (1998). Anglo-American Securities Regulation. Cambridge: CUP.10.1017/CBO9780511523045CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bebchuk, L.A. (2005). The case for increasing shareholder power. Harvard Law Review 118, 833914.Google Scholar
Bebchuk, L.A., Cohen, A. and Ferrell, A. (2009). What matters in corporate governance?. Review of Financial Studies 22, 783827.10.1093/rfs/hhn099CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bebchuk, L.A. and Fried, J.M. (1996). The uneasy case for the priority of secured claims in bankruptcy. Yale Law Journal 105, 857934.10.2307/797243CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bebchuk, LA., and Roe, M. (1999). A theory of path dependence in corporate ownership and governance. Stanford Law Review 52, 127170.10.2307/1229459CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bellenden Ker, H. (1837). Report on the Law of Partnership with an Appendix Thereto, London: House of Commons.Google Scholar
Bénabou, R. and Tirole, J. (2003). Intrinsic and extrinsic motivation. Review of Economic Studies 70, 489520.10.1111/1467-937X.00253CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, M. and Claassen, R.J.G. (2022). The corporate power trilemma. Journal of Politics 84, 20942106.10.1086/717851CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berry, E. (2019). Limited partnership law and private equity: an instance of legislative capture?. Journal of Corporate Law Studies 19, 105135.10.1080/14735970.2018.1456393CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blair, M.M. (2003). Locking in capital: what corporate law achieved for business organizers in the nineteenth century. UCLA Law Review 51, 387455.Google Scholar
Blankenberg, S., Plesch, D. and Wilkinson, F. (2010). Limited liability and the modern corporation in theory and in practice. Cambridge Journal of Economics 34, 821836.10.1093/cje/beq028CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bodenhorn, H. (2006). Bank chartering and political corruption in antebellum New York: free banking as reform. In Glaeser, E.L. and Goldin, C. (eds), Corruption and Reform: Lessons from America’s Economic History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Bottomley, S. (2024). Corporate regulation in the public interest – from concession to authorisation. Journal of Corporate Law Studies 24, 331355.10.1080/14735970.2024.2416020CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bouckaert, B. (1991), Corporate personality: myth, fiction or reality?. Israel Law Review 25, 156186.10.1017/S0021223700010347CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratton, W.W. (1989a). The “nexus of contracts” corporation: a critical appraisal. Cornell Law Review 74, 407465.Google Scholar
Bratton, W.W. (1989b). The new economic theory of the firm: critical perspectives from history. Stanford Law Review 41, 14711527.10.2307/1228806CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, R., Lim, Y. and Evans, C. (2020). The impact of full franking credit refundability on corporate tax avoidance. eJournal of Tax Research 17, 134167.Google Scholar
Bruner, C.M. (2020). Corporate Governance Reform and the Sustainability Imperative. Yale Law Journal 131, 12171277.Google Scholar
Bruner, C.M. (2022). The Corporation as Technology. Oxford; OUP.10.1093/oso/9780197635179.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. (1970). In defense of caveat emptor. University of Chicago Law Review 38, 6473.10.2307/1598958CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buocz, T. and Eisenberger, I. (2023). Demystifying legal personhood for non-human entities: a Kelsenian approach. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 43, 3253.10.1093/ojls/gqac024CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butler, H.N. (1986). General incorporation in nineteenth century England: interaction of common law and legislative processes, International Review of Law and Economics 6, 169187.10.1016/0144-8188(86)90002-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Capitan, W.H. (1966). Part X of Hume’s “dialogues”. American Philosophical Quarterly 3, 8285.Google Scholar
Chan, J. and Lim, E. (2024). How it matters who makes corporate rules. European Business Organisation Law Review 25, 655693.10.1007/s40804-024-00326-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cheffins, B.R and Reddy, B.V. (2023). Will listing rule reform deliver strong public markets for the UK?, Modern Law Review 86, 176213.10.1111/1468-2230.12758CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cheffins, B.R. (2004). The Trajectory of (Corporate Law) Scholarship. Cambridge: CUP.10.1017/CBO9780511495533CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cheffins, B.R. (2021). Stop blaming Milton Friedman!. Washington University Law Review 98, 16071644.Google Scholar
Ciepley, D. (2013). Beyond public and private: toward a political theory of the corporation. American Political Science Review 107, 139158.10.1017/S0003055412000536CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Claassen, R.J.G. (2023). Political theories of the business corporation. Philosophy Compass 18, e12892.10.1111/phc3.12892CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coase, R.H. (1974). The lighthouse in economics. Journal of Law & Economics 17, 357376.10.1086/466796CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, F. (1935) Transcendental nonsense and the functional approach. Columbia Law Review 35, 809849.10.2307/1116300CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, M.L., Ruane, S. and Sinfield, A. (2020). Taxation and social policy. Social Policy and Society 19, 431436.10.1017/S1474746420000159CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cottrell, P.L. (1980). Industrial Finance 1830–1914. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Dari-Mattiacci, G., Gelderblom, O., Jonker, J. and Perotti, E.C. (2017). The emergence of the corporate form. Journal of Law, Economics & Organization 33, 193236.10.1093/jleo/ewx002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deakin, S. et al (2017). Legal institutionalism: capitalism and the constitutive role of law. Journal of Comparative Economics 45, 188200.10.1016/j.jce.2016.04.005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deakin, S. (2019) Juridical Ontology and the Theory of the Firm. In Gagliardi, F. and Gindis, D. (eds) Institutions and Evolution of Capitalism, Cheltenham: Elgar.Google Scholar
Den Haan, W.J., Freund, L.B. and Rendahl, P. (2021). Volatile hiring: uncertainty in search and matching models. Journal of Monetary Economics 123, 118.10.1016/j.jmoneco.2021.07.008CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dewey, J. (1926), The historic background of corporate legal personality. Yale Law Journal 35, 655673.10.2307/788782CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DiMaggio, P.J. and Powell, W.W. (1983). The iron cage revisited: institutional isomorphism and collective rationality in organizational fields. American Sociological Review 48, 147160.10.2307/2095101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dow, G.K. (2022). The labor-managed firm, Oliver Williamson, and me. Journal of Institutional Economics 18, 219236.10.1017/S1744137421000448CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Easterbrook, F.H. and Fischel, D.R.R. (1983). Voting and corporate law, Journal of Law and Economics 26, 395427.10.1086/467043CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Easterbrook, F.H. and Fischel, D.R.R. (1985). Limited liability and the corporation. University of Chicago Law Review 52, 89117.10.2307/1599572CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Easterbrook, F.H. and Fischel, D.R.R. (1989). The corporate contract. Columbia Law Review 89, 14161448.10.2307/1122807CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edelman, J (2010). When do fiduciary duties arise?. Law Quarterly Review 126, 302327.Google Scholar
Fairfax, L.M. (2006). The rhetoric of corporate law: the impact of stakeholder rhetoric on corporate norms. Journal of Corporation Law 31, 675718.Google Scholar
Feldman, Y., Libson, A. and Parchomovsky, G. (2021). Corporate law for good people. Northwestern University Law Review 115, 11251184.Google Scholar
Feldmann, M. (2019). Global varieties of capitalism. World Politics 71, 162196.10.1017/S0043887118000230CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freeman, M., Pearson, R. and Taylor, J. (2007). ‘Different and better?’ Scottish joint stock companies and the law, c.1720-1845. English Historical Review 122, 6181.10.1093/ehr/cel373CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frey, B.S. (1994). How intrinsic motivation is crowded out and in. Rationality and Society 6, 334352.10.1177/1043463194006003004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galanis, M. (2020). Corporate law versus social autonomy: law as social hazard, Law and Critique 32, 132.10.1007/s10978-020-09267-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallanis, T.P. (2000). The rule against perpetuities and the law commission’s flawed philosophy. Cambridge Law Journal 59, 284293.10.1017/S000819730000012XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gatti, M. (2023). Corporate Governing: Understanding Corporations as Agents of Socioeconomic Change, European Corporate Governance Institute Law Working Paper 730/2023.10.2139/ssrn.4530776CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geldart, W.M. (1911). Legal personality. Law Quarterly Review 27, 90108.Google Scholar
Getzler, J and Macnair, M. (2006). The Firm as an Entity Before the Companies Acts, Oxford Legal Studies Research Paper 47/2006.Google Scholar
Gierke, O. (2014). Political Theories of the Middle Ages, translated by Maitland, F.W., Mansfield: Martino.Google Scholar
Gindis, D. (2009). From fictions to aggregates to real entities in the theory of the firm. Journal of Institutional Economics 5, 2546.10.1017/S1744137408001203CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gindis, D. (2020). Ernst Freund as precursor of the rational study of corporate law. Journal of Institutional Economics 16, 597621.10.1017/S174413741700056XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gindis, D. and Micheler, E. (2024). Institutional theory for corporate law: an invitation, Journal of Corporate Law Studies 24, 331355.10.1080/14735970.2024.2414465CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gindis, D. and Singer, A.A. (2022). The corporate baby in the bathwater: why proposals to abolish corporate personhood are misguided. Journal of Business Ethics 183, 983997.10.1007/s10551-021-05019-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gladstone, W. et al (1844). First Report of the Select Committee on Joint Stock Companies, together with the Minutes of Evidence (Taken in 1841 and 1843), London: House of Commons.Google Scholar
Goodhart, C.A.E. and Lastra, R.M. (2020). Equity finance: matching liability to power. Journal of Financial Regulation 6, 140.10.1093/jfr/fjz010CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gower, L.C.B. (1956) Some contrasts between British and American corporation law. Harvard Law Review 69, 13691402.10.2307/1337659CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grandy, C. (1989). New Jersey corporate chartermongering, 1875-1929. Journal of Economic History 49, 677692.10.1017/S0022050700008810CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grantham, R.B. (1998). The doctrinal basis of the rights of company shareholders. Cambridge Law Journal 57, 554588.10.1017/S0008197398003055CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, S. (2004). Limited liability: a Necessary Revolution?. The Company Lawyer 25, 99101.Google Scholar
Grossman, S.J. and Hart, O.D. (1986). The costs and benefits of ownership: a theory of vertical and lateral integration. Journal of Political Economy 94, 691719.10.1086/261404CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grundfest, J (1992). The limited future of unlimited liability: a capital markets perspective. Yale Law Journal 102, 387425.10.2307/796841CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gubler, Z.J. (2024). The neoclassical view of corporate fiduciary law. University of Chicago Law Review 91, 165238.Google Scholar
Gullifer, L. and Payne, J. (2020). Intermediated securities and investor protection. Law Quarterly Review 136, 201205.Google Scholar
Hager, M.H. (1989). Bodies politic: the progressive history of organizational “real entity” theory. University of Pittsburgh Law Review 50, 575654.Google Scholar
Hale, R.L. (1943). Bargaining, duress and economic liberty. Columbia Law Review 43, 603628.10.2307/1117229CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halpern, P., Trebilcock, M. and Turnbull, S. (1980). An economic analysis of limited liability in corporation law. University of Toronto Law Journal 30, 117150.10.2307/825483CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamill, S.P. (1999). From special privilege to general utility: a continuation of Willard Hurst’s study of corporations. American University Law Review 49, 81180.Google Scholar
Hancké, B. (2009). Debating Varieties of Capitalism: A Reader. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
Hansmann, H. and Kraakman, R. (1991). Towards unlimited shareholder liability for corporate torts. Yale Law Journal 100, 18791934.10.2307/796812CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansmann, H. and Kraakman, R. (2000). The essential role of organizational law. Yale Law Journal 110, 387440.10.2307/797521CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansmann, H. and Kraakman, R. (2001). The end of history for corporate law. Georgetown Law Journal 89, 439468.Google Scholar
Hardman, J. (2023). Fixing the misalignment of the concession of corporate legal personality. Legal Studies 43, 443460.10.1017/lst.2022.44CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardman, J. (2024). The making of corporate legal concession theory. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 44, 181199.10.1093/ojls/gqad028CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hardman, J. (2025). Conceptual challenges for creditors of companies. In Wood, J., Elina, S. and Tribe, J. (eds), Creditors and Directors: Law and Liability. Oxford: OUP (forthcoming).Google Scholar
Harris, R. (2020a). A new understanding of the history of limited liability: an invitation for theoretical reframing. Journal of Institutional Economics 16, 643664.10.1017/S1744137420000181CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, R. (2020b). Going the Distance: Eurasian Trade and the Rise of the Business Corporation, 1400-1700. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Harris, R. and Lamoreaux, N.R. (2019). Opening the black box of the common-law legal regime: contrasts in the development of corporate law in Britain and the United States in the Late Nineteenth and Early Twentieth Centuries. Business History 61, 11991221.10.1080/00076791.2018.1501027CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H.L.A. (1953). Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence. Cambridge: CUP.Google Scholar
Hart, O. and Zingales, L. (2022). The new corporate governance. University of Chicago Business Law Review 1, 195216.Google Scholar
Haskins, G.L. (1977). Extending the grasp of the dead hand. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 126, 1948.10.2307/3311757CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heugens, P.P.M.A.R and Lander, M.W. (2009). Structure! Agency! (and other Quarrels): a meta-analysis of institutional theories of organization. Academy of Management Journal 52, 6185.10.5465/amj.2009.36461835CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodgson, G.M. (2022). Donald T. Campbell on the institutions of scientific knowledge and the limits of interdisciplinarity. Journal of Institutional Economics 18, 969980.10.1017/S1744137422000121CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horowitz, S.J. and Sitkoff, R.H. (2014). Unconstitutional perpetual trusts. Vanderbilt Law Review 67, 17691823.Google Scholar
Horwitz, M. J. (1992), The Transformation of American Law, 1870–1960: The Crisis of Legal Orthodoxy. New York: OUP.10.1093/oso/9780195070248.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurt, C. (2019). Partnership lost. University of Richmond Law Review 52, 491556.Google Scholar
Ireland, P. (1999). Company law and the myth of shareholder ownership. Modern Law Review 62, 3257.10.1111/1468-2230.00190CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ireland, P. (2005). Shareholder primacy and the distribution of wealth. Modern Law Review 68, 4981.10.1111/j.1468-2230.2005.00528.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ireland, P. (2010). Limited liability, shareholder rights and the problem of corporate irresponsibility. Cambridge Journal of Economics 34, 837856.10.1093/cje/ben040CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ireland, P. (2011). Law and the neoliberal vision: financial property, pension privatisation and the ownership society. Northern Ireland law Quarterly 62, 132.Google Scholar
Ireland, P., Grigg-Spall, I., and Kelly, D. (1987). The conceptual foundations of modern company law. Journal of Law and Society 14, 149165.10.2307/1410303CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, T.H. and Kronman, A.T. (1979). Secured financing and priorities among creditors. Yale Law Journal 88, 11431182.10.2307/795626CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, M.C. and Meckling, W.H. (1978). Can the corporation survive?. Financial Analysts Journal 34, 3137.10.2469/faj.v34.n1.31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnston, A. (2011). Facing up to social cost: the real meaning of corporate social responsibility. Griffith Law Journal 20, 221244.Google Scholar
Kantorowicz, E.H. (1997). The King’s Two Bodies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, G. and Parkinson, J. (2000). The Conceptual Foundations of the Company. In Parkinson, J. Gamble, A. and Kelly, G. (eds), The Political Economy of the Company, Oxford: Hart.Google Scholar
Kim, H., Macey, J. and Underhill, K. (2023). Does ESG Crowd Out Support for Government Regulation?, Coase-Sandor Working Paper Series in Law and Economics No. 983.Google Scholar
Klein, W. A. (1982). The modern business organization: bargaining under constraints. Yale Law Journal 91, 15211564.10.2307/795997CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koessler, M. (1949). The person in imagination or persona ficta of the corporation. Louisiana Law Review 9, 435449.Google Scholar
Kraakman, R. et al (2017). The Anatomy of Corporate Law: A Comparative and Functional Approach. 3rd edn, Oxford: OUP.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198739630.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreps, D.M. (1997). Intrinsic motivation and extrinsic incentives. American Economic Review 87, 358364.Google Scholar
Kuran, T. (2005). The absence of the corporation in Islamic law: origins and persistence. American Journal of Comparative Law 53, 785834.10.1093/ajcl/53.4.785CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kurki, V.A.J. (2022). Can nature hold rights? It’s not as easy as you think. Transnational Environmental Law 11, 525552.10.1017/S2047102522000358CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lalafaryan, N. (2024). Private credit: a renaissance in corporate finance. Journal of Corporate Law Studies 24, 4195.10.1080/14735970.2024.2351230CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laski, H. (1916). The personality of associations. Harvard Law Review 29, 404426.10.2307/1326689CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lim, E.W.K. (2021) Concentrated ownership, state-owned enterprises and corporate governance. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 41, 663691.10.1093/ojls/gqaa050CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lobban, M. (1996) Nineteenth century frauds in company formation: Derry v Peek in context. Law Quarterly Review 112, 287334.Google Scholar
Loftus, D. (2002). Capital and community: limited liability and attempts to democratize the market in mid-nineteenth-century England. Victorian Studies 45, 93120.10.2979/VIC.2002.45.1.93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lund, D.S. and Pollman, E. (2021). The corporate governance machine. Columbia Law Review 121, 25632634.Google Scholar
MacCormick, N. (2007). Institutions of Law: An Essay in Legal Theory. Oxford: OUP.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198267911.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macey, J.R. (1999). Fiduciary duties as residual claims: obligations to nonshareholder constituencies from a theory of the firm perspective. Cornell Law Review 84, 12661281.Google Scholar
Macey, J.R. (2022). ESG Investing: Why here? Why now?. Berkeley Business Law Journal 19, 258291.Google Scholar
Macgregor, L. (2020). Partnerships and legal personality: cautionary tales from Scotland, Journal of Corporate Law Studies 20, 237262.10.1080/14735970.2019.1654805CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machen, A.W. (1910). Corporate personality. Harvard Law Review 24, 253267.10.2307/1324056CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, C. (2011). From privilege to right – themes in the emergence of limited liability. Juridical Review 294–313.Google Scholar
MacNeil, I. (2009). Uncertainty in commercial law. Edinburgh Law Review 13, 6899.10.3366/E1364980908000966CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahoney, P.G. (1999). The pernicious art of securities regulation. University of Chicago Law Review 66, 13731394.10.2307/1600372CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maitland, F.W. (1900). The corporation sole. Law Quarterly Review 16, 335354.Google Scholar
Maitland, F.W. (1905). Moral Personality and Legal Personality. Journal of the Society of Comparative Legislation 6, 192200.Google Scholar
Mark, G.A. (1987). The personification of the business corporation in American law. University of Chicago Law Review 54, 14411483.10.2307/1599739CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayer, C. (2017). Who’s responsible for irresponsible business?. Oxford Review of Economic Policy 33, 157175.10.1093/oxrep/grx028CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCahery, J.A. and Vermeulen, E.P.M. (2001). The evolution of closely held business forms in Europe. Journal of Corporation Law 855–878.Google Scholar
McQueen, R. (2016). A Social History of Company Law. Abingdon: Routledge.10.4324/9781315565194CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mehrotra, A.K. (2010). The public control of corporate power: revisiting the 1909 U.S. corporate tax from a comparative perspective. Theoretical Inquiries in Law 11, 497538.10.2202/1565-3404.1250CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Micheler, E. (2021). Company Law: A Real Entity Theory, Oxford: OUP.10.1093/oso/9780198858874.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Micheler, E (2024). Separate legal personality – an explanation and a defence. Journal of Corporate Law Studies 24, 301329.10.1080/14735970.2024.2365170CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millon, D. (1990). Theories of the corporation. Duke Law Journal 201–262.10.2307/1372611CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, M.T. (2013). Corporate Governance in the Shadow of the State. Oxford: Hart.Google Scholar
Moore, M.T. (2014). Private ordering and public policy: the paradoxical foundations of corporate contractarianism. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 34, 693728.10.1093/ojls/gqu006CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morawetz, V. (1886). A Treatise on the Law of Private Corporations. 2nd edition, Boston: Little Brown.Google Scholar
Morgan, G. and Kristensen, P.H. (2006). The contested space of multinationals: varieties of institutionalism, varieties of capitalism. Human Relations 59, 14671490.10.1177/0018726706072866CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgan, J. and Tumlinson, J. (2019). Corporate provision of public goods. Management Science 65, 44894504.10.1287/mnsc.2018.3137CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Naffine, N. (2003). Who are law’s Persons? From cheshire cats to responsible subjects. Modern Law Review 66, 346367.10.1111/1468-2230.6603002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neocleous, M. (2003). Staging power: Marx, Hobbes and the personification of capital. Law & Critique 14, 147165.10.1023/A:1024753201618CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Padfield, S. (2014). Rehabilitating concession theory. Oklahoma Law Review 66, 327361.Google Scholar
Parkinson, J.E. (1993). Corporate Power and Responsibility: Issues in the Theory of Company Law, Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
Patterson, M. and Reiffen, D. (1990). The effect of the bubble act on the market for joint stock shares. Journal of Economic History 50, 163171.10.1017/S0022050700035774CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pennington, R.R. (1989). Can Shares in Companies be Defined?. Company Lawyer 10, 140144.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. (2023). The State. Princeton: Princeton University Press.10.1515/9780691244396CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollock, F. (1911). Has the common law received the fiction theory of corporations?. Law Quarterly Review 27, 219235.Google Scholar
Radin, M. (1932). The endless problem of corporate personality. Columbia Law Review 32, 643667.10.2307/1114707CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ripken, S.K. (2010). Corporations as people too: a multi-dimensional approach to the corporate personhood puzzle. Fordham Journal of Corporate & Financial Law 15, 97177.Google Scholar
Ripken, S.K. (2019). Corporate Personhood, Cambridge: CUP.10.1017/9781108241366CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roe, M.J. (1993). The modern corporation and private pensions. UCLA Law Review 41, 75116.Google Scholar
Romano, R. (1984). metapolitics and corporate law reform. Stanford Law Review 36, 9231016.10.2307/1228610CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Runciman, D. (1997). Pluralism and the Personality of the State. Cambridge: CUP 10.1017/CBO9780511582967CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saville, J. (1956). Sleeping partnership and limited liability, 1850-1856. Economic History Review 8, 418433.Google Scholar
Schwartz, A.A. (2012). The perpetual corporation. George Washington Law Review 80, 764830.Google Scholar
Seavoy, R.E. (1972). Laws to encourage manufacturing: New York policy and the 1811 general incorporation statute. Business History Review 46, 8595.10.2307/3112777CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simes, L.M. (1955). The policy against perpetuities. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 103, 707738.10.2307/3310010CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, A.A. (2019). The corporation’s governmental provenance and its significance, Economics and Philosophy 35, 283306.10.1017/S0266267118000299CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sjåfjell, B., Johnston, A. Anker-Sørensen, L. and Millon, D (2015). Shareholder Primacy: the Main Barrier to Sustainable Companies. In Sjåfjell, B. and Richardson, B.J. (eds), Company Law and Sustainability: Legal Barriers and Opportunities. Cambridge: CUP.10.1017/CBO9781107337978CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slayton, R. and Clark-Ginsberg, A. (2018). Beyond regulatory capture: coproducing expertise for critical infrastructure protection. Regulation and Governance 12, 115130.10.1111/rego.12168CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, D.C. (2020). The mid-victorian reform of Britain’s company laws and the moral economy of fair competition. Enterprise & Society 22, 11031139.10.1017/eso.2020.33CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stehr, P. (2023). Expropriation as a measure of corporate reform: learning from the Berlin initiative. European Journal of Political Theory 24, 7091.10.1177/14748851231197799CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stigler, G.J. (1971). The theory of economic regulation. Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 2, 321.Google Scholar
Stout, L. and Gramitto, S. (2018). Corporate governance as privately-ordered public policy: a proposal. Seattle University Law Review 54, 551576.Google Scholar
Sundaram, A.K. and Inkpen, A.C. (2004). The corporate objective revisited. Organization Science 15, 350363.10.1287/orsc.1040.0068CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sylla, R. (1985). Early American banking: the significance of the corporate form. Business and Economic History 14, 105123.Google Scholar
Sylla, R., Legler, J.B. and Wallis, J.J. (1987). Banks and state public finance in the new republic: the United States, 1790-1860. Journal of Economic History 47, 391403.10.1017/S0022050700048142CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Televantos, A. (2020). Capitalism Before Corporations: The Morality of Business Associations and the Roots of Commercial Equity and Law. Oxford: OUP.10.1093/oso/9780198870340.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, R.B. (2024). Upending the State’s Power to Regulate Corporate Separateness. In Barnes, V and Hardman, J. (eds) Origins of Company Law. Oxford: Hart.Google Scholar
Tillman, R. (1974). Apology and ambiguity: Adolf Berle on corporate power. Journal of Economic Issues 8, 111126.10.1080/00213624.1974.11503165CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, J.D. (2018). The Development of English Company Law Before 1900. In Wells, H. (eds), Research Handbook on the History of Corporate and Company Law. Cheltenham: Elgar.Google Scholar
van Zandt, D.E. (1993). The lessons of the lighthouse: “government” or “private” provision of goods. Journal of Legal Studies 22, 4772.10.1086/468157CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Veldman, J. and Willmott, H. (2020). Performativity and Convergence in Comparative Corporate Governance. Competition & Change 24, 408428.10.1177/1024529419857382CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Veldman, J. and Willmott, H. (2022). Social ontology of the modern corporation: its role in understanding organizations. In Meyer, R.E., Leixnering, S. and Veldman, J. (eds), The Corporation: Rethinking the Iconic Form of Business Organization. Leeds: Emerald.Google Scholar
Vinogradoff, P. (1924). Juridical persons. Columbia Law Review 24, 594604.10.2307/1113204CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Mehren, A.T. (1990), The “battle of the forms”: a comparative view. American Journal of Comparative Law 38, 265298.10.2307/840101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watson, S.M. (2019). The corporate legal person. Journal of Corporate Law studies 19, 137166.10.1080/14735970.2018.1435951CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watson, S.M. (2022). The Making of the Modern Company, Oxford: Hart.10.5040/9781509923656CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wedderburn, K.W. (1986). The Worker and the Law. Middlesex: Penguin.Google Scholar
White, H. (1974). The historical text as a literary artefact. Clio 3, 277303.Google Scholar
Williamson, O.E. (1991). Comparative economic organization: the analysis of discrete structural alternatives. Administrative Science Quarterly 36, 269296.10.2307/2393356CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, O.E. (2000). The new institutional economics: taking stock, looking ahead. Journal of Economic Literature 38, 595613.10.1257/jel.38.3.595CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winkler, A. (2018). We the Corporations, New York: Liveright.Google Scholar
Wolfe, A. (1993). The modern corporation: private agent or public actor?. Washington and Lee Law Review 50, 16731696.Google Scholar
Wolfe, F., Lohmann, H. and Böhnke, P. (2022). The standard of living among the poor across Europe. Does employment make a difference?, European Societies 24, 548579.10.1080/14616696.2022.2076892CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolfson, N. (1980). A critique of corporate law. University of Miami Law Review 34, 959994.Google Scholar
Woodward, S. (1985). Limited liability in the theory of the firm. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 141, 601611.Google Scholar
Wright, R.E. (2010). Rise of the corporation nation. In Irwin, D. and Sylla, R. (eds), Founding Choices: American Economic Policy in the 1790s. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Zhang, T. and Morley, J. (2023). The Modern State and the Rise of the Business Corporation. Yale Law Journal 132, 19702047.Google Scholar