Hostname: page-component-6bb9c88b65-kfd97 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-07-24T07:23:31.569Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Is Sartre an Eleatic Monist?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 July 2025

James Kinkaid*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Bilkent University, Ankara, Turkey
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

It has long been recognized that Sartre’s description of “being-in-itself” in the Introduction to Being and Nothingness (B&N) is reminiscent of Eleatic monism, the view traditionally attributed to Parmenides on which there is only one mind-independent entity, which is undifferentiated and atemporal. I reconstruct two arguments from premises Sartre endorses in B&N for Eleatic monism. These arguments are interesting not only because they give new life to an old reading of B&N, but also because there has recently been a revival of interest in monism in analytic metaphysics.

Information

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Inc

1. Introduction

In the notoriously difficult Introduction to Being and Nothingness (B&N), Sartre presents his “ontological proof,” an argument meant to establish the existence of mind-independent substance and thereby refute a form of idealism that Sartre attributes to Husserl. The argument infers the existence of mind-independent substance (“being-in-itself”) from the “emptiness” of consciousness (“being-for-itself”), which I interpret as its purely relational nature.Footnote 1 A question left open by the “ontological proof” and the ensuing characterization of being-in-itself is whether Sartre endorses Eleatic monism—the view that there is a single mind-independent substance that is not subject to differentiation, temporality, and other features of the manifest world. Several commentators have noted the Eleatic resonances of Sartre’s description of being-in-itself. Yet little work has been done to determine whether B&N contains the resources for a principled and plausible defense of Eleatic monism. In the following, I argue that premises Sartre endorses across the bulk of B&N commit him to Eleatic monism.

Let me say a bit at the outset to frame my project. First, I take what one could call a “metaphysics-first”Footnote 2 approach to interpreting B&N. This is not an especially common way of approaching the text, whose lasting insights are typically taken to belong either to the philosophy of mind (e.g., Sartre’s views on self-consciousnessFootnote 3), on the one hand, or ethics (broadly construed to include issues like bad faith vs. authenticity and existential psychoanalysis), on the other.

On a metaphysics-first reading, Sartre’s existentialist/ethical project cannot be divorced from his bold and often puzzling ontology. A metaphysics-first reader such as myself owes some account of how a monistic metaphysics could bear on the more popular existentialist/ethical dimensions of the work. There is some precedent for deriving ethical conclusions from monistic metaphysics. An obvious example is Spinoza’s Ethics. On Schopenhauer’s view, the compassionate person sees through the principium individuationis, thereby recognizing the non-distinctness of all living beings and regarding their suffering as her own (Marshall, Reference Marshall2020). T.H. Green grounds his moral perfectionism in a monistic absolute idealism (Stern, Reference Stern, Golob and Timmerman2017). Now, I do think Sartre’s existentialist/ethical project is grounded in his metaphysics, but I doubt monism plays much of a role in that story. What does play a central role is being-for-itself’s non-self-identity, in contrast to the self-identity of being-in-itself emphasized in the Introduction; this contrast, for example, grounds Sartre’s claim that “man is a useless passion” due to his impossible project of being God (in-itself-for-itself) (B&N 797). But while I doubt that one needs to read Sartre as a monist to make sense of this grounding of the existentialist/ethical project in the metaphysical project, I see no reason to suppose that a monistic reading is incompatible with that grounding story.

Second, I should be clear about my intended audience. First, I am addressing myself to Sartre scholars who are skeptical of the Eleatic monist reading of B&N. I will raise some objections to a non-monist reading in Section 5, but the general challenge I issue to non-monistic readers is this: if Sartre is not an Eleatic monist, which premise(s) of the two arguments I reconstruct in Section 3 does he reject? Even should the monistic reading turn out not to be viable, I suspect meeting this challenge would deepen our understanding of Sartre’s views of negation, individuation, time, and more.

Second, I am addressing myself to contemporary analytic metaphysicians. There has been something of a monist revival in analytic metaphysics of late. Michael (Reference Michael2020) employs the Principle of Sufficient reason to mount a Bradleyan regress argument against the intelligibility of relations. Builes (Reference Builes2021) argues for a version of monism on which the world “just is the way it is” as the best account of the relation between objects and their properties. Horgan and Potrč (Reference Horgan, Potrč and Goff2012) argue for a monistic view they call “blobjectivism” based on the rejection of metaphysical vagueness. Schaffer (Reference Schaffer2010) argues for “priority monism,” on which the cosmos is the sole fundamental entity, from the possibility of “atomless gunk” and considerations about quantum entanglement. Rea (Reference Rea2001) argues that Eleatic monism follows from four plausible claims about material objects and spacetime.

I draw upon analytic work on negative facts, identity, time, truthmaking, mass logic, and ideology to articulate my interpretation of Sartre’s metaphysics. Notably, the reasons I see as leading Sartre to monism differ from those offered in favor of monism in the recent analytic literature. In Section 4, I draw upon analytic metaphysics to raise philosophical objections to the case for Sartrean monism—some of which are forceful but none of which are obviously decisive. I will not be considering what kind of uptake Sartrean monism would get from recent movements in continental metaphysics—“speculative realism,” “new materialism,” and “object-oriented ontology” (Harman, Reference Harman2005; Meillassoux, Reference Meillassoux and Brassier2008). This is in part because I can only do so much in one paper, in part because I lack the requisite expertise in contemporary continental metaphysics; one thing I can say, though, is that the speculative realists would presumably reject the transcendental idealism I attribute to Sartre (Section 3.3) as an instance of “correlationism.”Footnote 4

With these preliminary remarks out of the way, here’s the plan for the paper. After defining Eleatic monism and presenting some prima facie textual evidence for the Eleatic monist reading in Section 2, I show that premises Sartre endorses in B&N can be used to reconstruct two Eleatic arguments: one against the mind-independent reality of differentiation (Section 3.2) and the other against the mind-independent reality of temporal passage (Section 3.3). Underlying both arguments is a claim about negation and negativity that is both a central feature of the ontology of B&N and recognizable in the analytic literature on negative facts (Section 3.1). I consider some philosophical objections to the reconstructed arguments in Section 4. In Section 5, I evaluate a notable recent non-monistic reading of B&N and conclude that an Eleatic monist reading is both textually viable and philosophically interesting.

2. Being-in-itself and Eleatic monism

Rea (Reference Rea2001, 129) defines Eleatic monism as the conjunction of the following four theses:

  1. (a) There exists exactly one material thing.

  2. (b) What exists does not change.

  3. (c) Nothing is generated or destroyed.

  4. (d) What exists is undivided.

It’s important to keep in mind that if Sartre is a monist, his monism applies only to one of the regions of being he distinguishes. The “ontological proof” that Sartre presents in the Introduction to B&N is meant to refute a form of idealism on which all physical objects depend for their existence and nature on consciousness. The upshot of the argument is that there are “two absolutely distinct regions of being:” consciousness or “being-for-itself,” on the one hand, and mind-independent reality or “being-in-itself,” on the other. Sartrean Eleatic monism, to a first rough approximation that will be refined below, is the view that there is exactly one instance of being-in-itself, which is not subject to change, generation and destruction, or division.

The obscure final section of the Introduction, in which Sartre discusses the nature of being-in-itself, provides the main textual evidence for a monistic reading of B&N. Let’s start with Eleatic theses (b) and (c), which deny change (whether qualitative or substantial) to being-in-itself.

Transitions and becomings—anything that allows one to say that being is not yet what it will be, and that it is already what it is not—all of this is necessarily ruled out by being.

From this point of view… it escapes temporality. It is, and when it collapses one cannot even say that it is no longer.

Uncreated, without any reason for being or any relationship with any other being, being-in-itself is de trop for eternity. (B&N 29)

Being-in-itself is not subject to “transitions:” this suggests a denial of qualitative change. It is not subject to “becomings:” this suggests a denial of substantial change (generation and destruction). It is “uncreated” and “de trop for eternity:” this suggests a denial of substantial change for the cosmos as a whole. Finally, “it escapes temporality:” insofar as qualitative and substantial change occur in time, this too is suggestive of Eleatic theses (b) and (c).

Another passage that lends prima facie textual support to a reading on which Sartre denies substantial change to being-in-itself is the famous discussion of destruction.Footnote 5

A geological fold, or a storm, does not destroy anything—or, at least, they do not destroy directly: they merely alter the distribution of the mass of beings. After the storm there is no less than before. There is something else. And even this phrase is inappropriate, because in order to posit the disparity, we need a witness who can in some way retain the past and compare it to the present in the form of a ‘no longer’. (B&N 39)

Sartre’s claim here seems to be that there is no destruction without consciousness, i.e., being-for-itself. One way of understanding this claim is that consciousness carves up the “amorphous lump” (Dummett, Reference Dummett1973) or “blobject” (Horgan & Potrč, Reference Horgan, Potrč and Goff2012) of being-in-itself into discrete individuals; considered in itself, the blob loses nothing in a storm, earthquake, or war.

Next let’s turn to the Eleatic thesis (d):

It is as if a decompression of being were required to liberate an affirming of itself in the heart of being. Nor should we understand being as one undifferentiated self-affirmation: the lack of differentiation in the in-itself lies beyond an infinite number of ways of affirming oneself. We can sum up these first results by saying that being is in itself. (B&N 26–7)

Sartre’s talk of undifferentiation here is suggestive of the claim that mind-independent reality is undivided. Yet this passage is also in tension with thesis (a), insofar as Sartre denies that we should think of being-in-itself as (exactly) one undifferentiated being. I will return to this issue at the end of Section 3.2, where I follow Michael (Reference Michael2020) in replacing (a) with a more accurate way of formulating the monist position.

A number of commentators have taken the appearance of Eleatic monism in B&N at face value. For example, David Detmer writes

Being for itself makes a world out of being in itself through negation, much as a sculptor makes a sculpture through negative carving, by removing part of a slab of stone. (Detmer, Reference Detmer2008, 65)

Christine Daigle presents a similar picture:

The world of differences, categories, objects, space, and time is the world of phenomena for consciousness. It is consciousness that introduces such distinctions, and thus generates a world. Being-in-itself, however, remains unaffected by this. It is what it is. It is timeless, changeless: it is. (Daigle, Reference Daigle2010, 33)

Other interpreters who read Sartre as a monist about being-in-itself include Barnes (Reference Barnes and Sartre1993), Pettit (Reference Pettit1968), and Spade (Reference Spade1996). Pettit and Spade emphasize the specifically Eleatic resonances of Sartre’s position. Pettit, for instance, summarizes his comparison of Sartre and Parmenides as follows: “Like his forerunner, Sartre defines being in terms of self-identity, asserts at least its intensive monopoly, and regards it as eternal, static, one and homogenous” (172–3). Spade (Reference Spade1996) writes: “I cannot read this passage without thinking that Sartre had Parmenides in mind” (78). Spade also suggests that the “classical philosophical problem of negation” is behind Sartre’s Parmenidean pronouncements. I will develop this suggestion in detail in Section 3.

I will consider some textual evidence that prima facie tells against the Eleatic monist reading in Section 5, but I think the passages above give us good reason to ask whether Sartre has principled reasons for accepting Eleatic monism about being-in-itself. My answer (if the reader will allow me a bad pun) is fully positive.

3. Negation and Monism

In this section, I will develop Sartrean arguments for two Eleatic theses: that mind-independent reality is undifferentiated (Section 3.2) and that mind-independent reality is not fundamentally temporal (Section 3.3). The common ground between these arguments is a claim about negation: negation is not part of the fundamental structure of mind-independent reality. Before proceeding to the reconstructed arguments, I will first say a few words to elucidate this claim and to display its Sartrean credentials.

3.1. Against fundamental negation

Sartre characterizes being-in-itself as fully positive: “It is what it is, which means that, on its own, it cannot even not be what it is not; indeed we saw that it does not include any negation. It is full positivity” (B&N 28). This is in contrast to being-for-itself, which Sartre characterizes in terms of nothingness or “internal negation” (B&N 249–50). My purpose in this subsection is to spell out a principle that will be central to the Sartrean arguments I reconstruct in the remainder of Section 3.

The key principle is this: There is no fundamental negation or negativity. Russell (Reference Russell1919) speaks to the intuitive pull of this principle:

There is implanted in the human breast an almost unquenchable desire to find some way of avoiding the admission that negative facts are as ultimate as those that are positive.

(4)

Negative truths are generally taken to be a hard case for a theory of truthmakers. Theories of truthmaking are guided by the idea that “truth depends on being.” Negative truths pose a challenge insofar as their subject matter seems to concern not being, but non-being. One way to provide truthmakers for negative truths is to allow negative facts into one’s ontology. But as Fraser MacBride writes, “negative facts are an unruly bunch” (2022). First, positing negative facts is a heavy ontological commitment, since there are indefinitely many ways that reality is not. Second, if facts have constituents, it’s hard to see how negative facts concerning nonexistent objects and properties could obtain. A more conservative approach posits a “totality fact” as the truthmaker for all negative truths (Armstrong, Reference Armstrong2004).

So far I have spoken in ontological terms of negative facts. But it will be useful going forward to speak not only in ontological but also in ideological terms. Following Quine (Reference Quine1951), it is customary to distinguish a theory’s ontology—which entities it posits—from its ideology—the primitive concepts in which it is expressed. A theory’s ideology is the set of concepts needed to “write the book of the world,” “carve reality at the joints,” or limn reality’s structure (Lewis, Reference Lewis1983; Sider, Reference Sider2011). In the pursuit of a parsimonious theory, we often have to balance ontology and ideology against each other: a simpler ontology will require a more complex ideology and vice versa (Cowling, Reference Cowling2013; Quine, Reference Quine1951). For one example, in accounting for objective similarity, David Armstrong makes an ontological posit of universals, whereas David Lewis makes an ideological posit with the notion of naturalness. For another, eternalist theories of time posit past and future objects, whereas Priorian presentists posit primitive temporal operators. A familiar starting point in formulating a theory’s ideology is first-order predicate logic with identity. There is then room for debate about whether temporal and modal operators, operators for grounding and essence, mereological and set-theoretic concepts, and higher-order, plural, and mass quantification are part of primitive ideology. Moreover, there is room for debate about which logical concepts best limn reality’s logical structure (McSweeney, Reference McSweeney2019; Sider, Reference Sider2011).

Expressed in ideological terms, the principle that I see as implicit in Sartre’s characterization of being-in-itself is this: Negation and other negative concepts are not part of the primitive ideology needed to give a complete and perspicuous description of the mind-independent world. This is in contrast to being-for-itself, which can only be adequately characterized in terms of “internal” or constitutive negation. Spade gives perfect expression to this ideological principle in his discussion of Sartre’s relation to Parmenides: “…it ought to be possible to describe the whole of reality without ever once resorting to the little negative word ‘not’, or to any other negative word that implicitly has ‘not’ built into it. It ought to be possible simply to strike the word ‘not’ from our vocabulary” (76–7).

3.2. Against differentiation

The key to the Sartrean case against differentiation is the slogan “Omnis determinatio est negation: All determination is negation. This slogan was introduced by Spinoza and adapted by Hegel (see Melamed, Reference Melamed, Förster and Melamed2012 for discussion). Sartre devotes a section of the “Transcendence” chapter of B&N to unpacking the formula. In this subsection, I will summarize Sartre’s discussion of the slogan, introduce and set aside two readings of it, introduce my own reading, and mobilize it in defense of the Eleatic thesis that being-in-itself is undifferentiated.

The “Transcendence” chapter of B&N is devoted to articulating the relations that obtain between consciousness (being-for-itself) and mind-independent reality (being-in-itself). Much of the chapter is concerned with the constitution of various features of the manifest world, including determination or individuality, object-property structure (quality), spatiality and quantity, potentiality, equipmentality, and world-time. Sartre begins the section “On Determination as Negation” as follows:

To which being is the for-itself present? Let us note straight away that the question is badly put: being is what it is, and it cannot bear by itself the determination ‘this one’, in answer to the question ‘which one?’… the for-itself cannot be present to this one rather than that one, since its presence is what makes it the case that there is a ‘this one’ rather than a ‘that one’… The negativity of original transcendence is not determined on the basis of a this; rather, it makes it the case that a this exists. (B&N 263)

Taken at face value, this passage appears to say that the differentiation of being-in-itself into individuals (‘this’ and ‘that’) is dependent upon being-for-itself. On a straightforward reading, the idea is that determination or individuality consists in distinctness facts—e.g., “The table≠the chair”—which, as negative facts, depend on being-for-itself.

A deflationary reading of “all determination is negation” interprets Sartre as making a phenomenological point about conditions of the perception of individuals rather than an ontological point about principles of individuation. As Eshleman (Reference Eshleman, Eshleman and Mui2020) notes, the method of B&N is a complex mixture of phenomenological description, ontological analysis, transcendental argumentation, and metaphysical speculation. A phenomenological reading of the slogan is suggested by Sartre’s appeal to the figure-ground structure studied by the Gestalt psychologists: “The original relation between the whole and the this is at the source of the relation, illuminated by Gestalttheorie, between the ground and the figure” (B&N 258). On this reading, Sartre is concerned in “On Determination as Negation” with “constitution” in the Husserlian sense: not the construction or dependence of entities and their features from/on consciousness, but rather the structures of conscious acts in virtue of which entities and features are perceptually given (or otherwise consciously intended) (Hopp, Reference Hopp2020, 68).

The structures studied by the Gestalt psychologists are certainly important for phenomenology generally (see Gurwitsch, Reference Gurwitsch and Kersten2009) and for Sartre in particular (for instance, in his famous description of Pierre’s absence from the café). Against this phenomenological reading of the omnis principle, though, note again that Sartre claims that the negativity of consciousness “makes it the case that a this exists.” This language of “making it the case” strongly suggests that Sartre is making a claim about explanation or ontological dependence. And this suggests that in the “On Determination as Negation,” Sartre is concerned with an ontological account of how individuation occurs, rather than a phenomenological account of how individuals are given.

Another deflationary reading can be drawn from Brandom’s (Reference Brandom2019) discussion of Hegel’s adaptation of Spinoza’s slogan. On Brandom’s reading of the “Perception” chapter of the Phenomenology of Spirit, the kind of sensory awareness involved in perception of determinate particulars must be understood in terms of relations of material incompatibility, a relation that (Brandom’s) Hegel takes to be prior to formal or logical negation. Although Sartre’s debt to Hegel is undeniable and worth exploring in detail, Brandom’s formulation of “all determination is negation” is not available to Sartre as I interpret him. I’m sympathetic to the view that formal negation for Sartre is grounded in a more robust form of incompatibility.Footnote 6 Yet, I take it that Sartre’s ban on fundamental negativity applies not only to formal negation but to any negativity ideology, including incompatibility.Footnote 7 Second, as Brandom notes, determinate negation or material incompatibility is an irreducibly modal notion. Yet for Sartre, modality is a structure of the for-itself (see B&N Part Two, Chapter 1, Section 4). Insofar as relations of determinate negation are meant to obtain between concepts understood according to Hegel’s “conceptual realism” or “nonpsychological conception of the conceptual,” according to which “the objective world is always already in a conceptual…shape,” I’m doubtful that this reading of the slogan is available to Sartre (Brandom, Reference Brandom2019, 3).

On the two interpretations I’ve rejected, “all determination is negation” is a phenomenological claim—about the Gestalt structure of perception, on the first interpretation, or about the modally rich content of perception, on the other. On the reading I favor, “all determination is negation” is a claim about the ideological commitment of a pluralist metaphysics, i.e., a theory according to which there are many entities. Consider the simplest pluralist hypothesis: there are at least two entities. In first-order logic with identity, the entry in the “book of the world” for this hypothesis is

$$ \exists \mathrm{x}\exists \mathrm{y}\left(\mathrm{x}\ne \mathrm{y}\right) $$

The entry for the monistic hypothesis, on the other hand, is

$$ \exists \mathrm{x}\forall \mathrm{y}\left(\mathrm{x}=\mathrm{y}\right) $$

Compare the ideological commitments of the hypotheses: both employ quantification and identity, but only the pluralistic hypothesis employs negation. What the slogan says, then, is that any differentiation of reality into distinct (determinate) individuals incurs an ideological commitment to negation. Though expressed in a different idiom than Sartre would employ, I think this interpretation captures the point about individuation Sartre is making in “On Determination as Negation:” the differentiation of being-in-itself into ‘this’ and ‘that’ rests on negated identities like ‘the inkwell is not the table’ (B&N 262).

The pieces are now in place to complete the Sartrean argument for the Eleatic thesis that mind-independent reality is undifferentiated. By “all determination is negation,” differentiation depends on negation in the sense that one cannot formulate a pluralist metaphysics without employing negation. By “no fundamental negativity,” mind-independent reality cannot be accurately represented in irreducibly negative terms. It follows that a pluralistic metaphysics cannot accurately represent mind-independent reality. Thus mind-independent reality, or being-in-itself, is undifferentiated. This corresponds to Rea’s thesis (d): What exists is undivided.

What about thesis (a): There is exactly one material thing? Michael (Reference Michael2020) mounts a Bradleyan regress argument against the existence/intelligibility of relations, concluding that reality is undifferentiated. But he denies that the answer to the question “How many things are there?” is “one.” Rather, Della Rocca holds that in rejecting relations as unintelligible, one must also reject counting as unintelligible. His monist view is best expressed not as “There is exactly one being,” but rather “There is, simply, being” (78–82). As I noted in Section 2, Sartre’s obscure description of the undifferentiated nature of being-in-itself could be read as making a similar point. Moreover, “all determination is negation” might be taken to entail such a view: insofar as being-in-itself is free of negation, it is thereby free of determination and thus doesn’t even count as an individual. Insofar as the quantifiers of first-order logic are typically taken to range over individuals, this suggests that any regimentation into first-order logic will fail to fully capture the monist position. Della Rocca recognizes as much when he ends his defense of monism with a Tractarian gesture of silence at what cannot be said (namely, a blank page) (Michael, Reference Michael2020, 291).

I agree with Della Rocca that the Eleatic monist should deny that first-order logic adequately limns the structure of reality. As a friendly amendment to his position, though, I think that monism can be articulated in terms of mass quantification. Just as some authors argue that plural quantification (quantification over pluralities) is irreducible to singular quantification (quantification over individuals), Laycock (Reference Laycock2006) and McKay (Reference McKay and Carrara2016) have argued that mass quantification (quantification over stuff) is irreducible to quantification over individuals (singular or plural). Being-in-itself, on the Eleatic monist interpretation, is not an individual; it is an “amorphous lump” (or rather, some amorphous stuff) that gets “carved up” by consciousness. This suggests that monism is best expressed as follows

$$ \exists \unicode{x03BC} \forall \nu \left(\nu \le \unicode{x03BC} \right) $$

where ‘≤’ is the relation of parthood and μ and ν are variables ranging over stuff rather than individuals. In English, this formula reads: “There is some stuff of which all stuff is a part [or maybe more perspicuously, if less grammatically: of which all stuff is some].” This claim about parthood might seem incompatible with Eleatic thesis (d). But I take it that the force of (d) is that reality is not divided into individuals, or relatedly that there is no privileged decomposition of reality. Footnote 8

Despite this amendment to Della Rocca’s view, I think the monist will still have to resort to his Tractarian maneuvers. This is because the monist cannot say that reality does not divide into individuals, on pain of reintroducing negative and singularist ideology. Rather, (d) is best shown through the monist’s choice of ideology—or rather, not by what she says, but by what she doesn’t say.

In this section, I have argued that two premises Sartre endorses—the full positivity of being-in-itself and “all determination is negation”—commit him to (suitably modified versions of) Eleatic theses (a) and (d). I now turn to theses (b) and (c). I will show that Sartre is committed to these theses because he is committed to denying that temporal passage is a feature of being-in-itself.

3.3. Against temporality

We saw above that Sartre claims in the Introduction to B&N that being-in-itself “escapes temporality.” He expands upon this claim in the “Temporality” chapter:

…we may describe the law that applies to the being of an intraworldly instant in these simple words: ‘Being is’—and these words express a massive plenitude of positivity, in which nothing of what is not can be represented in any way whatsoever, not even by a trace, or a void, or a reminder, or a ‘hysteresis’. Being that is exhausts itself entirely in being; it has nothing to do with what is not, or with what is no longer. No negation, whether it be radical or in the milder form of ‘no… longer’, can find any place within this absolute density. (B&N 167)

Sommerlatte (Reference Sommerlatte, Eschleman and Mui2020) reads Sartre as claiming that “temporality is ontologically dependent on consciousness, and consciousness can only exist temporally” (198). Sommerlatte flags the similarity of Sartre’s view to Kant’s transcendental idealism (202). The Eleatic monist reading naturally leads to a transcendental idealist reading on which the differentiation and temporality of the manifest world are grounded in the negativity of consciousness.Footnote 9 On this view, differentiation and temporality are what Sartre calls négatités. Erhard (Reference Erhard, Eshleman and Mui2020) describes négatités as “existent yet irreducibly and essentially negative phenomena” (172). The most famous example of a négatité in B&N is Pierre’s absence from the café. Négatités are “transcendent realities,” but they “all immediately underline an essential relation of human-reality with the world” (B&N 60). They thereby resemble the features of the manifest world that Kant sees as dependent on the forms of sensibility and understanding but nevertheless objective features of appearances. Insofar as differentiation and temporality are irreducibly negative for Sartre, they are négatités and thus transcendentally ideal but empirically real features of the manifest world.

My plan for this subsection is to reconstruct Sartre’s argument that being-in-itself is not temporal against the backdrop of J.M.E. McTaggart’s (Reference McTaggart1908) infamous argument for the unreality of time. This manner of presentation will be useful because McTaggart’s argument has provided a framework, at least terminologically, for the analytic literature on time that I will draw upon to critically evaluate Sartre’s case against the temporality of being-in-itself. Since McTaggart it has been standard to distinguish two temporal series. The A-series orders temporal positions using the properties of being present, being past, and being future. The B-series orders temporal positions by the relations earlier than and later than. A-theorists hold that the A-series is fundamental, whereas B-theorists hold that all change can be described in terms of the B-series. A-theorists accord special ontological status to the present and defend the reality of temporal passage, whereas B-theorists hold that all times are equally real and hold a “spatialized” view of time (see Sider, Reference Sider2011, Chapter 11 for discussion). In the section “The Ontology of Temporality” Sartre draws a distinction that I believe maps onto the A/B-series distinction. What Sartre calls “static temporality” is the ordering of time in terms of “before” and “after”—this is the B-series. What Sartre calls “dynamic temporality” describes the flow of time from the past to the present to the future—this is the A-series.

McTaggart’s argument for the unreality of time runs as follows:

P1. Time is real only if the A-series exists.

P2. The A-series does not exist.

So, C. Time is unreal.

McTaggart argues for P1 as follows: Time is real only if real change occurs, and real change occurs only if there is an A-series. In defense of P2, he argues that the existence of an A-series would entail contradictions. This is because the A-properties are incompatible, and yet all events possess being past, being present, and being future—from different temporal perspectives, as it were (see Fine, Reference Fine2006) for a helpful presentation of the argument). Both premises of McTaggart’s argument have been subjected to extensive scrutiny. Without getting into these controversies, we can use McTaggart’s argument as a jumping-off point for exploring Sartre’s case against the fundamental reality of time.

The basic idea behind Sartre’s argument is that A-series concepts are pieces of negative ideology. In order to capture the flow or passage of time, the present has to be accorded a special status. Expressed ideologically, this special status is that the past and future are defined negatively by contrast to the present: the past is no-longer present, and the future is not-yet present. Given Sartre’s ban on negative fundamental ideology, being past and being future cannot accurately characterize mind-independent reality. But then the A-series does not belong to mind-independent reality. And if we loan McTaggart’s P1 to Sartre, it follows that being-in-itself “escapes temporality.”

I will discuss an objection to this argument in Section 4.2, but for now a few comments are in order. First, for Sartre it does not follow from the fact that being-in-itself is atemporal that time is unreal; rather, Sartre on this interpretation holds, like Kant, that time is empirically real but transcendentally ideal. This is because being-in-itself doesn’t exhaust what’s real, and temporality is a basic feature of consciousness or being-for-itself. In the “Temporality” chapter, Sartre cashes out the A-series in terms of structures discussed in the previous chapter, “The Immediate Structures of the For-Itself:” facticity, lack, value, and possibility (Sommerlatte, Reference Sommerlatte, Eschleman and Mui2020, 201). Later in the book, Sartre extends his analysis to the temporality of objects and the intersubjective temporality of the shared world (Sommerlatte, Reference Sommerlatte, Eschleman and Mui2020, 209).

Second, Sartre doesn’t just think that the past and future are defined negatively; he also thinks that the concept of the present is negative. This is because he analyzes the present at its most basic level in terms of what is intentionally present to consciousness (B&N 180–4). As he will go on to explore in the “Transcendence” chapter, intentionality has to be understood in terms of a kind of “internal negation”—in particular, consciousness’s not being the object toward which it is intentionally directed.

Third, Sartre holds not only that “dynamic temporality” (the A-series) depends on being-for-itself but also that “static temporality” (the B-series) depends on being-for-itself. This seems to be because static temporality has not just an order but also a direction, which, on Sartre’s view only being-for-itself can impose. Note that in rejecting the fundamentality of the B-series in addition to the A-series Sartre actually follows McTaggart, who recognizes a C-series that “is not temporal, for it involves no change, but only an order” (1908, 462).

Finally, note that while Sartre and McTaggart agree that the A-series is not fundamental, they do so for different reasons. McTaggart rejects the A-series because it is contradictory, whereas Sartre rejects it because of its negativity. This is worth mentioning for two reasons. First, though they share an obvious kinship, Sartre and McTaggart’s arguments for the unreality of time don’t stand or fall together; even if McTaggart’s argument that the A-series is inconsistent is unsound, there might still be hope for Sartre’s argument. Second, on the other hand, Sartre is not exactly shy of asserting what appear to be flat-out contradictions concerning being-for-itself. If we should read these flirtations with contradiction at face value, Sartre could happily accept McTaggart’s argument for the inconsistency of the A-series as providing confirmation of a dialetheic account of being-for-itself, i.e., an account on which there are true contradictions concerning being-for-itself.Footnote 10

In Section 3, I have reconstructed Sartrean arguments for two Eleatic theses: that being-in-itself is undifferentiated and that it is not subject to temporality. Both arguments rely on a ban on fundamental negative ideology that, while controversial, seems to be a foundational assumption of B&N and one with some intuitive plausibility. In the next section I will draw upon analytic discussions of negative facts, identity, and time to pose some challenges to the reconstructed arguments and consider how the Sartrean monist might respond.

4. Philosophical Objections

4.1. Differentiation

In Section 3.2, I reconstructed the following argument for the Eleatic thesis that mind-independent reality is undifferentiated: Pluralism is committed to admitting negation as part of its primitive ideology; because being-in-itself is “full positivity,” there is no fundamental negation, so pluralism cannot adequately represent mind-independent reality. In this subsection, I’ll consider several challenges to this argument, in ascending order of severity.

According to the first challenge, monism is implicitly committed to fundamental negation via its commitment to universal quantification. The thought is that, since the quantifiers are duals (i.e., ∀xφ is classically equivalent to ¬∃x¬φ), ideological commitment to universal quantification carries ideological commitment to negation. This worry is easily handled. On the Sartrean view I’ve sketched, the classical equivalence does not hold in the language used to “write the book of the world,” since that language does not contain negation. In the fundamental language, the existential and universal quantifiers are both primitive. This is compatible with holding that the classical equivalence holds in the non-fundamental language used to describe the manifest world (i.e., the world as structured by being-for-itself and its constitutive nothingness).

The next two questions were posed by an anonymous referee.Footnote 11 The first question is whether the “undifferentiation” of being-in-itself entails its “homogeneity.” I’ve interpreted the denial of differentiation as the denial that being-in-itself admits of a privileged, mind-independent decomposition into individuals. But we could also ask whether being-in-itself is (for lack of a better phrase) diversely propertied (F here, G there). That is, we could ask whether the “book of being-in-itself” could, compatibly with the ban on negative ideology, contain locutions capturing the qualitative diversity of the manifest world. Perhaps, the Sartrean monist could do this using a “feature-placing language” (Strawson, Reference Strawson1964), but this prospect raises two questions—one philosophical and one textual. First, it’s not clear to me whether qualitative diversity could be captured in a feature-placing language without smuggling in negative ideology through the backdoor. Second, Sartre seems to deny that we can say much of substance about being-in-itself beyond a simple: “It is what it is” (B&N 28). The referee’s second question is whether, if being-in-itself is not only undifferentiated but also homogenous, the second Eleatic monist argument becomes otiose. The thought is that, if we accept that time requires real change and also that being-in-itself is homogenous, it follows straightforwardly that being-in-itself is atemporal. I think there’s definitely something to this, but that it’s still dialectically worth laying out an independent case against temporality in case an alternative reading of the omnis principle turns out to be viable.

A third worry is that Sartre’s claim that there is no fundamental negation is simply false. Sider (Reference Sider2011), for example, argues that negation is part of fundamental ideology. He criticizes a rival truth-making conception of fundamentality on which all claims involving negation are made true by the existence of some entity or entities. His complaint is that this theory either smuggles in facts involving the banned negative ideology, or else it is ultimately unexplanatory (157–61). On the one hand, truthmaker theorists might appeal to a totality fact (“that’s all”), but Sider plausibly argues that this is implicitly negative (“there’s nothing more”). On the other hand, without this totality fact, the truthmaker theorist will just cite the fundamental entities as the truthmakers for all truths, but “[i]t’s hard to see how all the complexity we experience could possibly be explained from that sparse basis” (160). Evaluating this objection is well beyond the scope of this paper, but I suspect that matters would look very different in the transcendental idealist framework I attribute to Sartre, where the negativity of consciousness plays a decisive role in explaining the features of the manifest world.

Fourth, consider Stephen Barker’s and Mark Jago’s proposal for “being positive about negative facts” (Barker & Jago Reference Barker and Jago2012). Following Armstrong (Reference Armstrong1997), they hold that facts or states of affairs consist of particulars and properties standing in a non-mereological relation of unity. Their proposal is that this non-mereological unity relation comes in different flavors. To use their example, in the fact the lake’s being frozen, the particular (the lake) is unified with the property (frozenness) by instantiation, whereas in the fact the lake’s not being frozen, they are unified by anti-instantiation. Barker and Jago argue that their theory answers traditional worries about negative facts by showing how they exist in the same way as positive facts, are spatiotemporally located, and are causally efficacious. Applying the account to the case of differentiation, the distinctness facts underlying determination, e.g., “The table≠the chair,” would be analyzed in terms of the table, the chair, and the identity relation being unified by anti-instantiation. The Sartrean Eleatic monist would have to object that Barker and Jago’s anti-instantiation is a piece of negative ideology and so ruled out by the ban on negative ideology. Of course the ban on negative ideology is the big unargued-for premise in the case for Sartrean Eleatic monism, though one that Sartre could perhaps motivate on phenomenological grounds: he claims that being-in-itself—presumably including its full positivity—is disclosed to us immediately in boredom and nausea (B&N 6).

The final and most serious worry is that the distinctness facts posited by the pluralist are not fundamental. I’ll discuss two versions of this objection. The first appeals to the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles: distinctness facts are grounded in facts about discernibility. That is, the fact that a≠b is grounded in differences in the properties of a and b. The problem with this proposal as a response to Sartre is obvious: discernibility facts are expressed using negation. The second and more promising version of the objection seeks to ground distinctness facts in existence facts. The thought here is that a≠b is grounded in the existence of a and the existence of b. Burgess (Reference Burgess2012) illustrates the view as follows:

Imagine God creating a field of poppies. Once the flowers exist, there’s no need for Her to survey the field and stipulate that this poppy will be identical to itself, and distinct from that poppy, that poppy, etc. Intuitively, the identity/distinctness facts come along for free; they seem to be nothing over and above the relevant existential facts. (90)

Turner (2013) makes a similar point in a different context, claiming that identity is “thin:” “there’s nothing to identity over and above the existence of the individuals in question” (4). If this proposal for grounding distinctness facts in existential facts is workable, the pluralist can eliminate negation from her fundamental ideology, undermining the Sartrean case against differentiation I reconstructed. While this strikes me as a plausible reply for the pluralist to make, it may suffer from a circularity problem: the distinctness fact a≠b is grounded in the plurality of existence facts [Ea], [Eb], but what explains the distinctness of [Ea] and [Eb], other than the fact that a≠b?Footnote 12

4.2. Temporality

In Section 3.3, I reconstructed the following argument for the Eleatic thesis that mind-independent reality “escapes temporality:” Time is fundamental only if an A-series exists; concepts for the A-series are pieces of negative ideology; there is no fundamental negation; so mind-independent reality is atemporal. Since I discussed the possibility of fundamental negation in the last subsection, in this subsection, I will sketch an objection to the claim that A-series concepts are negative ideology.

The objection I have in mind derives from Arthur Prior’s tense realism. According to Prior, tense logic is part of fundamental ideology. Tense logic adds tense operators like the following to standard propositional or predicate logic:

P “It has at some time been the case that…”

F “It will at some time be the case that…”

The key point here is that, on the Priorian picture, these operators are primitive:

Tense logic is for me, if I may use the phrase, metaphysically fundamental, and not just an artificially torn-off fragment of the first-order theory of the earlier-later relation. (Prior and Fine Reference Prior and Fine1977, 32; quoted in Sider, Reference Sider2011, 240)

The Priorian view constitutes a challenge to the Sartrean argument against the temporality of being-in-itself because it denies that P and F are defined in terms of negation. Thus the Priorian tense realist can capture facts about temporal passage without violating the ban on fundamental negative ideology.

I find this objection fairly compelling, but let me mention one way that the Sartrean Eleatic monist could respond. Sider (Reference Sider2001) accuses tense realists of “cheating,” where the “cheater is unwilling to accept an ontology robust enough to bear the weight of the truths he feels free to invoke” (41). The problem is that primitive tensed properties are objectionably hypothetical in the sense that they “point beyond” their instances (Ibid.; see Caplan & Sanson, Reference Caplan and Sanson2011 for discussion). Though this is to trade a relatively lucid metaphor for some far more obscure metaphors, this worry about hypotheticality seems to be part of what Sartre is getting at in describing being-in-itself as “immanent,” “opaque,” and “massive” (B&N 26–7).

5. Textual Objections

Although the impression that Sartre flirts with Eleatic monism is widespread, a number of scholars have recently challenged the Eleatic monist reading. Sebastian Gardner, for example, begins by registering the appearance of Eleatic monism in Sartre’s notion of being-in-itself.

It seems that Sartre’s picture is one on which a Spinozist or Parmenidean One lurks, somehow still visible and showing through from behind a thin phantasmagoria of phenomenal objects projected onto it. Even if there is no immediate logical inconsistency in this picture, still it seems barely coherent. (Gardner, Reference Gardner2009, 76)

This picture, while certainly revisionary, doesn’t strike me as “barely coherent,” especially given the detailed defenses of monism in recent analytic metaphysics. In any case, Gardner sketches his alternative picture in discussion of the famous description of the chestnut tree root in Nausea.

It [existence] had lost its harmless appearance as an abstract category: it was the very stuff of things, that root was steeped into existence. Or rather the root, the park gates, the bench, the sparse grass on the lawn, all that had vanished; the diversity of things, their individuality, were only an appearance, a veneer. This veneer had melted, leaving soft, monstrous masses, in disorder—naked, with a frightening, obscene nakedness. (Sartre Reference Sartre and Alexander2007, 183)

On Gardner’s non-monist reading, the shift brought about by an experience of nausea is not best captured in terms of the contrast of “a conceptualized, determinately propertied object, with a raw, property-less substrate or raw matter” (Gardner, Reference Gardner2009, 78). Instead, the contrast between an ordinary experience and that of nausea is a difference in two “modes of apprehension:” an apprehension of the tree root as intelligible and meaningful in virtue of its connection to human projects versus an apprehension of the tree root in its brute, contingent existence. While Gardner puts this non-monistic interpretation on the table, he seems to think the monism-plus-transcendental-idealism reading I’ve defended is still viable (Gardner, Reference Gardner2009, 80).

Gusman (Reference Gusman2022) decisively rejects the monistic reading—what he describes as the “common misconception” that “outside of consciousness a monolithic mass of brute being exists from which consciousness distills definitive objects” (Gusman, Reference Gusman2022, 120). By my count, Gusman gives three main arguments against the monist reading. First, following Gardner, Gusman argues that Sartre’s description of what nausea reveals in the tree root scene from Nausea is incompatible with the monist reading. Second, Gusman argues that Sartre’s remarks on differentiation and totality in the Introduction to B&N and “On Determination as Negation” are incompatible with the monist reading. Third, in what I take to be his strongest argument, Gusman appeals to a passage from the 1947 lecture “Self-Consciousness and Self-Knowledge” to argue that being-in-itself is a mode of being rather than a “monolithic mass of brute being.” I’ll take each of these arguments in turn.

First, Gusman points out that in the tree root scene, Sartre refers to “masses, in disorder.” Gusman makes two points about this phrase. First, “[‘Masses’] is clearly plural, suggesting masses of beings rather than a single being” (Gusman, Reference Gusman2022, 125). Second, “These masses are in disorder, which also excludes that it is a single being. How can a single being be in disorder?” (Ibid.) To the first point, recall that the proper formulation of the Eleatic monist view I offered in Section 3.2 allows that there are “masses” of stuff that are part of the amorphous stuff of being-in-itself, as long as there is no privileged, mind-independent decomposition of being-in-itself into individuals. To the second point, the reference to “disorder” in the Nausea passage can be easily accommodated on the monism-plus-transcendental idealism reading. On this reading, what nausea reveals is that the order characteristic of the manifest image is not intrinsic to being-in-itself, but is rather due to the various ontological structures of being-for-itself. The “masses” are “in disorder” in the experience of nausea because the decomposition of being-in-itself into individuals characteristic of ordinary experience is shown to be a contingent imposition of consciousness.

Second, Gusman argues that some of the passages I’ve cited in support of my reading actually tell in favor of the non-monistic reading. First, he claims that Sartre’s denial that being-in-itself is “one undifferentiated self-affirmation” shows that the monist reading is untenable. He cites another passage from “On Determination as Negation” in support of the same point. There Sartre claims that “totality can only come to being only through the for-itself” (B&N 256). Remarking on this passage, Gusman writes: “Sartre cannot be more clear: there is no such thing as a pure monolithic being that encompasses all things outside of experience” (Gusman, Reference Gusman2022, 133). Gusman misreads these passages, or at least he overstates their evidential force in favor of a non-monist reading. First, I offered an alternative, monist-friendly reading of the Introduction passage about differentiation at the end of Section 3.2. As a reminder, Sartre’s point, as I read it, is that it’s not correct to say that there’s exactly one mind-independent being; following Della Rocca, the monist should instead say, “There is, simply, being,” and doing so requires a rejection of the ideology involved with individuals and counting (even counting to one). Second, and relatedly, Sartre’s point about totality is that “any totality presupposes an internal relation of being between the terms of a quasi-multiplicity,” i.e., that in order to quantify over all beings, those beings must already be individuated (B&N 256). This is perfectly compatible with the monist reading: Sartre’s point is that the concepts of individuality and totality are alike dependent on being-for-itself. Worse for Gusman, though, premises he endorses in his interpretation seem positively incompatible with a non-monist reading. Gusman writes that “Sartre stresses that the relationships between things are inessential to them: they are imposed upon them by us” (Gusman, Reference Gusman2022, 128). But if distinctness is included among these relationships, which Gusman seems to allow, then the argument I gave in Section 3.2 goes through. If distinctness is imposed by us, then there’s not a privileged, mind-independent decomposition of being-in-itself into individuals, as I’ve argued.

Finally, Gusman appeals to a passage from “Self-Consciousness and Self-Knowledge,” a 1947 lecture summarizing the arguments of the Introduction and Part II, Chapter 1 of B&N.

When it comes to being, however, we find that it accompanies all of an object’s appearances. In every one of its appearances, it remains the same. An appearance does not conceal it, but it does not reveal it, either. If I so please, I may cut this book into tiny pieces – [and] there will be as much being in each one of these pieces as there is in the book [as a whole]. When I change its form by burning it or gluing it together, there will always be the same amount of being in each of these manifestations. An infinite dissolution or transformation of the book will not reveal more of it to me, nor will it conceal it from me. (Sartre, Reference Sartre2023, 37)

This passage seems to tell against the Eleatic monist reading, since if being-in-itself were an amorphous stuff there would be less of it in each of the pieces of the book than there is in the book as a whole. Gusman interprets this passage as showing that being-in-itself is a mode of being, rather than an amorphous stuff. Sartre’s point then, according to Gusman, is that “[e]ach thing exists in this way, there is no ontological differentiation between their modes of being” (B&N 134). I admit that this passage should be read as making an “ontological” (about modes of being) rather than “ontic” (about entities) claim about being-in-itself, to use a Heideggerian distinction, and more generally that the distinction between being-in-itself and being-for-itself is a distinction in modes of being. But this is compatible with Sartre arguing that the mode of being-in-itself necessarily does not admit of plurality. The argument I reconstructed in Section 3.2 purports to show this, so in order to undermine the monist reading Gusman would need to say which premise of the reconstructed argument against differentiation Sartre rejects.

I’ve argued that all three passages Gusman adduces in support of his non-monist reading are compatible with the monist reading. This doesn’t alone show that the monist reading is correct, of course, but it does shift the burden back to the non-monist to explain where I’ve gone wrong in attributing the two reconstructed arguments from Section 3 to Sartre. The non-monist needs to offer alternative readings of at least one of three key claims Sartre makes in B&N: the ban on negative ideology, the omnis determinatio est negatio principle, and the claim that temporal concepts are negative. On what I’ve argued are straightforward and plausible interpretations of these claims, Eleatic monism follows. I invite non-monist readers of B&N to develop such alternative interpretations; doing so can only enrich our understanding of this fascinating and frustrating book.

6. Conclusion

I’ve argued that premises Sartre endorses in B&N commit him to Eleatic monism, understood in terms of (suitably modified versions of) Rea’s theses (a)-(d). The arguments against the differentiation and temporality of being-in-itself should be of interest to analytic metaphysicians invested in the recent monist revival. Moreover, by showing that plausible interpretations of key Sartrean claims entail Eleatic monism, I hope to have breathed new life into an old reading of Being and Nothingness.

Acknowledgements

This article has been cooking for a very long time, during which I’ve become indebted to a lot of people for shepherding it into being. An early version was presented at the APA Central in Denver, where I benefitted from Jeffrey Bell’s commentary and audience discussion. I received a lot of challenging and helpful questions from an audience at UC Riverside. Jim Kreines generously invited me to workshop the paper at his German idealism working group. Jake McNulty has been a huge advocate of the paper and made some invaluable suggestions on it. Michael Della Rocca likewise has been very generous in offering his feedback and support. Zach Joachim, Alex Yen, Aaron Garrett, and Michaela McSweeney gave me excellent feedback when I gave a mock talk. The biggest debt by far is to Jonathan Payton, whose suggestion about mass quantification transformed my thinking on the topic.

James Kinkaid is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Bilkent University. His research focuses on the phenomenological tradition, especially as it bears on contemporary metaphysics, philosophy of logic, and philosophy of mind.

Footnotes

1 This article is a sequel to my “Idealism and Transparency in Sartre’s Ontological Proof” (Kinkaid, Reference Kinkaidforthcoming), where I work out this interpretation of the ontological proof.

2 One difficulty in putting the phenomenological tradition into conversation with analytic metaphysics is that the two traditions draw the contrast between ontology and metaphysics differently. For the analytic tradition, following Quine, ontology is concerned with existence questions and is a subdiscipline of metaphysics. For the phenomenological tradition, ontology concerns essences, whereas metaphysics concerns existence (see the Conclusion to B&N for Sartre’s conception of metaphysics). This difficulty is merely terminological, however; Sartre’s “phenomenological ontology” counts as metaphysics in the analytic sense.

3 See, e.g., Longuenesse (Reference Longuenesse2017) and Boyle (Reference Boyle2024).

4 See Zahavi (Reference Zahavi2016) for a critical discussion of the speculative realists’ critique of the “correlationism” they attribute to the phenomenological tradition.

5 Thanks to Jake McNulty for suggesting this.

6 See Kinkaid (Reference Kinkaid2020, 1023-5).

7 See MacBride (Reference MacBride, Zalta and Nodelman2022) for a discussion of difficulties involved in distinguishing positive and negative ideology.

8 Huge thanks to Jonathan Payton for suggesting this way of formulating the Eleatic monist position.

9 See Gardner (Reference Gardner2009, 75-84) and McCulloch (Reference McCulloch1994, 111-7) for critical discussion of the transcendental idealist reading of Sartre.

10 Jordan (Reference Jordan2017) explores an apparent dialetheia in Sartre’s account of reflection. Brown (Reference Brown2023) and McNulty (Reference McNulty2025) pursue dialetheic reading of the chapter on bad faith. The possibility of a dialetheic reading is mentioned, though rejected, by Erhard (Reference Erhard, Eshleman and Mui2020).

11 Thanks!

12 See Burgess (Reference Burgess2012) and Shumener (Reference Shumener2017) for discussion.

References

Armstrong, D. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511583308CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. (2004). Truth and truth-makers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511487552CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, S., & Jago, M. (2012). Being positive about negative facts. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(1), 117138.10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00479.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, H. (1993). “Translator’s introduction.” In Sartre, J., Being and nothingness (pp. xiiixliii). New York: Washington Square Press.Google Scholar
Boyle, M. (2024). Transparency and reflection: A study of self-knowledge and the nature of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780199926299.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandom, R. (2019). A spirit of trust: A reading of Hegel’s Phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, N. (2023). How is lying to oneself possible? The dialetheism reading of Sartre’s bad faith. Kritike, 17(1), 4357.10.25138/17.1.a2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Builes, D. (2021). The word just is the way it is. The Monist, 104(1), 127.10.1093/monist/onaa023CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, A. (2012). A puzzle about identity. Thought, 1, 9099.Google Scholar
Caplan, B., & Sanson, D. (2011). Presentism and truthmaking. Philosophy Compass, 6(3), 196208.10.1111/j.1747-9991.2010.00380.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cowling, S. (2013). Ideological parsimony. Synthese, 190, 38893908.10.1007/s11229-012-0231-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daigle, C. (2010). Jean-Paul Sartre. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Detmer, D. (2008). Sartre explained: From bad faith to authenticity. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: Philosophy of language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Erhard, C. (2020). Negation, nonbeing, and nothingness. In Eshleman, M. & Mui, C. (Eds.), The Sartrean mind (pp. 172185). New York: Routledge.10.4324/9781315100500-12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eshleman, M. (2020). On the structure and method of being and nothingness. In Eshleman, M. & Mui, C. (Eds.), The Sartrean mind (pp. 143157). New York: Routledge.10.4324/9781315100500-10CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. (2006). The reality of tense. Synthese, 150(3), 399414.10.1007/s11229-005-5515-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, S. (2009). Sartre’s being and nothingness: A reader’s guide. New York: Continuum.Google Scholar
Gurwitsch, A. (2009). Phenomenology of thematics and of the pure ego: Studies of the relation between gestalt theory and phenomenology. In Kersten, F. (Ed.), The collected works of Aron Gurwitsch vol. 2: Studies in phenomenology and psychology. Dordrecht: Springer Science+Business Media. (pp. 193318).Google Scholar
Gusman, S. (2022). The secret smiles of things: Sartre’s realism reconsidered. Human Studies, 45, 119137.10.1007/s10746-021-09604-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (2005). Guerilla metaphysics: Phenomenology and the carpentry of things. Chicago: Open Court Publishing.Google Scholar
Hopp, W. (2020). Phenomenology: A contemporary introduction. New York: Routledge.10.4324/9781003047216CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, T., & Potrč, M. (2012). “Existence monism trumps priority monism.” In Goff, P. (Ed.), Spinoza on monism (pp. 5176). London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Jordan, M. (2017). Sartrean self-consciousness and the principle of identity. Sartre Studies International, 23(2), 98113.10.3167/ssi.2017.230207CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinkaid, J. (2020). What would a phenomenology of logic look like? Mind, 129(516), 10091031.10.1093/mind/fzaa031CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinkaid, J. (Forthcoming). Idealism and transparency in Sartre’s ontological proof, Inquiry.Google Scholar
Laycock, H. (2006). Words without objects: Semantics, ontology, and logic for non-singularity. Oxford University Press.10.1093/0199281718.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 343377.10.1080/00048408312341131CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longuenesse, B. (2017). I, me, mine: Back to Kant, and back again. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199665761.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacBride, F. (2022). Truthmakers. In Zalta, E. & Nodelman, U. (Eds.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2022/entries/truthmakers/>..>Google Scholar
Marshall, C. (2020). Schopenhauer on the content of compassion. Noûs, 55(4), 782799.10.1111/nous.12330CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCulloch, G. (1994). Using Sartre: An analytical introduction to early Sartrean themes. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
McKay, T. J. (2016). Mass and Plural. In Carrara, M. (Ed.), Unity and plurality: Logic, philosophy, and linguistics (pp. 171–93). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McNulty, J. (2025). Bad faith as true contradiction: on the dialetheist interpretation of Sartre. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 110(1), 150171.10.1111/phpr.13095CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McSweeney, M. (2019). Logical realism and the metaphysics of logic. Philosophy Compass, 14(1), 110.10.1111/phc3.12563CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McTaggart, J. M. E. (1908). The unreality of time. Mind, 17(68), 457474.10.1093/mind/XVII.4.457CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meillassoux, Q. (2008). After finitude: An essay on the necessity of contingency. Translated by Brassier, Ray. London: Bloomsbury.10.5040/9781350252059CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Melamed, Y. (2012). Omnis determinatio est negatio’—Determination, negation and self-negation in Spinoza, Kant, and Hegel. In Förster, E. & Melamed, Y. (Eds.), Spinoza and German idealism (pp. 175196. Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139135139.011CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Michael, D. R. (2020). The parmenidean ascent. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prior, A. N. & Fine, K. (1977). Worlds, Times, and Selves. University of Massachusetts Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. (1968). Parmenides and Sartre. Philosophical Studies (Dublin), 17, 161184.10.5840/philstudies196817094CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Ontology and ideology. Philosophical Studies, 1, 1115.10.1007/BF02198233CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rea, M. (2001). How to be an eleatic monist. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 129151.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1919). On propositions: What they are, and how they mean. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume) 2, 143.10.1093/aristoteliansupp/2.1.1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sartre, J. (2007). Nausea. Translated by Alexander, Lloyd. New York: New Directions Books.Google Scholar
Sartre, J. (2018). Being and nothingness. Translated by Richmond, Sarah. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Sartre, J. (2023). Self-consciousness and self-knowledge. Translated by Marco D. Dozzi. Sartre Studies International, 29(1), 2289.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2010). Monism: The priority of the whole. Philosophical Review, 119, 3176.10.1215/00318108-2009-025CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shumener, E. (2017). The metaphysics of identity: Is identity fundamental? Philosophy Compass, 12, 11310.1111/phc3.12397CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, T. (2001). Four-dimensionalism: An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/019924443X.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199697908.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommerlatte, C. (2020). It’s about that time: Sartre’s theory of temporality. In Eschleman, M. & Mui, C. (Eds.), The Sartrean mind (pp.198211). New York: Routledge.10.4324/9781315100500-14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spade, P. (1996). Class lecture notes on “Jean-Paul Sartre’s Being and Nothingness.https://pvspade.com/Sartre/sartre.html.Google Scholar
Stern, R. (2017). British idealism. In Golob, S. & Timmerman, J. (Eds.), The Cambridge history of moral philosophy (pp. 535548). Cambridge University Press.10.1017/9781139519267.042CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1964. Individuals. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Turner, J. (2013). Existence and many-one identity. Philosophical Quarterly, 63(251), 313329.10.1111/1467-9213.12001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahavi, D. (2016). The end of what? Phenomenology vs. speculative realism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 24(3), 289309.10.1080/09672559.2016.1175101CrossRefGoogle Scholar