Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cb9f654ff-5kfdg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-08-11T10:24:47.920Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part IV - Legal Protection for the Press Function

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 July 2025

RonNell Andersen Jones
Affiliation:
University of Utah
Sonja R. West
Affiliation:
University of Georgia

Information

Type
Chapter
Information
The Future of Press Freedom
Democracy, Law, and the News in Changing Times
, pp. 159 - 268
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NC
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

Part IV Legal Protection for the Press Function

11 Reinvigorating the Press Clause Through Negative Theory

Courts have been reluctant to interpret the First Amendment’s Press Clause as providing the press with significant protections distinct from those provided to all of us by the Speech Clause. But courts could choose to do so, and litigants and scholars can help illuminate those choices. What work could an independent Press Clause do apart from the work already done by the Speech Clause? This question requires us to think about why and how the press is different from other speakers for First Amendment purposes – more specifically, what distinct functions does the press perform and what distinct vulnerabilities does the press possess?

In terms of distinct press functions, the press serves the public through its watchdog, educator, and proxy roles. The press performs a critically important checking function by reporting on the government’s performance, including its misconduct.Footnote 1 The press informs the public about current affairs, science, health, the environment, art, entertainment, and much more. The press also serves as a proxy for the public by observing and reporting on events of importance to the public where the public does not have the time or other resources to observe those events directly.Footnote 2

These functions, in turn, explain the press’s distinct vulnerabilities to government retaliation: Because the press’s primary purpose is to scrutinize the government for the public’s benefit, the government has long perceived the press as inherently threatening to its political self-interest. Moreover, changes in the political environment (along with “the affordances of online social media platforms – anonymity, accessibility speed, and scale”Footnote 3) have aggravated threats to journalists’ physical safety, intensifying their vulnerability still further. As legal scholar Erin Carroll has detailed, “physical assaults against journalists in the United States increased nearly 1,400% in 2020” and “a 2018 study found that one in ten journalists surveyed had been threatened with death in the past year because of the work they do.”Footnote 4 So too have contemporary changes in technology exacerbated these vulnerabilities by posing existential challenges to the press’s financial survival.Footnote 5

“Negative” First Amendment theory, as I’ve written previously, “is about a negative value: distrust of government. And because the government gives us plenty of reason to distrust it, negative theory packs substantial power.”Footnote 6 Rooted in distrust of the government’s self-interested efforts to punish and thus silence the press, negative theory has long offered an important tool for understanding the Press Clause. And negative theory is now more valuable as an interpretive tool than ever, as press organizations and individual journalists are increasingly vulnerable to the government’s retaliation.

Among other things, negative theory can help us understand the Press Clause as providing an especially robust shield from the government’s retaliation – a shield different from that offered the public more generally by the Speech Clause precisely because of the press’s distinct functions and vulnerabilities. More specifically, directing judicial attention to the reasons to distrust the government’s adverse treatment of the press can reinvigorate Press Clause doctrine by informing courts’ choices of legal rules and their application of those rules once chosen.

A Press Clause doctrine informed by negative theory thus asks whether the government’s action gives us reason to worry that its choices have the intent and potential effect of muzzling the press as a watchdog.Footnote 7 “Affirmative” theories, in contrast, focus less on the government’s potential for regulatory abuse and more on the positive benefits of the press: Such theories urge that we interpret the Press Clause to provide the press with affirmative rights to newsgathering, like a right to receive information or access places not available to the public more generally.Footnote 8 Note, however, that applying negative theory to understand the Press Clause as providing a mighty shield against the government’s retaliation does not preclude us from also understanding the clause to afford the press with such affirmative rights.

Indeed, courts and commentators often rely on multiple theories when considering specific First Amendment problems.Footnote 9 For instance, the Speech Clause’s protection of political dissent from the government’s regulation can be explained in both negative terms (to guard against the government’s self-interested efforts to silence its critics) and affirmative terms (because political dissent valuably contributes to democratic self-governance, enlightenment, and autonomy).Footnote 10 In other words, “negative” and “affirmative” Press Clause theories are not mutually exclusive, and the different theories can cash out with different doctrinal yields.

11.1 The Government’s Retaliation Against the Press, Past and Present

We distrust the government’s regulation in settings where experience leads us to conclude that the government’s motives are self-interested or that its bias or competence is otherwise suspect. The framers of the Press Clause drew from exactly such experience, as they were all too aware of the government’s history of interfering with press freedom through press licensing and seditious libel.Footnote 11 As Floyd Abrams has explained, “the Press Clause was, at the very least, a deeply felt response to the deprivations of press liberty that the colonists had witnessed and to which they had been subjected.”Footnote 12

One need not be an originalist, however, to interpret the Press Clause through the lens of negative theory. A structural understanding of the press’s key functions explains the government’s incentives for punishing and silencing the press: As Justice Potter Stewart explained, by providing the public with “organized, expert scrutiny of the government,” a “free press” provides a “formidable check on official power.”Footnote 13

Examples abound – both old and new – of the government’s propensity to stifle the press’s scrutiny. Recall, for instance, the calculated efforts by Alabama government officials in the 1960s to drive journalists covering the Civil Rights Movement out of the state;Footnote 14 their tactics included weaponized defamation claims like those made in The New York Times Co. v. Sullivan.Footnote 15

Consider, too, governments’ punishment of local papers’ critical scrutiny by pulling advertising from those papers or terminating contracts with them for printing legally required notices of tax sales, public meetings, and more. To be sure, governments have long engaged in such retaliation,Footnote 16 but newspapers’ contemporary financial instability leaves them especially vulnerable to such actions, which threaten a considerable chunk of their revenue.Footnote 17

As yet another illustration, think of the government’s not-so-unusual practice of punishing journalists or press outlets critical of its performance by banning them from attending press conferences or communicating with government officials. Recall, for instance, former President Donald Trump’s practice of revoking, or threatening to revoke, the White House press credentials of journalists whose questions or reporting criticized his administration’s performance.Footnote 18

So, we can find examples aplenty of the government’s retaliatory tendencies with respect to the press. What to do about it?

11.2 How Negative Theory Could Reinvigorate Press Clause Doctrine

The contemporary Supreme Court leans heavily on negative theory when developing and applying its Speech Clause doctrine. Consider, for instance, United States v. Alvarez,Footnote 19 where the Court struck down a federal law that criminalized intentional falsehoods about receiving military honors, a law that neither punished nor chilled any valuable speech.Footnote 20 There, the Court relied on negative theory, focusing entirely on its distrust of the government’s potential for regulatory mischief: “Permitting the government to decree this speech to be a criminal offense, whether shouted from the rooftops or made in a barely audible whisper, would endorse government authority to compile a list of subjects about which false statements are punishable. That governmental power has no clear limiting principle.”Footnote 21

Other examples of the Court’s reliance on negative theory for Speech Clause purposes include Heffernan v. City of Paterson.Footnote 22 There, the Court upheld a First Amendment challenge to government officials’ demotion of an employee whom they mistakenly believed to have supported an opposition candidate. That the employee did not actually support – and thus had not engaged in protected political speech supporting – the candidate did not matter to the Court’s analysis. Instead, the government’s effort to suppress speech it perceived as threatening its political self-interest, by itself, violated the Speech Clause.

Yet the Court only occasionally invokes negative theory in its Press Clause cases. The rare exception – now four decades old – illustrates the rule: In Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co. v. Minnesota Commissioner of Revenue, the Court invoked a hefty dose of negative theory to strike down a state’s taxing scheme that applied only to the press (a tax on paper and ink used in the production of periodicals like newspapers) and only to certain members of the press (those that annually spent more than $100,000 on ink and paper).Footnote 23 The Court’s opinion reflected its deep distrust of the government’s motives and its censorial potential. Consider this, for example:

When the State singles out the press, though, the political constraints that prevent a legislature from passing crippling taxes of general applicability are weakened, and the threat of burdensome taxes becomes acute. That threat can operate as effectively as a censor to check critical comment by the press, undercutting the basic assumption of our political system that the press will often serve as an important restraint on government.Footnote 24

And this (where the majority explained the danger of enabling the state to single out the press for a different method of taxation even if the press’s tax burden were lighter than other businesses’):

The very selection of the press for special treatment threatens the press not only with the current differential treatment, but with the possibility of subsequent differentially more burdensome treatment. Thus, even without actually imposing an extra burden on the press, the government might be able to achieve censorial effects, for “the threat of sanctions may deter [the] exercise of [First Amendment] rights almost as potently as the actual application of sanctions.”Footnote 25

Recognizing the law’s “potential for abuse,”Footnote 26 the Court applied a version of strict scrutiny to strike it down.Footnote 27

That negative theory is now so often absent from courts’ Press Clause jurisprudence explains much of their failure to understand the Press Clause as doing work independent of the Speech Clause. Consider now two ways in which the robust infusion of negative theory could reinvigorate Press Clause doctrine.

11.3 Informing Courts’ Choices of Press-Specific Rules

First, reliance on negative theory – that is, concern for the government’s capacity for, and the press’s vulnerability to, retaliation – could in certain settings generate very different Press Clause rules. Think, for instance, how the Court’s decision in Branzburg v. HayesFootnote 28 might have turned out differently had it been informed by negative theory.

The Branzburg majority rejected the press’s argument that the Press Clause should be interpreted to provide journalists with a shield from law enforcement subpoenas requiring them to disclose their confidential sources. The Court instead concluded that the Press Clause confers the press with no distinct rights of its own, such that members of the press must comply with subpoenas along with everyone else. In so holding, the majority downplayed negative theory concerns, discounting reasons for distrusting the government’s exercise of its subpoena power specifically with respect to journalists:

It is said that currently press subpoenas have multiplied, that mutual distrust and tension between press and officialdom have increased, that reporting styles have changed, and that there is now more need for confidential sources, particularly where the press seeks news about minority cultural and political groups or dissident organizations suspicious of the law and public officials. These developments, even if true, are treacherous grounds for a far-reaching interpretation of the First Amendment fastening a nationwide rule on courts, grand juries, and prosecuting officials everywhere.Footnote 29

The dissent, in contrast, credited reasons to fear the government’s potential to abuse its power to retaliate against the press – particularly in the grand jury setting, where “the judiciary has traditionally imposed virtually no limitations on the grand jury’s broad investigatory powers.”Footnote 30 The dissent’s distrust of the government in this context thus led it to advocate a rule considerably less deferential to the government than the majority’s rule. Under the dissent’s preferred approach, the government would have been required to show probable cause to believe that a journalist has information “clearly relevant to a specific probable violation of law,” “that the information sought cannot be obtained by alternative means less destructive of First Amendment rights,” and that the government has a compelling need for the information.Footnote 31

As we can see, judicial awareness of the government’s incentives and capacity to retaliate against the press can support courts’ choice to apply Press Clause rules considerably more suspicious of the government.

11.4 Informing Courts’ Application of Existing Rules in Press Clause Cases

Second, negative theory can valuably inform courts’ application of rules already chosen. Under doctrine developed primarily for Speech Clause claims, an individual proves the government’s retaliation in violation of the First Amendment if they can show that (1) they engaged in speech or other activity protected by the First Amendment, (2) the government took action that would chill a person of “ordinary firmness” from continuing to engage in such speech or protected activity, and (3) the government’s action was substantially motivated by their speech or other protected activity.Footnote 32 Courts routinely apply this rule to retaliation claims brought by the press, just like any other speaker. Among the biggest barriers to the press’s success under this framework is its difficulty in convincing courts that the government’s action had the requisite potential to chill a person of “ordinary firmness.” Attending to the government’s self-interest in silencing critical coverage along with the press’s vulnerabilities to such retaliation, however, can lead to different results.

Consider, for instance, the difference that negative theory could have made in Baltimore Sun v. Ehrlich.Footnote 33 There, the Fourth Circuit rejected a newspaper’s challenge to Maryland Governor Robert Ehrlich’s decision to bar state employees from speaking with two Baltimore Sun reporters because he was unhappy with those journalists’ coverage of his administration.

The Sun’s challenge emphasized negative theory concerns, taking pains to explain the burden of such actions on “small news organizations [that u]nlike The Sun … do not have sufficient resources to attempt to withstand such a blatant attempt to influence their coverage.”Footnote 34 Along the same lines, the amicus brief filed by The Washington Post described in detail how the governor’s actions interfered with the press’s checking functions in ways that ultimately harmed the public: “All [who report on the Maryland state government] have effectively been warned that if they are critical of the Governor or his administration, they too can be denied access to information that they need to do their job.”Footnote 35 This brief also underscored the vulnerability of smaller news organizations to actions like the governor’s, observing that “the problem is particularly acute for those newspapers covering state government with small staffs [who] can ill afford to have the Governor blackball anyone they assign to the State House.”Footnote 36

Yet the Fourth Circuit rejected The Sun’s claim, concluding that the governor’s action would not have had a chilling effect on journalists of ordinary firmness. The panel held that “a reporter endures only de minimis inconvenience when a government official denies the reporter access to discretionary information or refuses to answer the reporter’s questions because the official disagrees with the substance or manner of the reporter’s previous expression in reporting.”Footnote 37

But an opinion attentive to negative theory concerns – in other words, an opinion attentive to the reasons to distrust the government’s adverse treatment of the press or specific members of the press – would have supported a different result. More specifically, an opinion informed by negative theory would have recognized the threat posed to the press’s checking function in general (and to the work of smaller news outlets in particular) when punitively denied access to the information that makes quality reporting possible. Today, nearly twenty years later, the precarious financial state of most media organizations means that nearly all press outlets – not just smaller outlets – are acutely vulnerable to such restrictions. In other words, a decision informed by negative theory could apply the traditional three-part anti-retaliation rule to conclude that the governor’s action did indeed chill journalists of “ordinary firmness.”

Note too that negative theory could also support a court’s choice of an entirely different, more government-suspicious rule for evaluating such claims, as discussed above.Footnote 38 In other words, courts could choose to apply strict scrutiny – thus requiring the government to bear a heavy burden in justifying its action – when the government singles out specific press speakers for disadvantageous treatment due to the critical content of their coverage.Footnote 39 Indeed, this is the approach the contemporary Court purports to take for Speech Clause purposes whenever the government singles out specific messages for disadvantageous treatment.Footnote 40

Relatedly, negative theory can inform courts’ capacious understanding of the ways in which the government can retaliate against the press. For instance, negative theory can help us understand how, under some circumstances, the government’s retaliatory lies, threats, or other speech can violate the Press Clause when they have the intent and effect of chilling journalists’ and press outlets’ critical coverage. Although the government’s speech is generally exempt from First Amendment review, the government’s speech can violate the Constitution when it interferes with its targets’ constitutionally protected choices or opportunities in ways that would violate a constitutional right if the government’s interference took the form of traditional lawmaking or regulation.Footnote 41

More specifically, the government’s speech can retaliate against press targets in violation of the First Amendment by changing the behavior of either of two sets of audiences: The government’s speech may cause third parties to retaliate against the government’s targets because of their protected activity, and the government’s speech may directly silence their targets.Footnote 42 Examples of the former, for Speech Clause purposes, include the Mississippi State Sovereignty Commission’s lies in the 1950s and 1960s to the employers, friends, families, and neighbors of civil rights activists – falsely asserting those activists’ sexual misconduct, financial improprieties, or illegal drug use – to silence their speech advocating desegregation.Footnote 43 Examples of the latter include the government’s threats of criminal or economic punishment directly against its targets.Footnote 44

A Press Clause doctrine informed by negative theory would look for evidence of the government’s retaliatory motives and chilling effects in its speech involving the press. For this reason, under some circumstances, the government’s expressive attacks rise to the level of retaliation prohibited by the Press Clause not only if they directly threaten their targets but also if they have the intent and effect of causing third parties to retaliate – physically or economically – against the press.Footnote 45

***

In short, a Press Clause doctrine illuminated by negative theory would reflect awareness of the government’s incentives to retaliate against the press to disrupt the press’s scrutiny of the government. And a Press Clause doctrine illuminated by negative theory would recognize the press’s vulnerability to the government’s retaliatory efforts to undermine its checking function. In this way, attention to negative theory can reinvigorate Press Clause doctrine by informing courts’ choices of legal rules and by informing their application of rules once chosen.

12 The Constitutional Exceptionalism of Religion and the Press

Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances.Footnote 1

The text of the First Amendment explicitly protects two foundational social institutions: religion and the press.Footnote 2 Since 2021, however, the Supreme Court has increasingly granted one of these two institutions – religion – a status of heightened constitutional privilege. In a series of cases, the justices have extended what commentators have dubbed “most favored nation” status to religious organizations and activities.Footnote 3 As a practical matter, this means that in any given circumstance, the government may not treat religious groups and activities less favorably than it treats the best-treated secular group or activity. For example, if a COVID-era regulation prohibited indoor gatherings of more than ten people but exempted grocery stores, under this line of reasoning the government must give the same exemption to houses of worship. The Court has, moreover, required this privileged treatment of religion regardless of whether the government’s justification for the exemption applies or is relevant to the religious actor or activity.

This approach has been a sea change in religion law. Under late twentieth- and early twenty-first-century precedents, religion was deliberately treated as unexceptional, largely due to countervailing Establishment Clause concerns.Footnote 4 These cases dictated that the government was not only prohibited from favoring one religion over another but also could not favor religion over secular institutions or interest. Indeed, to avoid the entanglement of government and religion, the Court often permitted the government to treat religion less favorably – say, by providing government funding to pursue secular but not religious education.Footnote 5 That presumption has now flipped. Today, religion enjoys exceptional status.

In contrast, current law treats the other First Amendment institution – the press – as wholly unexceptional. However the press is defined – from newspapers to television to bloggers in pajamas to professional journalistsFootnote 6 – it receives no greater constitutional protections than any other speaker. The Court has essentially read the Press Clause out of the Constitution, voiding its specific textual commitment, despite the absence of any countervailing constitutional provision parallel to the Establishment Clause. Until religion law’s recent exceptional turn, the law’s treatment of religion and the press were in some sense parallel. Recently, they have diverged, as press law has not kept pace with changes in religion law.

In this chapter, I argue that the press should be treated at least as constitutionally exceptional as religion, and I explore what such press exceptionalism might mean in practice.

In addition to both being named in the constitutional text, the press and religion share important sociological similarities. Both promote core components of the freedom of belief through institutional organization – religion protects self-determination of faith, while the press safeguards democratic self-determination. History also supports interpreting protections for religion and the press in parallel, as do the text of the First Amendment and Bill of Rights when read as a whole. Like much of the Bill of Rights, the First Amendment aims to protect forms of organized action, belief, and dissent – in religion, in the press, and in assembly – that could counter the power of the newly established federal government. In light of the Court’s recent changes to religion law, courts and scholars should embrace a reading of the First Amendment that treats the press as the constitutionally exceptional institution that it is.Footnote 7

To identify how press exceptionalism should be organized, it is important to bear in mind that while the First Amendment’s protections for religion and the press are structurally and functionally similar, they protect related but distinct values and institutions. The religion clauses ensure the institutional prerequisites of freedom of faith; the Press Clause protects the institutional prerequisites of democracy. For this reason, courts should shape press laws’ exceptionalism around the role of the press as a democratic institution, focusing on how it uniquely supports and focuses informed public discourse, government accountability, and the robust exchange of ideas essential to self-governance.

12.1 The Gap Between the Exceptional Treatment of Religion and the Press
12.1.1 The Advent of Religious Exceptionalism

In the 1990 case of Employment Division v. Smith, the Supreme Court held that the Constitution does not require exemptions to generally applicable laws for religious actors. The Court explained that because of the wide diversity of religious beliefs in the country, “we cannot afford the luxury of deeming presumptively invalid, as applied to the religious objector, every regulation of conduct that does not protect an interest of the highest order.”Footnote 8 Under Smith, courts should apply only rational basis review (which is highly deferential to the government) to generally applicable laws that incidentally burden religion. Shortly thereafter, the Court clarified that Smith applies only to neutral, generally applicable laws, not laws that “discriminate[] against some or all religious beliefs or regulate[] or prohibit[] conduct because it is undertaken for religious reasons.”Footnote 9

Both religious conservatives and liberals concerned about the disparate impact on minority religions have long criticized the Court’s decision in Smith.Footnote 10 The recent turnover of the Court’s membership, which established a solid 6-3 conservative supermajority that includes several members holding deep religious commitments, led many to speculate that Smith’s days were numbered.Footnote 11 Although the Court has not (yet) overruled Smith, in a series of cases it has adopted increasingly low thresholds for triggering religious exemptions. Collectively, these latest decisions have so dramatically expanded protections for religious actors that they have, in practical terms, nearly flipped Smith’s holding without formally overturning the precedent.

In the 2021 case Tandon v. Newsom, which Jim Oleske calls “the most important free exercise decision since [Smith],”Footnote 12 a majority of the Court formally adopted, for the first time, the most-favored-nation theory of religious exemptions.Footnote 13 Decided on the “shadow docket”Footnote 14 by summary order without briefing or argument, Tandon blocked California’s COVID-related restrictions on in-home gatherings. The Court held that because the state permitted some secular businesses, such as grocery stores, to bring together more than three families, a three-family limit on in-home gatherings for any purpose, including religious ones, violated the Free Exercise Clause. The Court stated that “government regulations are not neutral and generally applicable, and therefore trigger strict scrutiny under the Free Exercise Clause, whenever they treat any comparable secular activity more favorably than religious exercise.”Footnote 15

Several months later, the Court extended and elaborated on Tandon’s most-favored-nation approach in Fulton v. City of Philadelphia.Footnote 16 Fulton involved a challenge brought by Catholic Social Services to Philadelphia’s requirement that those who contract with the city to provide foster care placement services commit not to discriminate against certain classes, including LGBTQ+ couples. While explicitly declining to overturn Smith,Footnote 17 the Court held that because Philadelphia’s foster care contracts included a “system of individual exemptions” available “at the sole discretion of the Commissioner,” the city’s antidiscrimination rule was not generally applicable. For that reason, strict scrutiny, rather than Smith’s rational basis review, applied, and in the Court’s view, Philadelphia had not sufficiently justified its refusal to grant Catholic Social Services an accommodation allowing it to refuse to serve LGBTQ+ couples.Footnote 18

Many commentators have argued that the Court’s adoption of the most-favored-nation theory of religious exemptions marks a radical change in religion law – and one with far-reaching consequences.Footnote 19 Douglas Laycock, the originator of the theory, has observed that “if a law with even a few secular exceptions isn’t neutral and generally applicable, then not many laws are.”Footnote 20 And Cary Coglianese and Daniel Walters have argued that Fulton “opened the barn door for anyone with religious objections to escape from their duty to obey vast swaths of the law,” because “provisions explicitly authorizing exceptions to otherwise seemingly general rules” are “rife throughout the law.”Footnote 21 Without overruling Smith, Fulton and Tandon dramatically limited the contexts in which it applies.

The Roberts Court has expanded religious exceptionalism in other ways as well. It recently made it easier for employees to obtain religious accommodations at work under Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964.Footnote 22 It broadened the contexts in which religious employers no longer need to follow workplace antidiscrimination laws.Footnote 23 It interpreted the Free Exercise Clause as requiring states to fund sectarian schools and programs if they fund nonsectarian ones.Footnote 24 And it protected a public school football coach from discipline for praying at midfield after games.Footnote 25

Taken together, these shifts represent a revolution in religion law. In the eyes of the current Supreme Court, Derek Black has argued, religious rights are assuming “something of a superstatus”Footnote 26 in which the Court “seems to treat religious activity as preferred over all other activities, including the exercise of other fundamental rights.” The Court has placed “free exercise rights at the top of a hierarchy of protected rights; free exercise can never be treated worse, but can be treated better, than other fundamentally protected activities.”Footnote 27 Religion, in other words, has become constitutionally exceptional.

12.1.2 The Currently Unexceptional Press

By contrast, under current law, the press is constitutionally unexceptional. In Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission, the Court asserted that it has “consistently rejected the proposition that the institutional press has any constitutional privilege beyond that of other speakers,”Footnote 28 that “there is no precedent supporting laws that attempt to distinguish between corporations which are deemed to be exempt as media corporations and those which are not,” and that such a distinction would raise constitutional concern as speaker-based discrimination.Footnote 29 As Sonja West describes,

Under th[is] nondiscrimination view, the Press Clause does not function as an active protector of the press, allowing (and perhaps demanding) government efforts that enable the news media to do their job. Rather, proponents of this view see the Press Clause as an obstacle to government regulations that grant special privileges to select speakers including the news media. The right it secures, they argue, is simply the right of all speakers to be treated equally in their ability to publish speech.Footnote 30

Eugene Volokh is a proponent of this nondiscrimination view. He construes the Constitution’s mention of “the press” as “protect[ing] everyone’s use of the printing press (and its modern equivalents) as a technology,” rather than as a specialized industry or a social institution.Footnote 31

12.2 The Press as a Social Institution Analogous to Religion

The press should be understood as analogous not to other speakers but to religion. Just as religion is not just any type of belief system through which we can acquire values, morals, or ideas of right and wrong, the press is not just any speaker.Footnote 32 Both the press and religion fill fundamental societal roles as institutions that organize people into communities of common interests, beliefs, and purposes. These institutions not only structure and communicate ideas and values but also guide the attention and action of their followers. The press and religion are institutions that allow individuals to unite into groups with similar purposes, where they can accomplish common goals, meet challenges, and create meaning and community. Critically, both institutions provide essential platforms through which people can organize to oppose ideas, laws, or values with which they disagree.

It is important to recall that when the Bill of Rights was adopted, its rights applied only against the federal government, not the states.Footnote 33 As a result, the Bill of Rights juxtaposed the people and the states with the federal government, a contrast most explicitly seen in the Ninth and Tenth Amendments. The Bill of Rights protected the self-determination and resistance of the people as organized into self-determining bodies, including states and religious orders. This served a dual purpose: It protected the autonomy of subnational communities while also providing bulwarks against excessive federal power. The First Amendment protected both subnationally established religions and subnational republican governance.

As a whole, the First Amendment can be understood as privileging the protection of various forms of organized self-determination and dissent: in religion, in the press, and in assembly.Footnote 34 At the time of the founding, prior to the emergence of major political parties, the press and religion stood out as two of the most vital social institutions through which the people could stand up to more powerful actors. (Notably, the Second Amendment’s protection of organized militias served a similar purpose.Footnote 35) Seen through this lens, the First Amendment’s parallel textual protection for “religion” and “the press” is a reflection of their similar social roles in fostering self-organization, self-determination, and self-protection.Footnote 36

If religion is to be treated exceptionally, the press should be as well. In fact, there is justification for treating the press more exceptionally than religion. According to the constitutional text, the right to freely exercise one’s religion must be balanced against the countervailing concerns of the Establishment Clause, which safeguards against governmental support for, favoritism of, or entanglement with religion. Yet the First Amendment’s guarantee of a free press does not include a similar competing interest. At the very least, the exceptionalism of the press should be elevated to that of current religion law.

While the societal roles of religion and the press are similar, their specific purposes are not.Footnote 37 The Constitution protects the press as a democratic institution. Democracies depend on forms of discourse and shared reality. They require elements of a shared world – shared facts, shared concern, and shared focus – which form the basis and the possibility of collective action through governance.Footnote 38 It is for this reason that the First Amendment is “the guardian of our democracy.”Footnote 39 The history of the origins of the Press Clause excavated by David Anderson supports this view.Footnote 40 As he points out, on the eve of the Revolutionary War, the Continental Congress explained the need for “the freedom of the press”:

The importance of this consists, besides the advancement of truth, science, morality, and arts in general, in its diffusion of liberal sentiments on the administration of Government, in its ready communication of thoughts between subjects, and its consequential promotion of union among them, whereby oppressive officers are shamed or intimidated, into more honourable and just modes of conducting affairs.Footnote 41

Anderson elaborates that while the continental charters did not protect press freedoms, by the founding, most state constitutions did – explicitly as protectors of self-government:

The first press clauses were written in response to a resolution of the Second Continental Congress, calling upon the states to repudiate the authority of the crown and establish their own governments. These press clauses were produced not merely as salutary additions to an existing order, but as part of the urgent process of establishing “such government as shall, in the opinion of the representatives of the people, best conduce to the happiness and safety of their constituents in particular, and America in general.”Footnote 42

The advent of press clauses during the Revolution and their adoption both in the federal and most early state constitutions demonstrates the perceived importance of the press to self-government.

While religion and the press were adopted as parallel institutional bulwarks both of freedom and self-determination and against tyranny, the press serves a distinctly democratic purpose. For this reason, though the press and religion should be treated as institutional analogs for constitutional purposes, the doctrine should treat the press as exceptional in ways that reflect its organizing purpose to facilitate self-governance.

12.3 The Press as an Exceptional Democratic Institution

What would be the practical result if the press was treated as exceptional in ways oriented around its constitutional purpose? What would “most-favored-nation status” mean for the press – that is, for the press to receive equivalently favorable treatment as religion does under current law?

At a conceptual level, most-favored-nation status for the press could mean a number of things.Footnote 43 It could mean (1) that if a law makes an exception for another speaker, the press must also receive that exception. That is, if any speaker receives a privilege, the press must as well. Or it could mean (2) that the press can, and sometimes must, receive rights or privileges that others do not. Courts and scholars should embrace both principles to harmonize press and religion law.

Practically, most-favored-nation status for the press could, for example, require that representatives of the press, however defined,Footnote 44 have privileged access to governmental information – at least, as in the religion context, where access to that information is provided to any non-press private actor. This could include access to governmental institutions, such as jails, prisons, and other governmental buildings, as well as government documents, such as Office of Legal Counsel memos or records of closed-door legislative deliberations. The Press Clause could function as a sort of constitutionally grounded sunshine law, allowing the press to access, disseminate, and provide a basis for public action on governmental actions.Footnote 45 A First Amendment doctrine that embraced the exceptional role of the press might likewise protect a reporter’s privilege not to disclose confidential sources or exempt the press from surveillance or searches in some contexts – at least as long as any non-press actor also had the same privilege, as, for example, an attorney might in the context of attorney-client privilege.

Most-favored-nation treatment for the press would also require the rejection of the current nondiscrimination theory of the press, which, as Sonja West has analyzed, prompted the Court in Citizens United to categorically extend First Amendment campaign expenditure rights to all corporations. Importantly, this could affect other areas of First Amendment law that currently depend on the equivalence of the press with all other speakers. Doctrine that recognized the exceptional status of the press could mean, for example, that campaign finance laws could limit non-press political expenditures more than press expenditures.

But press exceptionalism need not be constituted solely by negative rights against governmental action; it could require positive support for the press. Most importantly, it could mean constitutionally required funding for local news and public media. If a core purpose of the Press Clause is to disseminate shared facts and foster shared focus and concern – or, as the Continental Congress opined, “the advancement of truth, science, morality, and arts in general,” the “diffusion of liberal sentiments on the administration of Government,” “communication of thoughts” between citizens, and the “promotion of union among them, whereby” public officials can be embarrassed into “more honourable and just modes of conducting affairs”Footnote 46 – public funding of local journalism and public media could vitally advance that goal, particularly given the economic headwinds now facing the press.

First Amendment doctrine that embraced a most-favored-nation theory of the press might permit, or even require, market-structuring laws – such as antitrust, bankruptcy, or property rules – that facilitate and advance a flourishing press able to accomplish its constitutional purposes.Footnote 47 For example, press law might permit laws that require social media to pay news outlets. Or it might allow or require copyright rules that promote journalism, for example, by requiring artificial intelligence (AI) companies that rely on large language models trained on press creations to contribute to the support of local or public media as much or more than they are required to compensate non-press authors of training data.

***

The First Amendment’s Press Clause provides explicit constitutional protection for the press as a fundamental democracy-enabling institution, just as the religion clauses distinctively protect religion as a central institutional protector of self-determination in the realm of faith and conscience. Given the current Court’s recent embrace of religious exceptionalism – providing religious actors most-favored-nation status – there should be a parallel recognition of press exceptionalism. The text and history of the First Amendment, along with the structural role of the press in our constitutional system, support recognizing a special status for the press that is tailored to its democratic purpose. This press exceptionalism should permit, and may require, government action to promote a free and vibrant press that can foster the forms of discourse, shared knowledge, shared concern, and shared focus necessary for democratic self-governance.

13 The Other Press Clauses

The Constitution’s free expression clauses are famously bare-bones: “Congress shall make no law … abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press.”Footnote 1 The historical drafting record is likewise thin – the constitutional framers spent little time debating press protections at the Constitutional Convention.Footnote 2 Yet post-ratification, the paths of these two provisions have diverged. The Supreme Court has devoted substantial attention to the Speech Clause, interpreting it broadly to cover an array of activities. In contrast, it has largely ignored the Press Clause, reading it mostly as ancillary to the ever-expanding set of speech protections.Footnote 3 The Press Clause has little independent meaning today.Footnote 4

Yet imagine a different text, with a different drafting history. What if the Constitution provided that “the liberty of the press shall forever remain inviolate,”Footnote 5 or that freedom of the press is “one of the invaluable rights of man?”Footnote 6 What if the Press Clause were a stand-alone provision, or the discussion of the meaning and scope of speech and press provisions had figured largely into the constitutional drafting debates?Footnote 7 Would protections for the press look different today?

Such language and history do exist – in state constitutions. All fifty states have adopted constitutions that explicitly shield freedom of speech and the press.Footnote 8 And nearly all of them contain language that is substantially different from the language of the First Amendment.Footnote 9 These state constitutions contain fifty separate speech and press provisions, each with different drafting processes and different histories of judicial interpretation.Footnote 10 Moreover, state constitutions contain myriad additional constitutional provisions – many without federal analogs – that both privilege and protect the press.Footnote 11

Since the 1970s, members of the press have advocated for increased constitutional protections under the First Amendment.Footnote 12 Some of these efforts have been successful. Yet these rights have generally been extended to the public as a whole.Footnote 13 The Supreme Court has mostly rejected calls to read the First Amendment to extend exclusive constitutional protections for the press.Footnote 14 This has left the press without particularized constitutional shields for many newsgathering activities, like accessing prisons or shielding confidential sources.Footnote 15

There are reasons to revisit these precedents today. The economic and political power of the institutional media has diminished in recent years, with local press institutions disappearing at alarming rates.Footnote 16 At the same time, attacks on journalists have increased.Footnote 17 In response to these growing pressures on the institutional media, scholars have turned their attention back to the First Amendment, asking, for example, whether the Press Clause could be “revitalized” or “awakened” to offer a more abundant set of rights and privileges for the press.Footnote 18

Earlier press law scholarship of this type focused on the meaning and scope of the Press Clause, including whether its drafters intended only to protect against prior restraints.Footnote 19 Professor David Anderson’s landmark article from 1983 argued that the drafters intended the First Amendment to sweep more broadly. He contended that they envisioned constitutional press protections to operate as a structural check against governmental abuse.Footnote 20 More recent Press Clause scholarship has built upon this work, taking up related questions, such as how to define “the press” for constitutional purposesFootnote 21 and how the Supreme Court’s perceptions of the press have changed over time.Footnote 22

This work is rich and thoughtful, yet it focuses almost exclusively on the federal Constitution.Footnote 23 This chapter, in contrast, turns attention to the “other” press clauses, along with state constitutional speech protections and various other state constitutional provisions implicating the press. It asks how these various state-level protections might be utilized to protect the institutional press in new or better ways.Footnote 24 And it asks how the lessons of these state experiences might be applied back to the federal context.Footnote 25 In this way, the chapter plugs into two separate strands of scholarship.

The first is the small but expanding literature exploring the scope and meaning of the federal Press Clause.Footnote 26 The second is a larger body of work examining how state constitutional liberties offer expanded rights protection beyond what the federal Constitution guarantees.Footnote 27 This movement to expand state constitutional rights is often described as “new judicial federalism.” Supreme Court Justice William Brennan is widely credited as its founder, at least in the movement’s modern form.Footnote 28 In his landmark 1977 Harvard Law Review article, State Constitutions and the Protection of Individual Rights, Brennan warned that the steady expansion of federal individual liberties’ protections during the Warren Court had come to an end.Footnote 29 In the face of this federal rights retrenchment, he argued, state courts must take up the mantle of the progressive cause and construe state constitutional rights provisions to fill in these federal constitutional gaps. He urged state supreme courts to break with federal judges, even when interpreting analogous state constitutional provisions.Footnote 30

Many did so. If the promise of state constitutional rights protection was overlooked at the time of Brennan’s call to action, that is no longer true today. State courts have spent decades untangling the relationship between state and federal constitutional rights provisions.Footnote 31 They have developed a rich body of case law cataloging when and how state courts have interpreted state constitutional individual liberties provisions more expansively than their federal counterparts, as well as when they should.Footnote 32 Scholars have also developed typologies of different methodological approaches to state constitutional rights interpretation.Footnote 33 A wide variety of methods have been adopted, from “lockstep” interpretations adopting federal court constructions wholesale to “primacy” approaches that emphasize independent state construction and give little weight to federal interpretations of equivalent provisions.Footnote 34

This chapter mostly sidesteps these methodological debates.Footnote 35 It focuses instead on the specific context of state constitutional press protections.Footnote 36 Much of the “new judicial federalism” scholarship is subject specific. The courts’ early jurisprudence in this area largely focused on the scope of criminal law protections, for example.Footnote 37 The Warren Court steadily expanded constitutional protections for criminal defendants, and in the face of the U.S. Supreme Court’s retreat from this project, state supreme court judges asked whether state constitutions might fill the gap.Footnote 38 The legal scholarship followed suit.Footnote 39

Since then, different substantive state constitutional provisions have captured judicial and scholarly attention at different moments. Today, for example, many advocates and scholars have turned to state constitutional privacy provisions as a potential source of reproductive rights protection in the wake of the Supreme Court’s elimination of federal abortion protections in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization.Footnote 40 And in the face of the growing climate crisis, advocates have looked to state constitutional provisions addressing public health rights or the right to a healthy environment as a promising source of new legal protection.Footnote 41 As the Supreme Court moves further to the right,Footnote 42 progressive scholars and advocates will most likely continue to look to state constitutions as an alternative source of rights protection.Footnote 43

In the decades since Brennan’s article, scholars and judges have also looked to state constitutional speech and press provisions.Footnote 44 They have asked whether these protections sweep more broadly than the First Amendment Speech and Press Clauses, as well as whether they should.Footnote 45 State courts have also explored the meaning of state free expression protections when construing state constitutional speech and press provisions.Footnote 46 But more could be done. Press advocates haven’t always utilized these press and other state constitutional provisions effectively.Footnote 47 And state courts have often construed state constitutional free expression provisions in lockstep with the First Amendment, despite significant textual and historical distinctions.Footnote 48

Further, legal scholars have largely overlooked state constitutional protections for the press. Some have compared the development of free expression rights in the state versus federal constitutional contexts for specific states.Footnote 49 Yet the scholarship examining state constitutional protections for the press is more limited.Footnote 50 This is true even though these state constitutional press protections offer crucial benefits. State constitutions can provide protection where the U.S. Constitution has failed. Many state constitutional press and speech provisions already sweep more broadly than the First Amendment under current state precedent. And many more could be reasonably construed this way.Footnote 51 Moreover, state constitutions are more easily amended in response to new or changing threats to the press.Footnote 52

The lessons of state constitutional law can also be useful for advocates of expanded federal press protections. Many of the policy arguments advanced by the U.S. Supreme Court in the course of rejecting particularized rights for the press can be challenged by the experience of the states. The state constitutional experience offers alternative law and policy choices, distinct from the path the U.S. Supreme Court has chosen under the First Amendment. Mining these state law histories can be helpful for refuting the Court’s policy-oriented claims and imagining alternative futures for federal constitutional press protections.Footnote 53

This chapter proceeds in two sections. Section 13.1 outlines the text, drafting history, and interpretive precedents of federal and state press and speech clause protections, focusing attention where state courts have interpreted state constitutional press protections to sweep more broadly than the First Amendment. Section 13.2 examines the future of federal and state press and speech clauses. It identifies state constitutional provisions and precedents that could be seized upon by advocates to expand protections for the press. And it provides examples of ways that the experiences of the states can be used to bolster arguments for broader press protections under federal law.

13.1 Constitutional Protections for the Press

Federal and state constitutions articulate very different textual protections for the press. This is true in terms of both press and speech clauses and more ancillary provisions like rights of information access. These state constitutions also have vastly different histories of drafting and judicial interpretation. This part maps out these distinctions across the federal and state contexts, focusing attention on the substantive areas where the states have extended press protections beyond what the First Amendment allows.

13.1.1 Constitutional Text

The Press Clause of the First Amendment provides that “Congress shall make no law … abridging the freedom … of the press.”Footnote 54 It is paired with the Speech Clause, set off by semi-colons from both the religious clauses and the assembly and petition clauses that follow.Footnote 55 The U.S. Supreme Court has extended few, if any, substantive rights protections under the Press Clause alone.Footnote 56 Rather, press-related protections have been extended through some combination of speech and press rights. The Court has also repeatedly declined to extend exclusive constitutional protections enjoyed by press speakers alone.

In contrast, the states have taken a different approach. All fifty state constitutions extend protections for freedom of speech and the press.Footnote 57 But only two states – Hawaii and South Carolina – have adopted free expression provisions that track the language of the First Amendment.Footnote 58 The other forty-eight state constitutions depart from the federal model.Footnote 59 Many do so in ways that suggest strong protections for the press.

For example, many of these state free expression provisions protect a broader set of substantive rights than those contained in the First Amendment. Forty states protect the right to “speak, write, and publish” as three distinct components of freedom of expression.Footnote 60 A few state constitutions also make explicit the democratic role of free press provisions, specifying that the printing press must be free to those who wish to “examine” the work of “any branch of government.”Footnote 61 Still others protect “the free communication of thought and opinion,” which may encompass a broader set of activities than speech and press protections alone.Footnote 62

Protections for the press are also articulated in stronger terms in some state constitutions. For example, Kansas’ speech and press clause provides that “the liberty of the press shall be inviolate.”Footnote 63 Virginia’s stipulates that “freedoms of speech and of the press are among the great bulwarks of liberty and can never be restrained except by despotic governments.”Footnote 64 And Mississippi’s provides that “freedom of speech and of the press shall be held sacred,”Footnote 65 elevating free expression provisions to those “worthy of religious veneration.”Footnote 66

There are notable structural distinctions as well. Most state constitutions protect speech and press in a single stand-alone provision. Only two pair free expression with religious rights.Footnote 67 And one state, Rhode Island, protects the rights of speech and of the press in separate constitutional sections.Footnote 68 Such structural separation further supports construing press and speech protections separately rather than as coextensive rights.

Most state constitutions also articulate press and speech rights in positive terms. Only a handful contain an exclusively negative expression of these rights, analogous to the First Amendment’s prohibition that “Congress shall make no law” abridging the freedom of speech or the press.Footnote 69 The rest articulate protection at least in part in positive terms. Around three-quarters of state constitutions provide that “every person” has an affirmative right to speak and publish freely.Footnote 70 And about half contain both negative and affirmative articulations. They provide that “every person shall be at liberty to speak, write or publish his opinions on any subject.” And they provide that “no law shall ever be passed curtailing the liberty of speech or of the press.”Footnote 71

State courts have often found this negative/positive rights distinction salient when interpreting the scope of state constitutional press shields.Footnote 72 They have pointed to these affirmative constructions of state constitutional provisions as evidence of an intentional decision by state constitutional drafters to provide broader free expression protections than those provided by the First Amendment. For example, New York’s highest court has interpreted the state’s constitution to offer stronger defamation protections for statements of opinion than the U.S. Constitution provides.Footnote 73 In doing so, it reasoned that these state speech and press provisions “reflect the deliberate choice of the New York State Constitutional Convention not to follow the language of the First Amendment, ratified 30 years earlier, but instead to set forth our basic democratic ideal of liberty of the press in strong affirmative terms.”Footnote 74

This is not to say that all state constitutional textual distinctions trend in this same direction, toward broader protection. Some contain more watered-down articulations of free expression rights. For example, a handful provide that the liberty of the press “ought” not be violated, in contrast with the more forceful prohibition contained in the First Amendment.Footnote 75 Many state constitutions also spell out the limits of these protections more explicitly than the First Amendment. For instance, forty state constitutions include language specifying that those who exercise speech and press rights are “responsible for their abuse.”Footnote 76 And around half of state constitutional free expression provisions stipulate that truth must be accepted as a defense to libel, which some courts have read to be rights-contracting.Footnote 77 Yet overall, many of these textual distinctions and departures in state constitutions suggest expanded state-level protections for the press in comparison to the First Amendment.

13.1.2 Constitutional Histories

The First Amendment drafting history is thin. The drafters spent little time debating proposed press protections at the Constitutional Convention.Footnote 78 And the debates of the state ratifying conventions often yielded conflicting conclusions.Footnote 79 The drafters almost certainly intended to restrict prior restraints against speech.Footnote 80 But consensus has splintered from there over the original meaning of the First Amendment.Footnote 81 There is a vast literature plumbing these drafting histories for evidence of the federal constitutional drafters’ original intent when enacting these constitutional press and speech protections.Footnote 82 Ultimately, much of the confusion likely stems from the drafters’ own differing visions of speech and press protections.Footnote 83

When it comes to the drafting histories of the fifty state free expression provisions, however, the interpretive task becomes even more difficult. There are fifty state press clauses contained in fifty separate state constitutions. Collectively, these state constitutions have been amended more than 7,000 times.Footnote 84 It is impossible to provide a detailed accounting of each of these histories. They are too varied, too long, and too complex. Yet even a cursory review yields some insights.

The earliest state constitutional press clauses were drafted during the revolutionary period, and these state constitutional provisions reflect the drafters’ preoccupation with checking government abuse.Footnote 85 The colonists chafed at British control over the press, and revolutionary leaders seized upon the issue of press freedom both to shore up support for the cause and to distinguish themselves from British rule.Footnote 86 They declared freedom of the press to be “a great bulwark of liberty,”Footnote 87 necessary for the “ready communication of thoughts” among citizens.Footnote 88 And nine of the eleven state constitutions adopted during the Revolutionary War contained a press clause.Footnote 89 These state constitutions were “revolutionary manifestos.”Footnote 90

The state constitutional texts embody this revolutionary history. Pennsylvania’s 1776 Declaration of Rights, for example, provides that “the printing presses shall be free to every person who undertakes to examine the proceedings of the legislature, or any part of government.”Footnote 91 Virginia’s 1776 Declaration of Rights declares that “freedom of the press is one of the great bulwarks of liberty, and can never be restrained but by despotic governments.”Footnote 92 And New Hampshire’s 1783 Bill of Rights provides that “the liberty of the press is essential to the security of freedom in a state; it ought, therefore, to be inviolably preserved.”Footnote 93 As Professor Anderson has argued, these early press clause provisions suggested that press freedom operated as a structural democratic check against governmental abuse.Footnote 94

State constitutional drafting documents provide further support for this proposition. For example, William Cushing, the chief justice of the Massachusetts Supreme Court and one of the drafters of the Massachusetts Constitution, exchanged a series of letters with John Adams in 1789 about Massachusetts’ press clause.Footnote 95 They asked whether truthful criticism of government could be punished under this provision. Both men concluded it could not, and they rooted their decisions in structural democratic concerns.Footnote 96 “The liberty of publishing truth can never effectually injure a good government,” Cushing argued, but it might restrain a despotic one.Footnote 97 Adams agreed. Otherwise, “how are the characters and conduct” of elected representatives “to be known by their constituents, but by the press?”Footnote 98

This is not to say that the drafters and ratifiers of these state constitutional press provisions envisioned a wholly expansive set of rights. To the contrary, they tolerated substantial punishment of printers who supported the British cause.Footnote 99 John Adams signed the Sedition Act, and William Cushing enforced it.Footnote 100 These drafting histories are voluminous and contain many contradictions.Footnote 101 Yet the authors of these state press clauses were expressly concerned with the implications of a free press for a functioning democracy. As Professor Anderson put it, the drafters “may not have been sophisticated enough to realize that true freedom of expression must include freedom for even the most dangerous ideas, but they had seen the connection between press criticism and political change.”Footnote 102

In contrast, the language of the First Amendment became abstracted away from these revolutionary era claims over the course of its drafting process. The initial “bulwark of liberty” language was dropped from the First Amendment text. The speech and press protections were then joined with other expressive and religious liberties.Footnote 103 Yet many state constitutions still contain these original declarations explicitly tying freedom of the press to the preservation of democratic self-governance and the prevention of governmental abuse.Footnote 104 The text and histories of these early press clauses suggest that these state constitutional drafters viewed the press as a key check against the threat of an oppressive government.Footnote 105

Another key theme to emerge from these fifty distinct drafting histories is that state constitutions have been repeatedly altered and replaced over the course of 200 years. They have been amended at a much higher rate than the federal Constitution – an average of 115 times, versus the 27 amendments of the U.S. Constitution.Footnote 106 Of the original thirteen colonial constitutions, only Massachusetts’ survives today. The rest have been replaced one or more times.Footnote 107

This makes the task of ferreting out original intent difficult. Should a judge consider only the statements of the original drafters? What if other parts of the constitution were changed but the free expression clause remained intact? What does such legislative silence tell us? Such questions not only make it more complicated to identify original meaning but also make it more difficult to offer a coherent story about the drafting histories of these fifty state constitutions. Each state’s constitutional drafting history merits its own book-length treatment. This chapter does not attempt to offer a comprehensive account, nor does it provide a cohesive or overarching story of free expression in the states.Footnote 108 Instead, it focuses attention on a handful of substantive areas where press privileges and freedoms have been most strongly implicated.

13.1.3 Constitutional Interpretations

State courts have diverged in their interpretations of state constitutional press protections. This part surveys these precedents, focusing attention on the substantive areas where state constitutional texts have yielded more expansive protections for the press than the First Amendment. These include protections for confidential sources, recognition of constitutional rights of access, prohibitions against prior restraint, and protections against liability for defamation.Footnote 109

Not all of these protections are press specific. Some, like protections against prior restraints and defamation liability, extend to all speakers. Yet in practice, they tend to have an outsized effect on the press. Courts have long assumed that press speakers are uniquely at risk when it comes to both defamation lawsuits and the effects of a prior restraint on publication.Footnote 110

13.1.3.1 Reporter’s Privilege

The U.S. Supreme Court has repeatedly rejected the press’s claims to First Amendment-based protections for newsgathering processes, including protection for reporters’ confidential sources and information. In its landmark 1972 decision Branzburg v. Hayes, the Court addressed the claims of three reporters who refused to comply with a grand jury subpoena to reveal confidential information and sources.Footnote 111 The journalists argued that such disclosures would imperil the journalist-source relationship and impede the free flow of information to the public. They appealed to the Court to recognize a constitutionally based evidentiary privilege for journalists’ confidential sources and other confidential information.Footnote 112

The Supreme Court declined to do so, at least in the grand jury subpoena context. It reasoned that such a privilege does not appear in the text of the Constitution.Footnote 113 Nor had the courts recognized such a privilege at common law.Footnote 114 For more than 200 years, the Court wrote, the press had “flourished” without a First Amendment-based evidentiary shield.Footnote 115 The press was “far from helpless to protect itself” and didn’t require further constitutional protection.Footnote 116 “We are asked to create another [constitutional privilege] by interpreting the First Amendment to grant newsmen a testimonial privilege that other citizens do not enjoy,” the Court wrote. But “this we decline to do.”Footnote 117

In the decades since, many federal circuits have recognized a First Amendment-based privilege in other contexts. They have narrowed the holding in Branzburg to grand jury subpoenas, recognizing a qualified constitutional or common-law privilege in other judicial proceedings.Footnote 118 But they have splintered widely in their interpretations of this privilege, leading to a patchwork and inconsistent set of case law from one circuit to another.Footnote 119 For example, five circuits have recognized a qualified First Amendment privilege in some criminal cases. Two have extended the qualified shield only in some civil contexts. And one – the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit – has held there is no reporter’s privilege for nonconfidential material.Footnote 120

The states have pursued a different approach. Some have extended greater state constitutional protections for reporters’ confidential information and sources. California, for example, has enshrined the privilege directly into its state constitutional text. Article I, § 2 of the state constitution provides that members of the press may not be held in contempt for refusing to disclose either their confidential sources or their unpublished information gathered in the course of the reporting process.Footnote 121

The history of this provision is instructive. The California legislature enacted a statutory shield law in 1935.Footnote 122 But the courts began to push back, arguing that the law interfered with the judiciary’s inherent constitutional authority to execute its judicial duties.Footnote 123 Judges began to hold reporters in contempt, in spite of the requirements of the shield law.Footnote 124 The public responded by passing a ballot initiative in 1980 constitutionalizing the privilege.Footnote 125 The pamphlet accompanying the ballot explained to voters that the Supreme Court had declined to recognize a First Amendment-based privilege in Branzburg and therefore enhanced state constitutional protection was needed. “If our democratic form of government – of the people, by the people – is to survive, citizens must be informed,” the pamphlet stated. “A free press protects our basic liberties by serving as the watchdogs of our nation.”Footnote 126

While California is the only state to extend an explicit constitutional privilege for journalists, other state supreme courts have recognized an implicit privilege that derives from state speech and press protections.Footnote 127 Many others have enacted statutory shields, recognized a common law privilege, or extended protection through the rules of evidence.Footnote 128 These state privileges are often roughly equivalent to the scope of the qualified First Amendment privileges extended by the federal appellate courts.Footnote 129 But their boundaries can be distinct.Footnote 130 Moreover, these state provisions operate as an independent source of protection. This is significant, because the federal courts have been more reluctant in recent years to read Branzburg as extending constitutional protections for the press.Footnote 131 If the federal courts do roll back the scope of federal constitutional protections, such state-level shields will assume greater importance.Footnote 132

13.1.3.2 Rights of Access

Throughout the 1970s, journalists petitioned the Supreme Court to recognize First Amendment rights to access government information. The Court repeatedly declined to do so.Footnote 133 In the 1978 case KQED v. Houchins, for example, the Court rejected the press’s claim to a First Amendment right to access prison facilities.Footnote 134 After multiple inmates died at a prison in California, the county sheriff curtailed journalists’ access to the facilities.Footnote 135 A group of journalists sued, arguing that they had a constitutional right to access the prison. The Court denied the claim, holding that there is no First Amendment right of access to “all sources of information within government control.”Footnote 136

Two years later, in Richmond Newspapers v. Virginia, the Court did recognize a First Amendment right to access criminal trials.Footnote 137 But it made clear that the privilege extended to the public as a whole rather than to the press exclusively.Footnote 138 Moreover, the lower courts have largely limited the privilege to the judicial branch.Footnote 139 With a few exceptions for trial-like administrative proceedings like immigration hearings, the lower federal courts have not extended the right of access to the executive or legislative branches.Footnote 140

Many states, in contrast, have extended constitutional access rights more broadly. A handful have enshrined rights of information access directly into the state constitutional text. At least six state constitutions contain explicit “right-to-know” provisions, which impose constitutional obligations on governments to provide public access to government records and proceedings.Footnote 141 These rights are often articulated in expansive terms. Louisiana’s constitution, for example, provides that “no person shall be denied the right to observe the deliberations of public bodies and examine public documents, except in cases established by law.”Footnote 142 These state right-to-know provisions can be used by courts to expand access rights beyond the federal minimum. Courts in these states often reference these constitutional provisions to underscore the sweeping nature of the transparency obligations imposed on state and local governments.Footnote 143

Some state constitutions contain broader legislative transparency requirements as well. For example, Article I, § 5 of the U.S. Constitution provides that legislators may close proceedings when “in their Judgment” the discussion “require[s] Secrecy.”Footnote 144 But equivalent state provisions do not always permit state legislatures this same discretion to close legislative doors.Footnote 145 Further, some state legislative access provisions expressly contemplate the unique position of the press. Alabama’s constitution, for example, provides that under certain conditions the legislative houses may exclude the public from its proceedings, but they may not exclude “representatives of the press.”Footnote 146

There are other salient distinctions between federal and state constitutional access provisions as well. While the federal constitutional right of access is derived from the text of the First Amendment,Footnote 147 for example, roughly half of state constitutions contain express “open courts” provisions.Footnote 148 State courts, moreover, have often interpreted these requirements broadly. For instance, in Washington, the courts have held that the constitutional open-courts provision requires judges to proceed through a rigorous five-step analysis before they may exclude the public from access to certain court proceedings.Footnote 149

State rights of access may also reach a greater set of government actors. The First Amendment right of access is limited to the judicial branch.Footnote 150 But many state constitutional access provisions extend further. At times this is explicit. For example, Missouri’s constitution expressly states that legislative records are public records.Footnote 151 Voters made the change in 2018 after the legislature tried to exempt itself from the state public records law.Footnote 152 And Kentucky’s constitution provides that a governor who grants pardons or commutes sentences must make the supporting records available to the public.Footnote 153 Such provisions make clear that constitutional access requirements extend beyond the judicial branch.

Finally, implicit state constitutional rights of access – those that derive from explicit press and speech provisions – may also sweep more broadly than the federal constitutional right of access. For example, the Utah Supreme Court has held its state constitution requires additional factual showings before a court may order the press not to disseminate information about a trial, beyond what the First Amendment requires.Footnote 154 Taken together, these various state-level constitutional rights of information access can have important implications for the press’s ability to engage in newsgathering efforts.

13.1.3.3 Prior Restraints

Under the First Amendment, prior restraints against publication are presumptively unconstitutional. But they are not prohibited outright. In Near v. Minnesota, the U.S. Supreme Court struck down a prior restraint on the publication of a magazine.Footnote 155 But it recognized there may be times where such restrictions were permissible, such as when protecting “the number and location of troops” in wartime.Footnote 156 Decades later, the Court reaffirmed its holding in the Pentagon Papers case,Footnote 157 holding once again that prior restraints are constitutionally disfavored but not categorically prohibited.Footnote 158

A handful of states have taken a different approach. They have interpreted state constitutional free expression provisions to create an absolute prohibition against prior restraints. As early as 1805, for example, the Pennsylvania Supreme Court read the state’s press provision to mean that citizens were free to “publish as [they] please in the first instance without control.”Footnote 159 Later that century, the California Supreme Court held that the state constitution’s speech and press provision forbids all prior government restraints on speech.Footnote 160 It reasoned that the First Amendment and the state constitution contained very different textual provisions. The state constitutional provision provided that “every citizen may freely speak, write, and publish his sentiments on all subjects.” And the state supreme court concluded that the plain language of this provision made clear that a citizen “shall have no censor over him to whom he must apply for permission.”Footnote 161

Other states followed suit, rooting their decisions in textual distinctions between the federal and state speech and press provisions. Arizona’s constitution, for example, provides that “every person may freely speak, write, and publish on all subjects.”Footnote 162 The state supreme court has read this language to mean that “there can be no censor appointed to whom the press must apply for prior permission to publish.”Footnote 163 Similarly, the Washington Supreme Court has read its free expression provision to “rule out prior restraints under any circumstances.”Footnote 164 And the Missouri Supreme Court has read its constitutional protections for speech and the press to operate as “an affirmative prescription against any exception.”Footnote 165

These decisions do not rule out the possibility of post-publication liability. To the contrary, most state constitutions provide that individuals are “responsible for the abuse” of speech and press rights.Footnote 166 But in terms of ex ante restraints on speech, some state supreme courts have held that their state constitutional free speech and press provisions sweep more broadly than the First Amendment.

13.1.3.4 Defamation

Some state constitutions also extend broader protections against defamation liability than those provided by the First Amendment. In The New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, the Supreme Court held that the First Amendment required government officials to show “actual malice,” or either knowledge of the truth or reckless disregard for the truth, in order to prevail in a defamation suit.Footnote 167 The Court reasoned that aggressive libel lawsuits by government officials would have the effect of chilling public speech and criticism.Footnote 168 A decade later in Gertz v. Welch, the Court extended the requirement to public figures more broadly.Footnote 169

In the decades since, Sullivan and its progeny have offered broad protections for the media to aggressively critique the government. They have also made it difficult for many defamation plaintiffs to prevail. The lower courts have expanded the definition of “public figure” to encompass many private figures unwittingly dragged into a public controversy.Footnote 170 At the same time, the media landscape has also changed in important ways in recent years.Footnote 171 Some critics have pointed to these legal and societal changes to argue that Sullivan should be overturned. Most notably, Justices Clarence Thomas and Neil Gorsuch have attacked Sullivan on both historical and empirical grounds, arguing that the press no longer deserves such insulation against defamation liability.Footnote 172

There is no indication that Sullivan is at imminent risk of being reversed.Footnote 173 But if it were to be overturned, state constitutional defamation law would take on new salience. Any loss of federal constitutional rights would put new pressure on the equivalent state constitutional provisions.Footnote 174 State constitutional speech and press provisions could act as a partial safety net against the threat of federal constitutional retrenchment of First Amendment rights.

Many state courts would likely retain actual malice requirements under their state constitutions, even if Sullivan were to be cast aside. Actual malice requirements originated in the states.Footnote 175 Although these early state court decisions were mostly rooted in common law rather than in state constitutional protections, these decisions predate Sullivan and would likely survive its repeal.Footnote 176 Further, state supreme courts have not had reason to weigh in on whether their state constitutions independently require actual malice. The First Amendment sets the constitutional floor, and any equivalent state law defamation protections would be redundant.Footnote 177 But the repeal of Sullivan would force state courts to confront this question. And it is likely that many would find that actual malice requirements persisted under state constitutional law, especially in states with a long tradition of extending broad speech and press protections.Footnote 178

This is not the only way that state constitutions implicate defamation liability. State courts have also interpreted state free expression provisions to provide broader protections against defamation suits. One example is state constitutional protection for statements of opinion. Until the 1980s, the federal lower courts offered extensive protections under the First Amendment.Footnote 179 The leading case was a U.S. Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit opinion that held that the First Amendment provided absolute immunity from defamation liability for opinion-based claims.Footnote 180 The D.C. Circuit case also articulated a four-part test for determining whether a statement qualified for this opinion-based protection.Footnote 181 Many other federal circuits and state supreme courts adopted this approach.

But the Supreme Court overruled the D.C. Circuit opinion in 1990, in Milkovich v. Lorain Journal.Footnote 182 It articulated a narrower conception of opinion protection instead, one that turned on whether a statement was provably false.Footnote 183 The decision sowed confusion in the lower courts.Footnote 184 And a number of state supreme courts eschewed this new approach, adhering instead to the more press-protective D.C. Circuit standard when it came to state constitutional defamation protections.Footnote 185

Notably, these state courts often rooted these decisions in textual and historical features unique to their state. New York’s highest court, for example, reasoned that the state constitution’s free expression provision articulates protection in “strong affirmative terms,” unlike the First Amendment’s negative prohibition against government interference.Footnote 186 The state court also described the state’s long history of press protection and New York City’s role as the “cultural center for the Nation.”Footnote 187 Such textual, historical, and cultural features distinct to the state, the court reasoned, weighed in favor of broader state constitutional protection against defamation liability.Footnote 188

Other state courts adopted similar reasoning. They held that their state constitutions, too, provided more robust protection against defamation liability. They likewise rooted these decisions in their states’ unique history and distinct constitutional texts. The Rhode Island Supreme Court, for example, emphasized that its colony had been founded by religious “dissenters” and that the “free flow of opinion and debate” had been especially “vital” to the state.Footnote 189 And the Utah Supreme Court cited the state’s tradition of aggressive editorial dissent between newspapers representing Mormon and non-Mormon interests when justifying recognizing broader defamation protections for statements of opinion than the First Amendment provided.Footnote 190

13.2 The Future of Constitutional Press Protections

State constitutions already operate as a source of independent protection for the press. Press advocates could do more to capitalize on these constitutional provisions. They could utilize state constitutions to extend new or expanded protections for the press. They could also mine the experience of the states and the history of state constitutional experimentation to bolster arguments for expanded federal press protections.

13.2.1 The Future of State Constitutional Press Protections

Textual and historical distinctions between federal and state constitutions have sometimes yielded broad protections for the press, beyond what the First Amendment provides. Further, certain states have also developed strong traditions of press protection, ones rooted in the distinct cultural or political features of the state.Footnote 191 But these efforts could be expanded. Press advocates could be more aggressive in raising state constitutional claims.Footnote 192 State courts could interpret these textual and historical distinctions to offer broader constitutional protections for the press. And voters could amend state constitutions in response to new or growing threats to journalism.Footnote 193

When it comes to state constitutional texts, there is significant overlap in the fifty state constitutional free expression provisions.Footnote 194 States that have already offered broader protections can serve as a roadmap for other states to follow. Decisions expanding press protections in one state can be utilized when advocating for similar recognition in another, especially when the textual language is closely aligned. For example, New York’s supreme court invoked the state’s “strong affirmative” right to “speak, write, and publish on all subjects” when extending strong protections for statements of opinion.Footnote 195 Thirty-nine other state constitutions contain this same provision, articulated in the same affirmative terms.Footnote 196 Yet only a few have followed suit. Press advocates in those other states could look to New York’s decision for guidance when raising similar claims.Footnote 197

Press advocates could also raise novel claims for protection, ones rooted in the unique textual or structural features of the state constitutions or the state’s distinctive histories and traditions. They could better capitalize on existing right-to-know protections, for example.Footnote 198 While state supreme courts often gesture to these provisions when discussing the state’s strong support for open government, they rarely interpret these clauses to offer meaningful expansions of the state-level rights of access. Press advocates could take up this cause. They could argue, for instance, that the constitutional right of access reaches government actors or entities not covered by public records statutes.

Press advocates could also utilize textual provisions that clearly assign the press a structural democratic role. They could draw upon constitutional language that emphasizes the role of the press in overseeing government – for example, provisions that stipulate the “printing presses shall be free to everyone who undertakes to examine the proceedings of the legislature or any branch of government.”Footnote 199 They could also invoke constitutional language that makes explicit the link between the suppression of the press and autocratic government, such as those declaring that freedom of the press “can never be restrained except by despotic governments.”Footnote 200 Such textual provisions make a powerful constitutional statement about the democratic role and responsibility of the press.

Press advocates could also lean more heavily on the affirmative nature of state press protections.Footnote 201 These affirmative provisions could be cited to support a set of expanded positive rights and obligations that flow from state press and speech protections. They could be used to argue in favor of more affirmative and active government interventions – ones that would proactively ensure a vibrant and healthy information ecosystem. These could include, for example, expanded newsgathering protections. A more radical interpretation of these positive rights provisions might be that they impose affirmative obligations on the government to support local news institutions – for example, through tax breaks or subsidies.Footnote 202 The collapse of the local press has lent new urgency to such projects.

State constitutional structural design could also be used to support expanded press protections. For instance, Rhode Island’s constitution enshrines protection for speech and the press in separate constitutional provisions.Footnote 203 The U.S. Supreme Court has interpreted these federal speech and press rights to overlap, leaving the Press Clause with little independent meaning.Footnote 204 Yet in the state constitutional context, such structural separation cuts against developing this same type of textual redundancy between press and speech rights.Footnote 205 Press advocates could better capitalize upon these types of distinctions.

Relatedly, variations in state constitutional drafting histories could also offer opportunities for press advocates. Many of the debates of the earliest state constitutions have been preserved.Footnote 206 Further, these original constitutions have all been amended or replaced, often repeatedly.Footnote 207 This introduces a range of methodological questions and complexities when it comes to state constitutional interpretation.Footnote 208 But it also means that there is a larger set of state-level drafting materials to draw upon.Footnote 209 These later state constitutions often have more detailed and better-preserved records of the drafting debates.Footnote 210 They, too, can be mined to support broader state-level press protections.

Finally, state constitutional processes can be used to expand protections for the press. State constitutions are more easily amended than the U.S. Constitution.Footnote 211 This permits voters to respond to new or emerging threats to the press through ballot initiatives and amendments. In this way, states’ bill of rights provisions serve a distinct political function from the federal Bill of Rights. These state constitutional processes allow state voters to respond more quickly to “particular government failures.”Footnote 212

Consider the example of California’s constitutional reporter’s privilege shield. Voters responded to specific threats to the press by elevating statutory reporter’s privilege protections to constitutional status.Footnote 213 Other states could follow suit. They could respond to new or emerging threats to the press through ballot initiatives and amendments. They could amend state constitutions to enshrine all manner of press protections into the constitutional text – not just confidential sources but also expanded protections against defamation liability, prior restraints, government surveillance of journalists, and more. To the extent that existing statutory press provisions seem imperiled, voters could constitutionalize them, making them more difficult to ignore or circumvent in the future.

13.2.2 The Future of Federal Constitutional Press Protections

State-level constitutional experimentation might also hold important lessons for ongoing debates about federal protections for the press. This is not universally true. Different political, historical, and legal considerations are in play at the federal versus state levels. Some state-level protections – for example, absolute prohibitions against prior restraints – might be ill-suited to the federal context, given the unique national security and military considerations at stake at the federal level.Footnote 214 Moreover, there are important textual distinctions between federal and state press and speech provisions that limit the extent to which state constitutional interpretations can be adopted wholesale into the federal context.

Yet some state-level innovations might still be helpful in informing federal press-advocacy efforts. Specifically, the experience of the states could be mined to refute some of the Court’s policy-based justifications for declining special First Amendment protections for the press. The Supreme Court has repeatedly declined to engage in the task of defining who qualifies for press-specific protections, for example. In Branzburg v. Hayes, the Court wrote: “Sooner or later, it would be necessary to define those categories of newsmen who qualified for the privilege,” a task made complicated because the “informative function asserted by representatives of the organized press in the present cases is also performed by lecturers, political pollsters, novelists, academic researchers, and dramatists.”Footnote 215 In other words, the definitional questions are simply too difficult for the courts to untangle.

The experience of the states undermines this claim. Forty-nine states extend some form of reporter’s privilege to journalists through a mix of common law, constitutional, and statutory protections.Footnote 216 This has required defining who qualifies for protection. The states have taken various approaches – some functional, others more formal.Footnote 217 But overall, the experience of the states suggests that this definitional concern may be overblown. The states have managed the task largely without controversy, often finding that the person asserting the privilege is so clearly a journalist that they don’t need to define the outer boundaries of its scope. As Professor Sonja West has argued, the experience of the states shows that “defining ‘the press’ can be done.”Footnote 218

We can also imagine how state experimentation might hold additional lessons for federal Press Clause constructions in the future. The Supreme Court has been hesitant to endow the federal Press Clause with any independent meaning. State constitutional examples can be used to illuminate new and different paths forward. These contrary experiences and histories of the states can be cited when urging the Court to revisit its holdings in such cases as Branzburg and Milkovich, for example.Footnote 219 State constitutional experimentation can be used to offer the Court a concrete set of examples for alternative options. And they can be used to help imagine a more expansive First Amendment – one that supports a more robust set of press rights.

13.3 Conclusion

The Roberts Court has curtailed the scope of various constitutional rights provisions in recent years. In response, scholars and activists have increasingly looked to state constitutions as an alternative source of protection. Across substantive areas like abortion and climate change, state courts have interpreted state constitutions to provide more expansive rights than the U.S. Constitution.Footnote 220 This chapter argues that members of the press should look to state constitutions as an alternative source of legal protection as well.

The U.S. Supreme Court has consistently declined to interpret the First Amendment in ways that extend special privileges to the press. But state constitutions can be used to fill in these federal constitutional gaps, operating as a powerful and independent source of protection for the media. Some states have already done so. They have extended greater protection under the state constitution when it comes to prohibitions against prior restraint, reporter’s privilege shields, rights of information access, and protections against defamation liability.Footnote 221 These decisions are rooted in textual, structural, and historical distinctions between the federal and state constitutions, as well as differences in the federal and state political experiences.Footnote 222

But more can be done. Press advocates could better capitalize on these distinctions going forward. They could look to the comparatively stronger texts of state constitutions to support stronger press rights. They could draw upon structural distinctions in state constitutions to avoid interpreting state-level press clauses to be wholly duplicative of state speech clauses. They could amend state constitutions in response to new and growing threats to the press. And they could hold up the examples of state constitutional experimentation to help imagine a new and more expansive First Amendment. These fifty “other press clauses” could step in where the federal Press Clause has failed.

14 The Long Shadow of Food Lion

While attending a conference a few years ago, I had a private conversation about undercover investigations with the deputy general counsel of one of the nation’s leading newspapers. When I asked about what I perceived to be a significant decrease in news media conducting such investigations, the person responded something to the effect of, “Well, Food Lion pretty much ended all that.” The reference was to the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit’s 1999 decision in Food Lion, Inc. v. Capital Cities/ABC, Inc.,Footnote 1 one of the most important lower federal court cases shaping freedom of the press under the First Amendment in the past twenty-five years. The case involved a lawsuit by a large grocery store chain against ABC News and two of its producers, who had conducted an undercover investigation revealing that some stores’ employees engaged in unsanitary, and possibly unlawful, food handling practices.Footnote 2 Although the ultimate outcome of the Fourth Circuit’s decision was on balance favorable to the press, it flatly rejected the news network’s contention that the First Amendment in any way limits tort claims against journalists engaged in this form of newsgathering.Footnote 3

This chapter discusses the continuing shadow of the Food Lion case, which looms over the efforts of journalists and, increasingly of other citizens, to engage in undercover investigations to discover and disseminate truthful information on matters of profound public concern. At a time when many impediments to freedom of the press have emerged, legal barriers to undercover investigations suppress a key newsgathering tool that was once an important part of the news media ecosystem. Section 14.1 provides a brief overview of undercover investigations in American journalism and then explores how the Food Lion investigation was developed internally and carried out by Susan Barnett and Lynne Dale, producers at ABC’s “Primetime Live” newsmagazine show.

In Section 14.2, the chapter describes the extensive litigation battle that followed ABC’s national broadcast of the Food Lion story and surveys the major legal objections to undercover investigations. It contends that the Food Lion decision created a significant degree of uncertainty about whether and when such investigations may be carried out without violating the law. The case never reached the U.S. Supreme Court, making it technically binding only in the five states governed by the Fourth Circuit. But because the Supreme Court has never taken up the specific First Amendment question implicated by the Food Lion case, the lower court’s decision continues to have widespread, arguably outsized, influence on the law governing undercover investigations.

Section 14.2 goes on to argue that Food Lion is responsible for a palpable chilling effect on those who might otherwise engage in undercover investigations, particularly those involving an investigator who secures employment with the target of an investigation. But Food Lion is more than just a legal precedent. Its deterrent effect also flows from the fact that it has shaped, and continues to shape, the journalism profession’s internal ethical debates about undercover investigations. Sections 14.1 and 14.2 are based in part on interviews conducted with Barnett and Dale, as well as with Nathan Siegel, one of ABC’s key legal counsel in the Food Lion case.Footnote 4

Section 14.3 proceeds to call for reconsideration of the Food Lion framework and articulation of a meaningful constitutional protection for some aspects of newsgathering, which are long overdue. It lays out a tentative framework for a limited First Amendment privilege to protect undercover investigators from both targeted and generally applicable criminal and civil laws, and it addresses the limitations on and concerns with recognition of such a privilege.

14.1 The News Media, Undercover Investigations, and Free Speech
14.1.1 Undercover Investigations in American Journalism

As I have written about extensively in other forums,Footnote 5 undercover investigations have been a fundamental component of newsgathering by the institutional press at various times throughout American history. Undercover investigations are actions taken by journalists who seek access to places, persons, and actions, when the investigative targets would otherwise not welcome investigators.Footnote 6 They typically involve two features that are sometimes questioned as problematic, unethical, or even illegal. First, the journalists gain access to the investigative target by using some form of deception – lying about their true identity, their news media employer, and their motives for seeking access to the target (or at least omitting relevant information about those things) – in order to gather information on matters of public concern.Footnote 7 One common undercover reporting tactic involves the journalist obtaining employment with the investigation’s target.

Second, those who engage in undercover investigations also often use hidden cameras or recording devices to memorialize the conduct or information they are seeking to expose. The recordings verify what would otherwise be only the investigator’s narrative account, thus lending substantial credibility to the information disclosed to the public. As Susan Barnett, one of the producers who went undercover for the Food Lion investigation told me, recording can be important to address a public increasingly skeptical of the press: If “[the viewers] don’t see it, they don’t believe it.”Footnote 8

American journalists began employing undercover investigative tactics before the Civil War, when northern newspapers sent reporters to the South to report on the abhorrent conditions of slavery.Footnote 9 During the war, undercover methods were also important tools for journalists from the North, who would have risked great danger reporting from the battlefields in the South had their true identities been known.Footnote 10 Since that time, the popularity of such investigations has ebbed and flowed, depending in part on historical context, changes in relevant legal and ethical principles, and the availability (or lack thereof) of other newsgathering methods.Footnote 11

Undercover investigations appear to have thrived during two periods in American history. The first high point was during the Progressive Era. By some accounts, the method was first popularized in the late 1800s and early 1900s by women seeking opportunities to break into what was then the male-dominated journalism profession. To the extent they could get newspaper jobs at all, women were hired primarily to write about issues that their editors believed were of concern only to women, such as fashion.Footnote 12 Women seeking to be treated as serious journalists turned to undercover investigations. But they were pejoratively dubbed “girl stunt reporters” for their exploits, suggesting that they were engaged in a kind of sensationalist journalism perhaps unworthy of “real” (i.e., male) reporters. Despite that label, these intrepid journalists exposed shocking misconduct across a wide range of the public and private sectors.Footnote 13

In an attempt to break into the profession with hard news stories, some female reporters went undercover to gather information and then write about many of the day’s most important social issues. The journalist most closely associated with this movement is Elizabeth Cochran, who wrote under the pen name Nellie Bly. Bly conducted numerous undercover investigations over the course of her impressive career but is best known for feigning symptoms causing her to be institutionalized at the Blackwell’s Island Insane Asylum for Women, where she discovered systematically inhumane treatment of its residents. She took this information and first documented these conditions in the pages of the New York World newspaper, and later in her book, Ten Days in a Mad-House.Footnote 14

Upton Sinclair, the writer who is perhaps most associated with undercover investigations, used similar methods to investigate conditions in the Chicago meatpacking industry in 1904. Though he initially undertook this work to expose the greed and excesses of the animal agriculture industry and the poor treatment of meatpacking workers, his investigation quickly turned to the stomach-turning conditions of food sanitation and handling, issues that later became the focus of his bestselling novel, The Jungle.Footnote 15 As Brooke Kroeger wrote, Sinclair:

… intended to provide a searing examination of Big Beef, its power and corruption, and the grisly working conditions of the immigrant poor. But his story soon began to turn on his stark depictions of how contaminated meat was making its way from the packinghouses of Chicago to the dinner tables of the world.Footnote 16

In order to gather information for their stories, Sinclair and others who conducted undercover investigations during the Progressive Era used either overt or implicit forms of deception to gain access to people, places, and conduct that would otherwise have been inaccessible to them. In each case, that information was conveyed to the public and meaningfully informed public discourse and policy debates. Of course, given the technology of the day, they did not, like contemporary journalists, use hidden recording equipment. Rather, they relied on their memories and surreptitious notetaking to memorialize their findings. Sinclair reportedly would retire to his living quarters each evening to write down his notes while his memory was still fresh.Footnote 17 Given that his investigation spanned a period of seven weeks, he had to find some way to ensure that his information was documented without being detected.

Although the earlier work of the women undercover journalists and Sinclair are often linked, Kroeger suggested that by Sinclair’s time, the standards for conducting such investigations and reporting the stories had evolved significantly. By the early twentieth century, journalists’ undercover investigations were more sophisticated and reporters “went to great lengths to verify and analyze their findings.”Footnote 18 Thus, at this early stage, the tactics of undercover investigations were maturing in accordance with the best standards of professional journalism.

Following the Progressive Era, “there seems to be a lull in undercover investigations, or at least ones that received national attention, from the mid-twentieth century until the 1970s.”Footnote 19 Although journalists conducted undercover investigations intermittently from the Progressive Era to contemporary times, their use became much more prevalent after the Watergate scandal in the early 1970s, which placed investigative journalism front and center in the public’s eye. Although it is unclear whether Washington Post reporters Bob Woodward and Carl Bernstein ever engaged in the tactics used by most undercover investigators, many other journalists began expanding the use of undercover investigations during the years surrounding Watergate.Footnote 20 Professional journalism organizations began focusing on creating or updating ethics codes for the industry during this period as well.Footnote 21

The late 1960s and early 1970s also witnessed the introduction of a new form of journalism, the television newsmagazine. The first such program to receive national attention, CBS’s still-popular show, “60 Minutes,” began airing in 1968.Footnote 22 A type of long-form journalism, “television newsmagazine shows … allowed television journalists to go beyond reporting on discrete stories of the day to taking on broader, more time-consuming, and more expensive investigations.”Footnote 23 They were in part the networks’ reaction to the high costs and lack of advertising support for full-length documentaries, with executives believing that a single broadcast including multiple segments might be more successful.Footnote 24 Although some of the content was (and continues to be) “soft” news stories, television newsmagazines also evolved into a successful vehicle for airing the results of undercover investigations, as the Food Lion case illustrates. In addition, television newsmagazines benefited from the evolving technology making it easier to engage in secret recording, though not nearly as easy as it has become today.

Undercover investigations by American journalists have led to the discovery of information critical to public discourse about matters ranging from public corruption to food safety to sweatshop labor conditions, to name just a few. Although these investigative techniques originated in the journalism profession, they have since been adopted, and even celebrated and legally authorized, in other contexts. Fair housing investigators have long engaged in civil rights testing, where investigators using false identities and financial backgrounds are sent in to detect evidence of illegal racial steering and often document their findings with secret recordings.Footnote 25 Union activists may lawfully lie about their affiliation with unions to obtain jobs with employers whose workers they want to organize.Footnote 26 Law enforcement officers use the same tactics as undercover journalists to expose criminal activity through undercover sting operations.Footnote 27 And, more recently, political advocacy groups across the ideological spectrum have adopted undercover investigations to expose what they believe to be wrongful conduct.Footnote 28 As such, undercover investigations are an important vehicle for promoting transparency, accountability, and democracy, one of the central functions of the First Amendment.Footnote 29

Undercover investigations may be even more central to promoting those goals in the current political and news environment.Footnote 30 The United States is currently living through a time of increasing partisan divide as well as mistrust of government and other institutions. Relatedly, the nation seems to be experiencing a period of epistemic chaos, with some people disputing the very nature of truth while misinformation and disinformation campaigns thrive in part because of the speed with which information can be transmitted over the internet.

In other times, one natural response to this environment might have been a thriving, independent press that could investigate and report on the most critical issues of the day, checking and exposing abuses of truth by government actors, political candidates and organizations, and foreign government interlopers. But the American press is itself experiencing an existential crisis. The institutional news media is struggling through both internal and external threats to its existence. American newspapers have been substantially impaired because their business model has been undermined by the emergence of the internet as a less expensive and more widely viewed platform for news and advertising.Footnote 31 A recent study by researchers at Northwestern’s Medill School of Journalism projects that by the end of 2024, the nation will have lost a third of its newspapers since 2005.Footnote 32

Shrinking revenues have also caused even the surviving major newspapers to cut budgets, sometimes in areas crucial to newsgathering. As discussed in greater detail below, conducting journalistically sound undercover investigations requires substantial resources.Footnote 33 The reduction in resources has also affected another important newsgathering tool, the pursuit of information through open records laws. One report indicated that, with the exception of The New York Times, legacy media companies have substantially reduced the number of requests they submit under the federal Freedom of Information Act.Footnote 34

Nor is the news media immune to the fundamental loss of public trust that plagues other institutions. Multiple sources may be contributing to this loss of trust, from the sustained performative attacks on the news media by high-profile politicians to the emergence of the perception that “fake news” now pervades the media landscape (even though many of these stories come not from mainstream media but from individuals, organizations, and even foreign governments spreading disinformation across social media platforms).Footnote 35 There is also an increasing sense, it appears, that people believe the media is no longer “objective,” even though news entities have never been entirely neutral.Footnote 36

Finally, attacks on the media have also been literal, rather than metaphorical, with acts of violence or threats of such violence becoming tragically commonplace around the world.Footnote 37 The United States is not immune to the rise in violence against journalists. According to the U.S. Press Freedom Tracker, there were 593 assaults against journalists in the United States in 2020, which was an almost 1,400 percent increase over the prior year.Footnote 38 And those are just reported incidents. As Erin Carroll has observed, “Online insults and threats against journalists – particularly against women – exploded. According to one recent study, abuse is so rampant that it is part of the ‘daily work lives’ of women journalists. Researchers worry that the line between online attacks and offline violence is faint.”Footnote 39

One reaction to the challenges facing professional journalism in the United States might be to reinvigorate its newsgathering capacity to shore up its important role in promoting democracy. This might include devoting greater resources to reporting important stories through undercover investigations. Instead, we are witnessing increasing legal and ethical objections to this once important investigative practice.

14.1.2 ABC’s Investigation of Food Lion

During the heyday of television newsmagazines’ undercover investigations, producers at ABC’s popular “Primetime Live” learned from a couple of different sources about concerns with practices at some branches of the Food Lion grocery store chain, which operates stores mostly in the southeastern United States.Footnote 40 The investigation and story were the project of two producers, Susan Barnett and Lynne Dale, who had never previously worked together.Footnote 41 Barnett and Dale initially came at the story from different angles. Barnett had recently completed a well-received “Primetime Live” story about the meatpacking industry and reached out to her source on that story – the Government Accountability Project (GAP),Footnote 42 a nonprofit organization dedicated to protecting and advocating for whistleblowers. GAP shared with her reports from Food Lion workers who had indicated that employees at some stores were adulterating food sold to consumers. Dale had independently been gathering information about labor violations at Food Lion, which prompted her to pitch that element of the story. “It wasn’t about rotten meat, it was about [Food Lion stores] working employees off the clock.”Footnote 43

Notwithstanding what critics have suggested about undercover investigations, journalists do not typically undertake such investigations as fishing expeditions, sweeping broadly while hoping to uncover some unsavory conduct by their targets. Rather, this undercover work is usually just one component of an extensive, meticulous investigation using a combination of more traditional journalistic techniques, which may have already revealed a reasonable suspicion that an undercover investigation will lead to the discovery of additional newsworthy information. This was the case with the Food Lion investigation.

The Food Lion investigation was conducted consistent with the network and producers’ professional journalistic standards. First, investigations were not conducted unless there was first credible information that undercover work would turn up newsworthy information. Importantly, substantial background reporting and sourcing took place as part of the investigation. The Food Lion investigation involved several months of traditional reporting before the undercover investigation began.Footnote 44 As Barnett said: “We do all the paper trail work. It’s not like that doesn’t happen and we just go undercover.”Footnote 45 Nor is the story done when the undercover investigation has been completed. The producers worked for at least an additional six months between the investigation and the time the story was aired on national television.Footnote 46 In the end, the producers had obtained information from over 120 sources, all of whom were current or former Food Lion employees.Footnote 47 In addition, Barnett and Dale noted that it was important that an undercover story be one of “national importance” and have “national implication,” and that hidden cameras not be used if there were other ways to obtain the relevant information.Footnote 48 The consideration of both the importance of the story and the availability of less intrusive means of gathering relevant information parallels some of the journalism profession’s published ethical standards relating to undercover investigations.Footnote 49

While Barnett had done undercover investigations before, this was Dale’s first foray into this newsgathering tactic. Barnett pitched going undercover as Food Lion employees to corroborate the information they had already received. As they designed their investigation, they worked closely with ABC News’s legal counsel.Footnote 50 ABC approved the producers getting jobs at Food Lion stores, not disclosing their affiliation with ABC, and using hidden cameras. But the network stipulated that Barnett and Dale were to use their real names and Social Security numbers when they applied for their jobs at Food Lion, though it approved of them modifying significant aspects of their backgrounds on their resumes.Footnote 51 The trial court noted that Dale lied about having prior experiences as a meat wrapper and that both Barnett and Dale provided false references, employment histories, and addresses, and omitted any reference to their employer, ABC.Footnote 52

To conduct the undercover part of the investigation, Barnett and Dale successfully obtained jobs at different Food Lion stores. Dale worked for two weeks as a meat wrapper in two different stores and Barnett worked as a delicatessen clerk for one week in one store. While working, they both performed their jobs in compliance with their assigned duties, and also engaged in an investigation to confirm the reports about food handling and labor practices.Footnote 53 They both wore hidden cameras that they were able to turn on at appropriate times to document problems with the stores’ practices and recorded a total of about 45 hours of video between them.Footnote 54

ABC aired the story on national television on its “Primetime Live” newsmagazine program on November 5, 1992. As the Fourth Circuit described the practices revealed by the report:

The broadcast included … videotape that appeared to show Food Lion employees repackaging and redating fish that had passed the expiration date, grinding expired beef with fresh beef, and applying barbeque sauce to chicken past its expiration date in order to mask the smell and sell it as fresh in the gourmet food section. The program included statements by former Food Lion employees alleging even more serious mishandling of meat at Food Lion stores across several states. The truth of the PrimeTime Live broadcast was not an issue in the litigation.Footnote 55

Both before and after the story aired, however, there was a protracted legal battle over the legality of ABC’s investigation and the subsequent broadcast. Section 14.2 describes that litigation and the important legal questions surrounding undercover investigations that it framed but did not necessarily answer.

14.2 The Food Lion Litigation and Potential Legal Barriers to Undercover Investigations

As valuable as undercover investigations can be to promoting democracy, transparency, and public discourse, there have long been objections to the secretive tactics necessary to carry them out. Targets of such investigations have been predictably upset when a journalist exposes their illegal or otherwise unsavory conduct to public scrutiny. During the Progressive Era, critics would describe intrepid women reporters with the pejorative label “girl stunt journalists” in order to convey a lack of journalistic legitimacy and to place them below their male peers on some sort of professional hierarchy.Footnote 56 This suggested that this type of important journalistic work was sensationalist and unprofessional. Perhaps not surprisingly, current critics of undercover investigations attack investigators with comparable epithets.Footnote 57 But at least in the earlier years, criticisms of such investigations were confined to simple rhetorical attempts to undermine journalists’ professional credibility. Beginning sometime in the 1990s, however, investigative targets began turning to the courts in an effort to legally punish and chill undercover investigations.Footnote 58

14.2.1 Legal Theories Regarding Undercover Investigations

In its case against ABC, Food Lion invoked all three of the potential common law claims typically brought against undercover investigators – fraud, trespass, and violation of the duty of loyalty. Before recounting the course of the Food Lion litigation, therefore, a brief overview of each of these theories is warranted. To a significant extent, these claims overlap. They each require us to examine whether one who engages in investigative deception has violated a common law duty that causes tangible harm to the investigation’s target. Importantly, the relevant tort law operates against a background First Amendment doctrine governing the regulation of lies.

14.2.1.1 Fraud

At first glance, common law fraud is arguably the worst fit when it comes to undercover investigations. In Food Lion, the court applied the law of North Carolina and South Carolina, the two jurisdictions where the investigation took place.Footnote 59 Fraud in those states generally requires the plaintiff to show that the defendant intentionally made a false statement to the plaintiff, with the intent that the plaintiff rely on that statement, and that the plaintiff suffered injury by reasonably relying on the statement.Footnote 60 The Restatement (Second) of Torts’ definition of fraud is narrower, applying only where the false statement is used to either lead someone to make decisions related to a business transaction or give a gift to the fraudster or a third party.Footnote 61

The paradigm case of fraud is the use of false statements to induce the listener to make a purchase or financial investment. In the Food Lion case, however, the argument was that the producers made false statements in order to induce Food Lion to hire them as employees. Notably, even if one could argue that an undercover investigator is inducing someone to make the “business transaction” of hiring the investigator, that hiring decision still must damage the plaintiff. Yet most undercover investigators who conduct employment-based investigations are hired as lower level, at-will employees. Thus, the target is paying them a salary for their labor, and, assuming the investigators actually perform the job for which they were hired, the target is not harmed.

Furthermore, to recover for fraud, the plaintiff must show that the fraud was the cause of the harm. When the target of an investigation sues a journalist, it typically asserts that its damages flow not from the act of hiring the investigator, but from the disclosure of information discovered during the investigation. That is, they seek publication damages. As discussed below, however, under a fraud theory, the investigation’s target cannot succeed on the theory that the fraud led to damages from the publication of truthful information acquired through the fraud.

A related theory is that when journalists mislead a target in an employment-based investigation, they are committing “resume fraud.” The most obvious implication from the term resume fraud is that it applies to someone who inflates or exaggerates her credentials.Footnote 62 Journalists and others who seek employment to carry out an undercover investigation are usually qualified to do the jobs, otherwise they would likely be quickly discovered. If they are qualified and perform their duties satisfactorily, there would be no damages other than, again, the harm from any resulting publication damages. Courts are divided on this point. The trial court in Food Lion agreed that Barnett and Dale committed resume fraud, but on this point the Fourth Circuit disagreed.Footnote 63

The question of whether lying to get a job to conduct an undercover investigation is protected by the First Amendment turns on the United States Supreme Court’s decision in United States v. Alvarez.Footnote 64 In Alvarez, the Court invalidated the Stolen Valor Act, a federal criminal law prohibiting a person from falsely claiming to have been awarded high military honors. In doing so, the Court held that false statements of fact are protected under the First Amendment unless they cause a legally cognizable harm or provide a material gain to the speaker.Footnote 65 In dicta, the Alvarez plurality identified lies to secure “offers of employment” as not protected, because obtaining a job constituted securing a valuable consideration.Footnote 66

It is unlikely that the Court was contemplating undercover investigators when it included this language. From the context of this paragraph, the Court is describing paradigmatic cases of common law fraud in which people lie with the intent to secure a financial benefit. “It seems clear that the phrase ‘material gain’ as used in Alvarez is meant to be a synonym for fraud or injury-causing lie. Material gain in this context implies that the prevaricator is deriving some tangible benefit from the deceived party – that is to say, it is a species of unjust enrichment.”Footnote 67

However, in Animal Legal Defense Fund v. Wasden, the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit held that there is no First Amendment protection for an undercover investigator who lies to gain employment with an investigative target. In Wasden, the plaintiffs argued that this language from Alvarez meant only to address those who falsely inflate their qualifications for a job, which more closely resembles common law fraud. They claimed that someone who understates their education or experience or omits their political affiliation to gain a job for the purpose of exposing wrongdoing does not fall within the Alvarez’s “offers of employment” language. The Ninth Circuit rejected that argument on a couple of grounds. First, it noted that someone who seeks employment with the intent to harm the employer is in “breach of the covenant of good faith and fair dealing that is implied in all employment agreements in Idaho.”Footnote 68 Second, and perhaps more importantly, the court wrote that:

Although it may be true that “the goal of undercover employment-based investigations is not to ‘secure moneys or other valuable considerations’ for the investigator, but rather to expose threats to the public,” ALDF ignores that the Supreme Court singled out offers of employment and that these undercover investigators are nonetheless paid by the agricultural production facility as part of their employment.Footnote 69

Other courts, including the Fourth Circuit in Food Lion (albeit before Alvarez was decided), have disagreed.Footnote 70 The implication of Wasden is that states may, without violating the First Amendment, punish even lies that understate one’s qualifications or omit one’s motivations in order to gain employment. If that is the case, then journalists will rarely if ever be able to engage in an employment-based investigation. But even if the Supreme Court narrows this language in Alvarez so that undercover investigators may lie to get jobs for the purpose of undercover journalism, there are other barriers under the common law of tort that would continue to deter them.

14.2.1.2 Trespass

Investigative targets sometimes sue undercover investigators for common law trespass. The Restatement defines trespass as the intentional entry onto the land of another “irrespective of whether [the trespasser] thereby causes harm to any legally protected interest of the other.”Footnote 71 Two features of trespass law make it especially complicated to apply to undercover investigators. First, consent is an affirmative defense to trespass.Footnote 72 In the case of an undercover investigation, the target has given the investigator consent to enter the property, even if they have done so unaware of the investigator’s true identity and motive. In other words, the property owner knows they have consented to someone entering their land. In some jurisdictions, consent is vitiated if the alleged trespasser has secured it through fraud;Footnote 73 in others, however, consent induced by fraud is valid, and no trespass has occurred.Footnote 74 As I have written elsewhere, it is problematic for the Alvarez First Amendment standard to turn on a particular jurisdiction’s state law, both because there would not be a uniform free speech standard across states and because uncertainty about the nature of state law in a particular jurisdiction may create a chilling effect on investigators.Footnote 75

In some states, however, legislators have begun invoking trespassory interests as a justification for the enactment of criminal laws directed at undercover investigations. In recent years, for example, some states have crafted legislation targeting animal rights groups, who have adopted the undercover tactics of journalists to expose extreme abuses of farmed animals at industrial agriculture production facilities. These statutes, often referred to as “Ag Gag” laws, appear to be a direct response to several highly publicized undercover investigations by groups such as People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA). These laws impose criminal penalties on any person who either seeks access to animal facilities using deception or engages in secret recording at those facilities, or both. Such laws could also be used to prosecute journalists who conduct undercover investigations at such facilities.

Ag Gag laws target activists who, like journalists conducting undercover investigations, gain employment or otherwise gain access to agricultural facilities by lying or omitting information about their identities, motives, and affiliation with animal rights organizations. There has been extensive litigation about the constitutionality of such laws, with the plaintiffs asserting that the laws interfere with their First Amendment free speech rights. Those cases have led to mixed results, with some laws having been struck down in wholeFootnote 76 or in partFootnote 77 and others upheld.Footnote 78

The state law trespass question is also relevant to whether there is any First Amendment protection for undercover investigators. As we have seen, the Supreme Court’s decision in Alvarez holds that lies are protected by the First Amendment unless they cause a legally cognizable harm to the listener or produce a material gain for the liar.Footnote 79 Trespass is a strict liability tort, however, so even a nonconsensual entry onto the land of another may lead to a tort judgment even if no actual harm has occurred. Thus, a lie that leads to a trespass (in a jurisdiction where fraud vitiates consent), may only be protected under the First Amendment if it causes no legally cognizable harm, but the Restatement says a trespass occurs “irrespective of whether [the trespasser] thereby causes harm to any legally protected interest of the other.”Footnote 80 Whether undercover investigations constitute a trespass or involve constitutionally protected speech turns on how to read these two seemingly contradictory legal rules together.

14.2.1.3 Duty of Loyalty

Finally, because successful undercover investigators often obtain employment with their targets to gain access to the information they seek, targets have sometimes also turned to a less common legal claim under the duty of loyalty. The duty of loyalty, which is recognized in some form in all jurisdictions, finds its roots in the law of agency, under which agents have a fiduciary duty to act loyally for the principal’s benefit.Footnote 81 In the context of an undercover investigation, an employer can sue an undercover journalist under the theory that because the journalist is also working for their media employer, the employee is being disloyal to the target employer. The duty of loyalty is often described as being rooted in the long-standing, and somewhat anachronistic, biblical admonition against serving “two masters.”Footnote 82 Because it is central to the Fourth Circuit’s analysis in Food Lion, we will return to the duty of loyalty in greater detail below.

14.2.1.4 Defamation, Privacy, and Other Less-Viable Theories

Other causes of action not raised in Food Lion might conceivably be raised in response to undercover investigations, but are even more clearly not viable paths to liability. First, an employer might claim that an investigation violates its right of privacy. The only common law privacy torts that could conceivably apply in the context of undercover investigations would be intrusion upon seclusion and public disclosure of private facts. Intrusion upon seclusion relates to the types of personal privacy we all value, as it requires the tortfeasor to have interfered with the plaintiff’s private space in a way that intrudes on a person or their private affairs or concerns, of a kind that would be highly offensive to a reasonable person.Footnote 83 Because undercover investigations seek information of public concern that can inform public discourse, they do not seem susceptible to this type of claim unless the investigator exceeds the reasonable bounds of the investigative plan. Public disclosure of private facts does not likely fit with undercover investigations because it only applies where the alleged tortfeasor reveals private information about the plaintiff that would be highly offensive to a reasonable person and the information is not of legitimate public concern.Footnote 84 Indeed, the public concern limitation seems uniquely suited to protect newsgathering generally.

A related concern is that an investigation could intrude on the legitimate privacy interests of fellow employees, who may be captured on video or whose conduct or remarks may be collected by the journalists.Footnote 85 While there may be cases in which this is true, as long as an employee is acting in the presence of the journalist and other employees, there is at least a more limited expectation of privacy in that they are at the very least aware that someone else is watching or listening to them. But there is, of course, a material difference between whispering a private thought or secret to a coworker and announcing that same information on national television. And in such an environment, confiding in a coworker is certainly not unlikely; Barnett and Dale fully acknowledged that they liked their fellow employees and found most of them to be nice people during their short tenures.Footnote 86

But there are reasonably easy ways to protect the privacy of fellow employees during an undercover investigation. First, any video that is used in a broadcast can blur out the faces and other identifying information of the other employees. Second, there can be clear boundaries on what is newsworthy and what is not, with the latter including private personal information disclosed or revealed by other employees during an undercover investigation that are not germane to the topic being investigated. Third, there could be protections against undercover investigators “doxxing,” revealing employees’ private identifying information that may subject them to violence, threats, harassment, or embarrassing exposure to the public’s eye. For example, suppose an undercover investigation reveals an employee to have engaged in morally abominable or illegal behavior, and the investigator then published that person’s home address or other ways to locate them. Even if those employees have engaged in misconduct, there are legal avenues for addressing that without revealing their personal information and subjecting them to abuse. Doxxing can be prohibited under ethical regulations or best practices designed to limit the scope of undercover investigations.

One reason that investigative targets have invoked these particular common law claims is that they are unable to sue for defamation. Undercover investigations typically lead to the publication of truthful information, and truth is an affirmative defense to defamation claims under American law.Footnote 87 The Fourth Circuit even recognized this in the Food Lion case, when it described part of Food Lion’s claim as “an end-run around First Amendment strictures.”Footnote 88

The only other way that investigative targets could sue their investigators for the publication of truthful information is if the targets can establish a theory of publication damages. But again, publication of truthful information cannot lead to liability under defamation law. Still, those who have been embarrassed by undercover investigations have tried to assert damages claims even for the publication of truthful information if the information was obtained through means that violated tort law. Those claims have typically faltered on causation grounds, with courts concluding that the cause of any reputational harm from the publication of truthful information is the underlying wrongdoing rather than the disclosure of information about that wrongdoing.Footnote 89

14.2.2 The Food Lion Litigation and Decision

Following good journalistic practice, before ABC aired the Food Lion story, it contacted the grocery store company to notify it about the forthcoming broadcast and asked for a response. When Food Lion learned of ABC’s plan, it immediately filed a lawsuit in Forsyth County Superior Court in North Carolina. Though Food Lion did not seek a prior restraint on the entire broadcast, its complaint argued that Barnett and Dale had obtained the hidden camera footage illegally and its prayer for relief requested a preliminary and permanent injunction barring the network from using any of that material in its broadcast.Footnote 90 The news media defendants removed the case to federal court on diversity grounds and successfully blocked the injunction.Footnote 91 After the story was broadcast, Food Lion continued its suit, seeking money damages for the harm allegedly caused by the investigation and broadcast. Its three central claims represent the most common legal theories used to sue undercover investigators – common law fraud, trespass, and breach of the duty of loyalty.

The ensuing litigation at the federal trial court level was an intense battle lasting four years and four months from the time the case was removed to federal court until the end of the trial.Footnote 92 The parties fought over discovery questions, sought protective orders, asserted privileges, produced expert witnesses, and filed countless pretrial motions. Food Lion also sought sanctions against the defendants and their attorneys relating to some of the discovery fights.Footnote 93 There were serious disputes about how to conduct the trial as well. It is unclear whether this was a result of a court order or the parties’ agreement, but the actual “Primetime Live” story was never presented to the jury.Footnote 94 This may have been the case because, as the trial court recognized, “Food Lion made no defamation claim and, therefore, did not challenge the truthfulness of the broadcast.”Footnote 95

Finally, more than four years after the “Primetime Live” broadcasts, the case went to trial.Footnote 96 After a multiweek trial on liability, the jury found all defendants liable for fraud and found Dale and Barnett liable for trespass and violating the duty of loyalty. The district court also found, based on the jury’s findings, that the defendants had violated the state unfair and deceptive trade practices statute. It ruled, however, that Food Lion could not recover damages for lost profits, lost sales, or other economic harms associated with the broadcast on the ground that those damages were not proximately caused by the defendants’ conduct.Footnote 97

With that limit, the compensatory damages phase of the trial proceeded, with the jury awarding $1,400 in compensatory damages for fraud, two $1 nominal damage awards against both Barnett and Dale for trespass and breach of the duty of loyalty, and $1,500 in damages for violation of the state statute.Footnote 98 Finally, after the third phase of the trial, the jury awarded a stunning $5,545,750 in punitive damages against ABC and two of its executive producers.Footnote 99 Though the trial court reduced the punitive damages award to $315,000 on remittitur,Footnote 100 the verdicts were a substantial blow to the network, its producers, and the future of undercover investigations.

The defendants appealed, arguing on several grounds that the verdict should be overturned.Footnote 101 In a significant victory for the defendants, the Fourth Circuit reversed several aspects of the trial court’s rulings. First, the court reversed the trial court’s judgment that all defendants had committed fraud. In a creative variation on resume fraud, Food Lion claimed that it relied to its detriment on the belief that Barnett and Dale would continue in their jobs past the short period in which they worked. It argued that it suffered administrative costs relating to the need to find, hire, and administratively process new employees to replace Barnett and Dale. Noting that neither of the producers represented that they would work at Food Lion indefinitely and that they were at-will employees, the court held that Food Lion could not have reasonably relied to its detriment on the misrepresentations made by Barnett and Dale to secure their jobs.Footnote 102 Most importantly, because the punitive damages award was tied to the fraud claim, the invalidation of that claim meant that the $315,000 verdict on that part of the case was vacated.Footnote 103

Next, the Fourth Circuit reversed one of the two theories on which Food Lion’s trespass claim rested. As discussed earlier, the states are divided on the question of whether a person who induces a landowner’s consent to enter property by misrepresentation has committed a trespass. Food Lion asserted that such misrepresentation did vitiate its consent, but the Fourth Circuit disagreed. While noting that the Restatement states that consent induced by misrepresentation is not valid, the court nonetheless observed that “the various jurisdictions and authorities in this country are not of one mind in dealing with the issue.”Footnote 104

On this point, the Fourth Circuit followed the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit’s decision in Desnick v. American Broadcasting Companies, Inc.Footnote 105 In Desnick, a news station and its reporters conducted an undercover investigation by pretending to be patients in need of cataract surgeries to investigate an eye doctor who was reported to recommend such surgeries when they were not medically necessary. Though the reporters engaged in deception, the Seventh Circuit rejected the doctor’s claim that they had trespassed. In an opinion by Judge Posner, the court held that the reporters’ entry into a business that is open to customers is not a trespass because “consent to an entry is often given legal effect even though the entrant has intentions that if known to the owner of the property would cause him for perfectly understandable and generally ethical or at least lawful reasons to revoke his consent.”Footnote 106 The court noted that in such a case, “[t]here was no invasion … of any of the specific interests that the tort of trespass seeks to protect.”Footnote 107 But other federal courts have disagreed on this critical point.Footnote 108

But the appellate court’s decision was not a complete win for journalism. The Fourth Circuit upheld liability against Barnett and Dale on the duty of loyalty claim and on a distinct trespass theory. First, it concluded that under state law, the producers had violated the duty of loyalty. The Fourth Circuit conceded that under existing case law in North Carolina and South Carolina, the duty of loyalty had only been recognized where “an employee competes directly with her employer,” “the employee misappropriates her employer’s profits, property, or business opportunities,” or “an employee breaches her employer’s confidences,” none of which were true here.Footnote 109 Nevertheless, the court predicted that, if faced with the issue, the courts of those states would have found a violation of the duty of loyalty on these facts. As it explained:

The interests of the employer (ABC) to whom Dale and Barnett gave complete loyalty were adverse to the interests of Food Lion, the employer to whom they were unfaithful. ABC and Food Lion were not business competitors but they were adverse in a fundamental way. ABC’s interest was to expose Food Lion to the public as a food chain that engaged in unsanitary and deceptive practices. Dale and Barnett served ABC’s interest, at the expense of Food Lion, by engaging in the taping for ABC while they were on Food Lion’s payroll. In doing this, Dale and Barnett did not serve Food Lion faithfully, and their interest (which was the same as ABC’s) was diametrically opposed to Food Lion’s. In these circumstances, we believe that the highest courts of North and South Carolina would hold that the reporters – in promoting the interests of one master, ABC, to the detriment of a second, Food Lion – committed the tort of disloyalty against Food Lion.Footnote 110

The court also upheld the nominal damages verdicts against Dale and Barnett for trespass. Although it found that their initial entry on to Food Lion’s property through “resume fraud” was not a trespass in itself,Footnote 111 it concluded that a trespass occurs when “a wrongful act is done in excess of and in abuse of authorized entry.”Footnote 112 That wrongful act was the producers’ violation of the duty of loyalty. The Fourth Circuit thus bootstrapped the producers’ violation of the duty of loyalty as the requisite wrongful act that converted their initially consensual entry into a trespass. The overall outcome of the appeal was that only the two $1 nominal damages awards against both Dale and Barnett were ultimately upheld.

Furthermore, while the court reduced the defendants’ financial liability to almost nothing, it rejected their contention that the First Amendment protected the producers from even that liability because the suit was targeting them for engaging in behavior that was indisputably newsgathering. The Fourth Circuit disagreed with the defendants’ First Amendment arguments, noting that the Supreme Court has held on more than one occasion that journalists are not constitutionally entitled to exemption from generally applicable laws, even when they are engaged in newsgathering.Footnote 113 Neither the tort of trespass nor the duty of loyalty, it concluded, “targets or singles out the press.”Footnote 114

Moreover, it’s noteworthy that the litigation lasted nearly seven years and likely cost ABC several million dollars to defend. ABC is a national television news network with substantial assets, but the chilling effect of this level of litigation costs would likely be more than enough to give pause to a local newspaper or television station that might have otherwise hoped to conduct an undercover investigation. In this way, litigation by the targets of undercover investigations has deterrent effects similar to those created by the prospect of costly defamation claims. Notwithstanding that in defamation cases, journalists have the extra First Amendment protection from New York Times Co. v. SullivanFootnote 115 and may ultimately prevail in most cases, the litigation costs alone may shape journalists’ decisions about what to investigate and what to publish.

Without some constitutional protection for undercover newsgathering, an important vehicle for facilitating the discovery and disclosure of information vital to democracy may be forever lost. Although some recent lower court decisions have offered hope for the development of some type of First Amendment privilege, other cases seem to foreclose that possibility. In the next part, I argue that Food Lion and its shadow have deterred journalists from engaging in employment-based undercover investigations. And I make a preliminary case for reconsidering Food Lion under certain conditions.

14.2.3 Food Lion’s Legal Deterrent Effect

Despite a seemingly good outcome and the relatively benign impact of nominal damages awards, Food Lion continues to have a chilling effect on undercover investigations. Its ruling on the duty of loyalty has more significant effects than it might at first seem. This is particularly so because many consider employment-based undercover investigations to be the most effective type of undercover investigations because they permit investigators to access people and places beyond the eyes of the general public.Footnote 116

First, although the Food Lion court did not directly accept the argument that consent to enter property induced by deception is a trespass, that area of the law continues to evolve. Courts upholding Ag Gag laws have been generally sympathetic to states’ claims that gaining access or employment to private property by deception interferes with the government interest in preventing trespass.Footnote 117 The plaintiffs in these cases have argued that although gaining access to private property by consent induced by false statements is a trespass under some states’ laws, the trespass harm in cases of investigators is de minimis and therefore does not constitute the type of legally cognizable harm that Alvarez contemplates. While some courts that have struck down Ag Gag laws have agreed,Footnote 118 others have decided the cases without addressing that specific argument.Footnote 119 This leaves that important legal question in limbo.

Even if the trespass theory asserted by investigative targets were to be ultimately rejected, Food Lion’s interpretation of the duty of loyalty may make that irrelevant. Recall that the Fourth Circuit ruled that even a person who has received the landowner’s consent to enter property as an employee may subsequently be engaged in a trespass if they breach the duty of loyalty by committing a wrongful act in excess of their authority to enter the premises.Footnote 120 The wrongful act, according to the court, was the act of “filming in non-public areas … adverse to Food Lion.”Footnote 121 But that describes virtually every single person who conducts an employment-based undercover investigation, thus exposing them to trespass liability via their inevitable violation (in the Fourth Circuit’s view) of the duty of loyalty. Thus, the $1 verdicts notwithstanding, the impact of this part of the holding cannot be overstated. Undercover investigators always engage in deception when they conduct an employment-based investigation. They must lie or obscure their true identity, the sponsor of their investigation, and their motives whenever they try to get a job in this situation. The Fourth Circuit’s conclusion that this constitutes a trespass when their subsequent conduct breaches the duty of loyalty effectively reverses its holding that “resume fraud” does not constitute a trespass. It also effectively undermines its earlier conclusion that consent to enter property induced by misrepresentation does not constitute a trespass. This seems to slice the onion a little too thin.

Similarly, even if Alvarez is ultimately interpreted to allow First Amendment protection for investigative deception, Food Lion’s conclusion about the duty of loyalty would render that pro-speech holding a nullity. According to the Fourth Circuit, the duty of loyalty is breached not by “resume fraud” but by the very fact that the employee is simultaneously working for the sponsor of the investigation and its target.Footnote 122 Thus, under any interpretation of Alvarez’s “offers of employment” dictum, under Food Lion, the breach of the duty of loyalty would still represent a legally cognizable harm.

It is not surprising, therefore, that Food Lion’s trial strategy was to focus on Barnett and Dale’s supposed acts of disloyalty. Both before and during the trial, Food Lion’s lawyers attempted to portray Barnett and Dale as having staged some parts of the report that showed food sanitation or handling problems.Footnote 123 One incident described in the report was about a meat grinder that was not cleaned before the store closed one night, and that employees simply began using the uncleaned equipment the next day. Food Lion lawyers suggested that this was misleading, falsely alleging that Dale had sabotaged the store’s water heater so that it would be unavailable for cleaning – a charge that was later found by the jury to be untrue.Footnote 124 Siegel reported that the focus of Food Lion’s trial strategy was based on these “pseudo-staging allegations,” attempting to show that Barnett and Dale were not only failing to do their jobs as Food Lion employees but also actively interfering with Food Lion’s operations.Footnote 125 In a pretrial ruling, the district court found that allegations of “staging” were relevant to Food Lion’s duty of loyalty claim, but those staging claims were later ruled inadmissible by the judge, who found they had no merit.Footnote 126

To be sure, it isn’t clear that Food Lion is even correct that the duty of loyalty applies in this context. First, the Fourth Circuit appears to have been incorrect even as a matter of state law. Just two years after Food Lion was decided, the North Carolina Supreme Court held that the district court in Food Lion had “incorrectly interpreted our state case law” and that “although our state courts recognize the existence of an employee’s duty of loyalty, we do not recognize its breach as an independent claim.”Footnote 127 Moreover, in many jurisdictions that do recognize a duty of loyalty cause of action, liability turns on whether the employee has a fiduciary duty to the employer.Footnote 128 As previously discussed, most undercover investigators take lower level, at-will employment jobs, which are generally not entrusted with the type of duties from which a fiduciary relationship is created.Footnote 129

Furthermore, the Supreme Court has rejected this same type of agency law claim when directed at another type of undercover investigator. In N.L.R.B. v. Town & Country Electric, Inc.,Footnote 130 the Court considered an employer’s claim that an employee who was also a paid union organizer was not an “employee” within the meaning of the National Labor Relations Act. In doing so, the employer invoked the common law of agency, which it maintained prohibited a person from simultaneously serving “two masters,” the union and the employer.Footnote 131 But the Court disagreed with the employer’s argument, concluding that the common law did not prohibit this particular type of disloyalty. In an opinion by Justice Breyer, the Court stated that it is a “hornbook rule” that a “person may be the servant of two masters … at one time as to one act, if the service to one does not involve abandonment of service to the other.”Footnote 132 That seems to be the case with the investigation in Food Lion. In rejecting Food Lion’s claim that it should recover the wages it paid to Barnett and Dale, the Fourth Circuit observed that:

Dale and Barnett were paid because they showed up for work and performed their assigned tasks as Food Lion employees. Their performance was at a level suitable to their status as new, entry-level employees. Indeed, shortly before Dale quit, her supervisor said she would “make a good meat wrapper.” And, when Barnett quit, her supervisor recommended that she be rehired if she sought reemployment with Food Lion in the future.Footnote 133

Thus, it would appear that Barnett and Dale’s work for ABC did not “involve abandonment of service to” Food Lion. Notwithstanding this conclusion on damages, however, the court found that “it is possible to perform the assigned tasks of a job adequately and still breach the duty of loyalty.”Footnote 134

14.2.4 Food Lion’s Influence on Journalism Ethics

But Food Lion’s deterrent effect on undercover investigations derives not only from its status as a legal precedent but also because it has significantly influenced debates about the ethics of undercover investigations in the journalism profession. In recent years, there has been extensive criticism of undercover journalism from within the profession, with many claiming that the tactics necessary to carry out a successful undercover investigation demean the profession and undermine its credibility. Unlike other professions, journalism does not have a state licensing scheme, which would be severely problematic for freedoms of the press because it would grant the government too much control over journalists and might even be viewed as a form of prior restraint. But in other professions, ethical standards are set by professional licensing institutions. In journalism, each individual news institution, whether it be a newspaper or television network, sets its own internal ethical standards. While there are ethical codes published by professional journalism organizations, they are not binding. Ethical decisions are therefore decentralized, leaving substantial room for disagreement.

With regard to undercover investigations, this disagreement has been manifest. While some journalists defend undercover investigations as a critical tool for newsgathering, particularly to discover information that would not otherwise see the light of day, others argue that journalistic honesty cannot have exceptions and that truth is a central tenet of what it means to be a journalist. As Justin Marceau and I have written about extensively, this debate largely turns on the different schools of thought about the foundations of journalism ethics.Footnote 135 But the debate among journalists continues and is likely to persist.

While I cannot identify any empirical data or systematic examination of Food Lion’s impact on undercover investigations, there is a fair amount of anecdotal evidence that it has influenced the journalism ethics debate. First, as the quote from the beginning of this chapter suggests, in contemporary times, print newspapers have shown a great reluctance to undertake such investigations. Many of them have well-publicized ethical codes that forbid their employees from engaging in deception or using hidden cameras in their newsgathering.Footnote 136 It is unclear exactly when these codes went into effect, but my prior research suggests that the emergence of general professional objections to undercover investigations began in the late 1990s, roughly coinciding with the Food Lion decision.Footnote 137 For example, the Society of Professional Journalists (SPJ) first addressed undercover investigations explicitly in its 1996 revision to its Code of Ethics.Footnote 138 The prior 1973 version of SPJ’s Code of Ethics does not mention undercover investigations,Footnote 139 but the 1996 revision states that journalists should “Avoid undercover or other surreptitious methods of gathering information except when traditional open methods will not yield information vital to the public” and further advises that “Use of such methods should be explained as part of the story.”Footnote 140

Indeed, the Food Lion company itself tried to expand the reach of its courtroom victory by trying to influence university journalism curriculums.Footnote 141 In a highly controversial effort, shortly after the Fourth Circuit’s decision, Food Lion prepared materials about the case and sent them to around 200 journalism professors around the country.Footnote 142 “The grocery chain’s educational kit included a self-produced report, ‘Fakes, Lies and Videotape,’ and a 15-minute video prepared by a public relations firm, which uses unaired ABC footage to support the company’s contention that ABC’s report was untrue.”Footnote 143 The company also apparently engaged a journalism professor to assist them in their efforts.Footnote 144 It is unclear what, if any, influence Food Lion’s propaganda efforts had on journalism curricula, and many journalism faculty were quite skeptical about the effort. One professor noted that the materials prioritized Food Lion’s viewpoint but did not provide the counterpoint from ABC’s perspective that the investigation was consistent with journalism philosophy and norms.Footnote 145

There is also anecdotal evidence from commentators about Food Lion’s impact on undercover investigations. Seth Stern, advocacy director for the Freedom of the Press Foundation, recently observed a drop in undercover investigations. As he noted, the Food Lion case has been “often presented to young journalists as a cautionary tale,” and “the landmark case significantly slowed the once relatively common practice of ‘undercover’ journalism.”Footnote 146 Notwithstanding the fact that Food Lion ultimately resulted in only nominal damages, Stern suggested that the case made lawyers recognize a substantial risk of “punitive damages based on newsgathering methods.”Footnote 147 He suggested that because of the Food Lion case, many mainstream news outlets stopped engaging in hidden-camera and other undercover investigations.Footnote 148 As Stern observed, “There’s no telling how many stories the public missed out on as a result of the changes to journalism – both legal and cultural – brought about by Food Lion.”Footnote 149

My interviews with the ABC producers and lawyer in the Food Lion case support Stern’s observations and provide anecdotal support for my theory that employment-based investigations are decreasing. Although Susan Barnett and Lynne Dale went on to conduct multiple undercover investigations with different national television networks after the Food Lion case concluded, neither of them has done one requiring them to secure a job with the investigation’s target.Footnote 150 Dale reported that “we couldn’t get a job. That was off the table and had been off the table ever since Food Lion sued us.”Footnote 151 Similarly, media lawyer Nathan Siegel, who represented Barnett, Dale, and ABC during the Food Lion litigation, confirmed that there have been very few “undercover investigations since [Food Lion] that have turned on actually obtaining employment.”Footnote 152

Stern observed that not only have major journalism companies steered away from undercover investigations, but also that such investigations are “now often associated with fringe (and often disreputable) platforms,”Footnote 153 such as the far-right activist group Project Veritas. In response, he suggests that more mainstream journalists should (after consulting with lawyers) seize this tactic back from such groups, noting that the Fourth Circuit’s recent favorable decision in People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals v. North Carolina Farm Bureau FederationFootnote 154 could be a catalyst.Footnote 155

Another commentator has also framed the debate against the backdrop of groups with questionable credibility, but, unlike Stern, argues that the influence moves in the other direction. Erik Wemple, The Washington Post’s media critic, has argued that the fringe groups’ efforts to use undercover investigation have proven that the tactics are dishonorable.Footnote 156 Wemple wrote that before James O’Keefe established Project Veritas in 2011, “American journalists were falling out of love with undercover tactics – a breakup aided by Food Lion’s 1995 suit against ABC News for its clandestine exposé on the grocery behemoth’s unsavory meat-handling practices.”Footnote 157

Wemple goes on to say that “Mainstream outlets, accordingly, have spent the past couple of decades either swearing off undercover work or narrowing the circumstances when it’s warranted.”Footnote 158 He continued:

Project Veritas must not have been spending enough time reading Poynter.org for ethics guidance. “Especially since the Food Lion misrepresentation and hidden-camera stuff, news organizations don’t do the [full range]” of clandestine tactics, “where they put them all together at the same time,” says Lee Levine, a longtime First Amendment attorney. Contemporary examples of undercover stories are harder and harder to come by these days, says Levine – and even in the years when the practice was tapering off, he continues, news organizations that did embrace it were “very careful not to lie.”Footnote 159

14.3 Reconsidering Food Lion
14.3.1 Legal Hurdles to Reconsidering Food Lion

The case for reconsidering Food Lion must begin with some existing barriers under current First Amendment doctrine. As has long been documented and criticized, the Supreme Court has never recognized a substantive constitutional right for the press distinct from the First Amendment right of free speech.Footnote 160 Notwithstanding the First Amendment’s text, which specifically establishes a freedom of the press, the Court has ignored this and held that the press’s rights are coextensive with the rights recognized under the Speech Clause.Footnote 161 Even in cases where the Court has recognized important freedoms for the press, such as in cases holding that the First Amendment embodies a right to access certain types of criminal proceedings in court, those rights have been understood as belonging to the public, not to the press per se.Footnote 162

Furthermore, to date, the Court has consistently held that journalists are not entitled to exemptions from generally applicable criminal and civil laws, even if the enforcement of such laws directly impairs critical press functions.Footnote 163 More specifically, the Supreme Court has never recognized in any type of First Amendment right for journalists or others to protect them from laws or government action that inhibits their newsgathering. In Branzburg v. Hayes, the Court rejected the First Amendment claims of journalists who sought an exemption from testifying before grand juries and disclosing their confidential sources.Footnote 164 The reporters involved in that case argued that revealing their sources in grand jury proceedings would undermine their ability to engage in newsgathering because such sources would no longer trust that their identities would remain secret. While they did not seek an absolute privilege from grand jury subpoenas, the reporters argued that journalists should not be compelled to testify unless the State showed “sufficient grounds … for believing that the reporter possesses information relevant to a crime the grand jury is investigating, that the information the reporter has is unavailable from other sources, and that the need for the information is sufficiently compelling to override the claimed invasion of First Amendment interests occasioned by the disclosure.”Footnote 165

Rejecting the journalists’ privilege claim, the Supreme Court noted that the Constitution does not call for treating journalists differently from the average citizen, who must appear before a grand jury and testify when subpoenaed, even if the relevant information they have was obtained in confidence.Footnote 166 Key to the Court’s reasoning was its concern that journalists not be permitted to be exempt from every “incidental” burden on their professional work from generally applicable laws.Footnote 167 While the Court stated it was not holding that newsgathering does not qualify for First Amendment protection, it did not articulate when such protection would be available and has not done so in the fifty years since it decided Branzburg.Footnote 168

The Court also declared that members of the press are not exempt from generally applicable laws in Cohen v. Cowles Media Co.Footnote 169 In Cohen, a confidential source sued a newspaper for breach of contract and misrepresentation after it published a story disclosing the source’s identity. The newspaper asserted a First Amendment privilege, arguing that it should not be subject to liability for the publication of truthful information that is lawfully obtained.Footnote 170 While the Court accepted that proposition in the abstract, it held that “generally applicable laws do not offend the First Amendment simply because their enforcement against the press has incidental effects on its ability to gather and report the news … The press may not with impunity break and enter an office or dwelling to gather news.”Footnote 171

These precedents would seem to present insurmountable barriers to the recognition of even a limited privilege for undercover investigations. But while they may set the baseline for claims to be exempt from otherwise generally applicable laws, there is nonetheless still room to assert some privileges. First, notwithstanding Branzburg’s holding, many lower federal courts have subsequently recognized a “qualified privilege” permitting journalists to refuse disclosure of confidential sources if potential negative impact on newsgathering outweighs the public’s need for the information.Footnote 172 These courts seem to have taken to heart Branzburg’s recognition that the First Amendment provides “some protection” for newsgathering.Footnote 173 Nor is Cowles’s seemingly categorical rejection of a press exemption from generally applicable laws a complete bar to some constitutional protection for newsgathering. In some recent cases, lower courts have held that statutes that apply to a range of conduct are not exempt from First Amendment scrutiny where those statutes are applied to speech.Footnote 174

14.3.2 The Shape of a Legal Privilege for Undercover Investigations

A legal privilege to engage in investigative deception and secret recordings to gather information on matters of public concern might be established by the Supreme Court as part of the First Amendment’s Speech Clause or Press Clause. If the Court is unwilling to do so, such a privilege could be created at the local level by state supreme courts interpreting and applying their own speech and press clauses. Finally, as has occurred with shield laws that protect journalists from being compelled to disclose confidential sources, it could happen through state legislatures. The following sections discuss my proposal for possible ways to construct such a privilege.

14.3.2.1 Unconditional Privilege with Industry Self-regulation

If courts or legislatures were to recognize a newsgatherer’s privilege to engage in deception and secret recording to conduct undercover investigations, one approach they could take is to make it an unconditional privilege, but rely on the news media’s practice of self-regulation in other areas of press freedom in which broader public interests counsel against publication.Footnote 175 Despite the fact that news outlets are incentivized to pursue high circulation, ratings, and profits, the press counterbalances that demand with other concerns, such as maintaining credibility with its audience.Footnote 176

One might reject an approach relying on industry self-regulation on the grounds that it insufficiently protects against the potential invasion of property, privacy, and loyalty interests that undercover investigations are said to compromise. But in several areas, the journalism profession has engaged in self-regulation and resisted publication of newsworthy information that may technically be published without restriction because such publication is protected by the First Amendment. For example, at least where the media obtain the information from publicly available sources, the Supreme Court has established that the news media may publish the names of crime victims.Footnote 177 Yet it is recognized that because of internal ethics standards, the vast majority of media outlets generally do not report such information.Footnote 178 Similarly, self-regulation in journalism typically means that, despite the newsworthiness of these matters, the press does not report the names of juveniles involved in judicial proceedings, the results of presidential elections prior to the polls closing in western time zones, and information that might compromise national security interests.Footnote 179

Relying on the journalism profession to self-regulate regarding undercover investigations may not, however, accomplish the goal of expanding such investigations because there is substantial and ongoing disagreement about the ethics of such investigations among the American media.Footnote 180 Many major newspapers prohibit their reporters from conducting undercover investigations regardless of whether there is any legal protection for such conduct.Footnote 181 However, the recognition of a constitutional or other legal privilege to engage in deception and secret recording might influence the internal professional standards that prohibit such conduct.

Another significant disadvantage of the unconditional privilege coupled with industry self-regulation is that it relies on professional standards that may not be generally accepted outside of the institutional news media. That is, it might limit the privilege to only those in the newsgathering profession and thereby exclude undercover investigators working with nonprofit organizations to support their political advocacy. By definition, those groups and their investigators would not be bound by the standards of professional journalism. Some would argue that this is a feature, not a bug, of a profession-based standard – under this view, the trade-off necessary to recognize a privilege that outweighs other legal interests, such as trespass or the duty of loyalty, can only be justified if that privilege is limited to those who agree to be bound by the journalism profession’s ethical standards and are therefore professionally accountable. While I acknowledge this concern, the cost of a privilege limited to professional journalists would be the loss of information that might otherwise be uncovered through undercover investigations by non-journalists. And, as I argue below, ethical considerations may be accounted for by conditioning the privilege on adherence to a set of best practices, without regard to the identity of the investigator.

This version of the privilege would also arguably not apply to the increasingly common practices of citizen journalists, who are also not technically governed by professional journalistic standards. It is for this reason that I have previously argued that constitutional protection for undercover investigations be grounded in the Speech Clause rather than the Press Clause.Footnote 182 But recognizing a Press Clause privilege in this form would at the very least ensure the protection of important undercover investigations by the professional news media.Footnote 183

14.3.2.2 Conditional Privilege

An alternative model that courts or legislatures could consider is establishing a newsgatherers’ privilege to be exempt from criminal or civil liability for engaging in undercover investigative tactics conditioned on two distinct grounds. First, it would only apply to the extent the person conducting the investigation is involved in newsgathering activities. Second, the privilege would apply only where investigators have adhered to a set of best practices or ethical norms that would safeguard against intrusion on some of the interests that would otherwise be promoted by enforcement of such laws.

The newsgathering limitation would provide some flexibility to courts examining a First Amendment newsgathering defense in criminal or civil litigation because it would permit them to reject the enforcement of such laws only as applied to newsgathering. There is obviously nothing unconstitutional about a generally applicable law requiring employees to be loyal (however defined) to their employers. But it is equally obvious, I think, that when employers dust off this tort to be used only when they have been the target of an undercover investigation, some First Amendment scrutiny should be applied.

In one of the most recent Ag Gag cases, the Fourth Circuit invalidated North Carolina’s Property Protection Act, which created a new private right of action for employers to sue employees who entered “nonpublic areas of an employer’s premises,” captured the employer’s data, paper, records, or other documents or recording images or sound occurring within that premises, and used that information “to breach the person’s duty of loyalty to the employer.”Footnote 184 The law was challenged as unconstitutional on its face and as applied to animal rights investigators and others who wished to get jobs and disclose wrongdoing by their employers. The Fourth Circuit, however, invalidated the statute only as applied to the newsgathering activities of the animal rights organizations who challenged the law.Footnote 185 This is somewhat similar to a standard that Ashutosh Bhagwat has proposed. He has argued that while content-neutral regulations of the production of speech “are presumptively constitutional on their face,” they “may be challenged as applied to speech that contributes in some substantial way to democratic self-governance.”Footnote 186

This condition has the further advantage of applying the privilege to any person engaged in legitimate newsgathering activities, rather than just professional journalists. As described in much of my other work, undercover investigations by political groups contribute to public discourse in ways that are comparable to those conducted by members of the press.Footnote 187 If we conceptualized the privilege as grounded in the Speech Clause, it would apply to all investigators. And even if the protection was located in the Press Clause, that Clause has sometimes been understood to protect the actions of people who undertook their actions with the intent to disseminate the information they obtained to the public, rather than to a particular class of professional journalists.Footnote 188

The best practices condition would, like the newsgathering condition, allow the privilege to extend to both professional journalists and others, so long as the investigations adhere to best practices. Thus, civil rights investigators, animal rights activists, and labor organizers could assert the privilege even though they are not affiliated with the institutional press.

In our recent book on undercover investigations, Justin Marceau and I articulate a set of such practices.Footnote 189 Under our model, undercover investigations should follow several protocols as a safeguard against investigations that are unimportant, unnecessary, or overly intrusive. These standards are set forth in greater detail in our book, but a basic summary should suffice for the purposes of this chapter. First, the investigators must have “specific evidence” that an undercover investigation will “reveal misconduct, illegality, or wrongdoing on the part of [the] investigation’s target” and should be limited to seeking information on matters of public concern.Footnote 190 Next, the information should not be otherwise available, or not available at a sufficiently detailed level, through more conventional sources.Footnote 191 Deception, including affirmative misrepresentation about “the investigator’s identity, political affiliations, and motivations for gaining access to the investigation site” should be permissible, but only for the purpose of conducting the investigation.Footnote 192 Where an investigation is employment based, “the investigator should not exaggerate or inflate their credentials” and “must be able to competently perform their assigned job functions.”Footnote 193 Additionally, any secret recording “must be reproduced truthfully in reports to the public. No alterations or editing to mislead the listener or viewer are permissible,” although editing for “brevity, coherence, and to protect the privacy interests of the individuals recorded is permissible.”Footnote 194 Investigators must not “cause physical harm, theft (including intellectual property), or other harms to the property of the investigation’s target or to any person on the premises during the investigation” and should not “induce, solicit, or entrap others to engage in misconduct.”Footnote 195 Finally, investigators should not “deprive individuals who are associated with the investigation site of their dignity, privacy, or autonomy unless that is the direct result of those individuals’ participation in the suspected misconduct being investigated,” and investigations involving access to “commercial properties are preferable to investigations that involve access to private homes or spaces.”Footnote 196

Conditioning the privilege on compliance with these best practices has a couple of advantages. First, and probably most importantly, it substantially limits the possibility that any such investigation will cause the types of tangible harms that are the basis of criminal and civil regulations of deception and secret recording. Thus, while it does not completely discount those potential harms, it uses them to define the limits of the privilege. Second, imposing this set of conditions on the exercise of the privilege means that the privilege can extend to both professional journalists and non-journalists who are careful to adhere to these standards.

14.3.3 Addressing Concerns About an Undercover Investigations Privilege

There are, of course, many potential objections to the recognition of a newsgatherers’ privilege for undercover investigations. First, skeptics might argue that recognizing even a limited privilege would open the door to additional claims of privilege to violate other generally applicable laws. If undercover investigations are privileged, why shouldn’t journalists be permitted to violate laws against breaking and entering into spaces where information of public concern can be found? And why wouldn’t such privilege also extend to journalists who engage in computer hacking, accessing private databases to troll for information hidden on a company’s hard drive?

The interests compromised by break-ins and computer hacking, however, are far more tangible than those at stake in undercover investigations. The paradox of undercover investigations is that they take place secretly, but also in the open. In contrast to physical break-ins or computer hacks, in undercover investigations, the target knows that someone is observing questionable behavior on their property; they are just unaware of that person’s true identity or motives. While investigative targets may claim that their rights are being violated because the trust they place in the investigator has been violated, the expectation of privacy in such a situation is much lower or, in some cases, may be nonexistent. Professor Marceau and I have argued elsewhere that this reduced expectation of privacy is analogous to the third-party doctrine in criminal procedure. As we observed, “in talking to other persons or inviting them into parts of your life, one always assumes the risk that the person might turn out to be a reporter, a cop, or some other form of false friend.”Footnote 197 The same violation of trust might also arise with a current employee who engages in whistleblowing.Footnote 198 In other words, unlike with burglary or hacking, targets of undercover investigations assume the risk that the behavior they freely engage in while another person is present will later be revealed to others.

Another concern is that granting of legal permission for undercover investigations will lead to a massive expansion of such investigations, many of which may exceed the scope of legitimate newsgathering and result in serious privacy invasions and interference with businesses’ ability to maintain a functioning workplace. The fear is that the recognition of a legal privilege would create a kind of atmosphere in which newsgatherers recklessly conduct undercover investigations as fishing expeditions hoping to find something worth reporting. There are a couple of natural impediments, however, to such a massive expansion. First, some news outlets are likely to retain their internal ethical prohibitions against their employees engaging in the type of conduct necessary to carry out an undercover investigation. As the ethical debates reflect, some journalists and media companies are viscerally opposed to undercover journalism.Footnote 199 Although I strongly disagree with this approach and hope that the recognition of a privilege would influence those beliefs, individual news entities may still decide to act more conservatively if they so choose.

Second, as reflected by the details of the Food Lion investigation,Footnote 200 properly conducting undercover investigations requires enormous resources. Investigations are complex, time consuming, and demand a large number of personnel hours for background reporting, planning, conducting the investigation, post-investigation researching, and producing and editing the story that goes out to the public. This type of investigation cannot be undertaken lightly, even by a national news network. It is accordingly unlikely that recognition of a privilege will open the floodgates to an unreasonable number of new investigations.

Moreover, there are serious personal costs to journalists. The work is stressful. Barnett and Dale recounted their fear of being discovered by Food Lion employees during their undercover investigations. For example, Barnett recalled an instance when she was working at a Food Lion delicatessen. While instructing her, Barnett’s supervisor “patted me on the stomach to show me how you kind of put the sandwich next to your stomach and you roll it in the Saran wrap. Anyway, when she patted my stomach, she hit [recording] gear. And I remember just catching my breath at that moment.”Footnote 201

Undercover journalists can also suffer serious physical burdens. During the Food Lion investigation, the producers had to carry heavy equipment concealed under bulky clothing. This was physically taxing, so much so that Barnett threw out her back from wearing the recording equipment while trying to do her Food Lion job.Footnote 202 Today, technology has developed so that cameras can be hidden in something the size of a button, alleviating the bulk problem. But there were also specific hazards from the large battery packs necessary to supply the hidden cameras with power. Dale suffered severe burns from the battery she was carrying, something she could not do anything about until the end of her shift.Footnote 203 The extent to which this problem has been alleviated by technology is less clear. These physical challenges can not only create a risk of physical harm but also significantly increase the chances that journalists will be discovered.

14.4 Conclusion

For a relatively narrow, mostly pro-press freedom opinion, the Fourth Circuit’s decision in Food Lion has had a continuing and long-lasting deterrent effect on undercover investigations, both as a legal precedent and as an influence on journalists’ ethical debates about such tactics. Its invocation of the relatively obscure common law duty of loyalty in some ways supersedes the importance of the law of undercover investigations that has developed since it was decided. Repudiating Food Lion and recognizing a limited form of newsgatherer’s privilege for undercover investigations would be a useful reform that could restore an important journalistic tradition that has frequently led to the discovery and publication of information critical to public discourse and, in turn, to our democracy. At a time when many external and internal impediments already threaten the future of press freedom, perhaps taking this narrow but important step toward expanding the ability to engage in newsgathering could move the law in a promising direction.

15 The Enduring Significance of New York Times v. Sullivan

One of the Supreme Court’s most significant First Amendment rulings may be in peril. For the past sixty years, the landmark 1964 decision of New York Times Co. v. Sullivan and the cases that followed have secured strong First Amendment protections for the press and others who speak on public affairs. Under these cases, public officials and public figures must show that the speaker acted with “actual malice” or “reckless disregard” of the truth in order to win a libel suit.Footnote 1 Scholars and advocates have long celebrated Sullivan as one of the most important Supreme Court rulings for the protection of press freedom.

But in 2016, then-presidential candidate Donald Trump announced that he wanted to “open up” libel lawsFootnote 2 to make it easier for him to sue his critics in the press.Footnote 3 Since then, attacks on Sullivan have taken on a new – and highly partisan – tenor. In 2017, former Republican vice-presidential candidate Sarah Palin brought a high-profile defamation case against The New York Times in which she called Sullivan “obsolete in the modern speech landscape.”Footnote 4 Soon after, two Supreme Court justices, Clarence Thomas and Neil Gorsuch, urged the Court to reconsider Sullivan and its progeny.Footnote 5 Judge Laurence H. Silberman of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit agreed, penning a sharply worded dissent that called for the Court to overrule Sullivan, declaring that the press is “bias[ed] against the Republican Party” and stating that The New York Times and The Washington Post “are virtually Democratic Party broadsheets.”Footnote 6 A number of other litigants have also asked the Court to take a new look at Sullivan’s holdings, arguing that the ruling insufficiently protects the interest in personal reputation and awards the purportedly biased, liberal press with an unwarranted “subsidy” for untruthful publications.Footnote 7

Any reconsideration of Sullivan and its legacy, however, must not be done in a historical vacuum. The story of Sullivan is a powerful illustration of the unique functions the press fulfills in American democracy and the importance of Sullivan’s protections of those functions. The history of Sullivan demonstrates how, when provided with sufficient constitutional protections, the press embodies key democracy-enhancing roles, such as reporting on public affairs, transmitting newsworthy information to the public, monitoring the conduct of public officials, and holding officials accountable to the citizenry. Arising out of the Civil Rights Movement, the history of Sullivan also shows us how a free press can serve as a voice for underrepresented groups and shine light on matters of importance that might otherwise go unseen.

Yet, as this chapter demonstrates, this history also lays bare the high stakes of losing the First Amendment protections recognized in Sullivan. Prior to the Court’s ruling in Sullivan, government officials and other public figures routinely weaponized libel laws to suppress their critics, particularly members of the press. Journalists were arrested and assaulted. Major newspapers pulled their reporters out of the sites of ongoing public battles, leaving the public in the dark about significant newsworthy events. Libel law, to use Justice William Brennan’s words in Sullivan, had a silencing, “chilling” effect on press.Footnote 8 This chapter uses history to explain how and why Sullivan nearly eliminated those overwhelming threats to the press. If New York Times Co. v. Sullivan and related cases are overruled, libel suits could again become weapons of blatant political suppression.

15.1 Libel and the Press

Libel is a civil cause of action that protects personal reputation against false and defamatory statements. A defamatory statement is one that seriously lowers a person’s reputation; it exposes a person “to hatred, shame, obloquy, contumely, odium, contempt, ridicule, aversion, ostracism, degradation or disgrace [and] deprives one of their confidence and friendly intercourse in society.”Footnote 9 It “injures [a person] in his profession or trade, [and] causes him to be shunned or avoided by his neighbors.”Footnote 10

Before 1964, a person who sued for libel didn’t have to prove that the statement in question was false; rather, falsity was presumed. The plaintiff didn’t have to show actual injury to their reputation, only that the statement had the potential to harm their reputation. Libel was judged under the rule of strict liability, meaning that a publisher was responsible for its statements regardless of the publisher’s intent or state of mind at the time of publishing. The only ways a publisher could defend itself were by proving that the statement fell into one of a few narrow categories of statements that were “privileged,” legally justified or excused, or, more commonly, by proving the truth of the statement “in all its particulars.”Footnote 11 Truth was a complete defense to libel, but as a practical matter, proving the truth of a statement “in all its particulars” was difficult even if the statement was true. Prior to 1964, the Supreme Court had said repeatedly that defamation law did not implicate the First Amendment. Defamatory speech had no redeeming social value, the Court said, and its regulation could be left wholly to the states.Footnote 12

Under these rules, publishing criticism – even truthful criticism – of public officials was a dangerous undertaking for a newspaper. Public officials routinely saddled their critics in the press with libel claims (claims that would today be considered meritless), often recovering considerable damage awards. Libel lawsuits against newspapers were a regular feature of American politics prior to the 1960s. Political officials and other powerful figures frequently harassed and intimidated their critics in the press through retaliatory libel suits. At the turn of the century, for example, railroad magnate James Fisk sued The Springfield Republican for $100,000, followed by lawsuits against two other newspapers for the same sum and a third claiming $1 million in damages. In 1916, Henry Ford brought a spurious lawsuit against the Chicago Tribune for calling him an “ignorant idealist” and an “anarchist.”Footnote 13 Presidents even sued the press. In 1916, former President Theodore Roosevelt brought claims against a Michigan newspaper that accused him of being a drunk.Footnote 14 Libel lawsuits sent the muckraking newspaper The New York World, published by Joseph Pulitzer, into bankruptcy in the early twentieth century. Fear of devastating libel suits led editors to routinely hold back critical commentary about public officials. Under the law at the time, a newspaper could only be sure of escaping a libel suit when the facts were entirely confirmable “in every detail.”Footnote 15

Despite strict libel laws and the risk of being sued, some major press outlets, such as The New York Times, did find ways to publish. The Times used specialized lawyers and conducted extensive fact-checking and vetting procedures, reviewing all copy for possible libel.Footnote 16 As a result of its aggressive tactics and well-trained lawyers, The Times rarely paid out judgments in libel cases. But few newspapers had the financial and legal muscle of The Times. And libel remained a formidable latent threat, even for The Times.

As I describe in my book Actual Malice: Civil Rights and Freedom of the Press in New York Times v. Sullivan, libel suits almost destroyed The Times in the 1960s, when officials in the South figured out how to weaponize libel law to attack newspapers that criticized segregation and exposed official violence against civil rights protesters. This “libel attack” on the press, which produced a series of lawsuits, including the Sullivan case, illustrated how libel law could be exploited by vengeful public officials. It demonstrated to the Supreme Court, and the public more generally, how existing libel laws were anathema to the robust public discourse on public affairs that is the “central meaning” of the First Amendment.

15.2 The Attack on the Northern Press

The South’s libel attack on the northern press was a blatant attempt to halt media criticism of segregation and press coverage of the Civil Rights Movement more generally. The libel attack grew out of the southern campaign of “massive resistance,” its defiance of the Supreme Court’s 1954 decision in Brown v. Board of Education.Footnote 17 Segregationists feared the power of the press, and its power to sway public opinion toward integration and civil rights, with good reason. Media coverage of civil rights protests, and the violent backlash those protests generated, would prove critically important in building national support for civil rights that would lead to the Civil Rights Act of 1964. Images of civil rights activists being attacked by police and pictures of protesters being ejected from segregated lunch counters would illuminate the cruelties of the South’s racial system and the courage of those who defied it.Footnote 18

The catalyst to the libel suit at issue in Sullivan was the lunch counter sit-in movement that took off in the South in 1960. When sit-in protesters in Montgomery, Alabama, were assaulted by white mobs, Public Affairs Commissioner L. B. Sullivan, who supervised the police, did nothing to stop the attack. Shortly after, a civil rights organization called the Committee to Defend Martin Luther King and the Struggle for Freedom in the South published a full-page fundraising advertisement in The Times, titled Heed Their Rising Voices, which accused officials in Montgomery and other southern cities of inflicting violence on civil rights protesters. The ad was endorsed by sixty-four eminent figures in the arts and politics, whose names appeared on the ad. Also listed at the bottom of the ad were the names of twenty ministers who were leaders of King’s civil rights organization, the Southern Christian Leadership Conference. In reality, the ministers hadn’t endorsed the ad; their names were added at the last minute by the Committee to Defend Martin Luther King.Footnote 19 This advertisement would form the basis of the Sullivan case.

The ad, it turned out, contained minor errors of fact. For example, it incorrectly reported the names of the songs protesters had sung on the steps of the Capitol in Montgomery. The most serious error was the claim that officials in Montgomery had padlocked the dining hall of the Alabama State College to starve and punish the protesters, which wasn’t true.Footnote 20 The Times hadn’t fact-checked the ad before running it and thus had failed to adhere to its own well-established policy of vetting all copy for accuracy. Although Sullivan wasn’t mentioned by name in the ad, he claimed that he’d been defamed by statements in the ad implicating Montgomery “authorities” and “police” in violence against civil rights protesters.Footnote 21

The essence of the charges, however, was true: Sullivan had been complicit in violence, although perhaps not in all the specific acts described in the ad.Footnote 22 But Sullivan’s reputation wasn’t harmed. At the time, being known for committing violence against civil rights protesters would have only enhanced his reputation among whites in Montgomery. Sullivan and three Montgomery commissioners sued The New York Times and four ministers whose names appeared on the ad for $500,000 each.Footnote 23 Shortly after, the governor of Alabama, John Patterson, also sued The Times, the ministers, and King for $1 million, claiming he’d been defamed by the ad’s references to Alabama “authorities.”Footnote 24

Authorities in Birmingham likewise wasted no time in bringing libel suits against The Times over its news reporting on racial violence in the city – violence that had been abetted by local officials, including Bull Connor, Birmingham’s notorious commissioner of public safety.Footnote 25 These seven additional libel suits added $3.5 million in potential damages to The Times’ burden.Footnote 26 A Times reporter was even brought up on charges of criminal libel for his reporting on Birmingham, which could have led to six months’ imprisonment.Footnote 27 This use of libel law to enact a coordinated, state-sponsored attack on a disfavored newspaper was unprecedented in the history of the press.Footnote 28

The Alabama libel suits presented an existential threat to The Times, which operated on a low profit margin and was barely breaking even in 1960.Footnote 29 The libel suits threatened to bankrupt The New York Times.Footnote 30 In response, The Times’ lawyers made the historic decision of ordering all personnel to stay out of Alabama to avoid further libel trouble.Footnote 31 Because of the libel suits, the nation’s newspaper of record didn’t have a single reporter in one of the major sites of civil rights activity during the critical years of the Civil Rights Movement. The libel suits were having a chilling effect on the press.

In November 1960, an all-white jury in Montgomery concluded that the statements in the ad could be understood as defaming Sullivan and awarded him $500,000.Footnote 32 At the time, it was the largest-ever libel verdict in the country.Footnote 33 The Chicago Tribune noted that “even the most intrepid publisher must be intimidated into silence” by this use of libel law.Footnote 34 These successful libel suits, moreover, spurred a wave of copycat lawsuits. By 1964, southern officials had brought seventeen libel suits against northern media outlets seeking damage awards of more than $288 million.Footnote 35

Notable examples include a lawsuit brought by arch-segregationist Edwin A. Walker. Walker was a retired Army general who led a segregationist mob that assaulted reporters and federal officers to protest the admission of James Meredith, a Black student, to the University of Mississippi. Walker sued the Associated Press and ten other media outlets for $33 million in damages over accurate accounts that he had encouraged the rioting. The director of the Mississippi Highway Patrol, T. B. Birdsong, then sued The Saturday Evening Post over an article titled What’s Next in Mississippi, which imputed “official misconduct” to patrolmen during the Ole Miss riots, alleging that state troopers failed to help federal marshals rein in the mob and that patrolmen stood by while a white vigilante posse beat up a news photographer. Birdsong sought $276 million in damages – $1 million for himself and $1 million for each of the state’s 275 highway patrolmen. The sheriff of Etowah County, Alabama, sued the publisher of the Ladies’ Home Journal, Curtis Publishing, for $3 million for an article that accused the sheriff and his deputies of brutality in racial demonstrations. Tom King, a candidate for mayor of Birmingham, threatened a libel suit against The Saturday Evening Post for describing Birmingham as the most “backwards” city in America on race.Footnote 36

Many “publications are now under the shadow of potentially expensive [libel] actions,” noted the Columbia Journalism Review in 1963. “The characteristic actions of the 1960s appear to be suits growing out of local or regional retaliation for reporting or comment by a national news organization,” it observed. “Large awards and wide publicity seem to be encouraging more and more of the offended to sue.”Footnote 37 This was putting it rather mildly.

15.3 Appeal to the U.S. Supreme Court

After losing their appeal before the Alabama Supreme Court in 1962, The Times and the ministers appealed separately to the U.S. Supreme Court. The ministers’ appeal focused on segregation in the trial proceedings and the racial animus that had given rise to the libel prosecutions.Footnote 38 The Times, represented by eminent Columbia University Professor Herbert Wechsler, focused on libel law’s threat to freedom of the press and on the freedom of citizens to criticize their government more generally.

To avoid confrontation with the Supreme Court’s well-established position on the constitutionally unprotected status of libel and the thorny issue of how reputation and free speech should be balanced, Wechsler brilliantly shifted the focus of the appeal from the right to protect reputation to the right of citizens to criticize the government. Wechsler argued that permitting Sullivan to recover on the theory that he was defamed by criticism of the “police” in Montgomery was akin to the defunct crime of seditious libel. That crime, under which a government may punish its critics, had long been assumed to be unconstitutional.Footnote 39 “The decision of the Supreme Court of Alabama gives a scope and application to the law of libel so restrictive of the right to protest and to criticize official conduct that it abridges the freedom of the press, as that freedom has been defined by the decisions of the Court,” Wechsler’s brief argued.Footnote 40 “It transforms the action for defamation from a method of protecting private reputation to a device for insulating government against attack. If the judgment stands, its impact will be grave – not only upon the press but also upon those whose welfare may depend on the ability and willingness of publications to give voice to grievances against the agencies of governmental power.”Footnote 41

The brief continued, “We submit that such a rule of liability cannot be reconciled with this Court’s rulings on the scope of freedom of the press safeguarded by the Constitution. Those rulings start with the assumption that one of the prime objectives of the First Amendment is to protect the right to criticize ‘all public institutions.’ … We do not see how … criticism of an elected, public official may consistently be punished as a libel on the ground that it diminishes his reputation.”Footnote 42 Criticism of public officials, Wechsler argued, was protected absolutely by the First Amendment.Footnote 43

In March 1964, the Court threw out Sullivan’s verdict and placed constitutional limits on libel laws in the form of the “actual malice” rule. A public official could not recover damages for libel unless they could show that the statement was false and made with “actual malice” – knowledge that the statement was false, or “reckless disregard of whether it was false or not.”Footnote 44 Brennan created the “actual malice” rule, in part, to address the extreme and unusual facts of the case. He knew that a negligence standard, a standard of carelessness – which is the usual fault standard in personal injury cases and might have been the obvious standard to apply – wouldn’t have protected The Times, since it admitted that it had been careless in publishing the ad without checking the facts. Brennan, the consummate negotiator, also created actual malice as a compromise to please different blocs of justices on the Court, including the three “absolutist” justices, Black, Goldberg, and Douglas, who would have taken Wechsler’s extreme, absolutist position, and those justices who preferred less sweeping, balancing approaches.Footnote 45

Brennan saw another reason for adopting actual malice. Inspired by Wechsler’s analysis, Brennan offered the most extensive reading of the meaning of the First Amendment and its relationship to democracy in Supreme Court history to that time. Adopting Wechsler’s views of freedom of expression, Brennan wrote that the ability of citizens to engage in debate of public issues, debate that may include caustic and sharp attacks on government and public officials, was the “central meaning” of the First Amendment.Footnote 46 The essence of the First Amendment is the right of citizens to engage in “uninhibited, robust, and wide open” public discourse, which was the essence of self-governance.Footnote 47 Libel law’s rules of strict liability and the requirement that the defendant prove the truth had a “chilling effect” on public debate by producing self-censorship, Brennan wrote. Presented with rules that were overly strict, speakers would “steer … wide of the unlawful zone.”Footnote 48

Even a negligence standard, Brennan believed, didn’t provide adequate “breathing room” for speech, because “erroneous statement is inevitable in free debate.”Footnote 49 The Court adopted the actual malice standard as a way of providing First Amendment protection for speakers who criticized public officials, while at the same time allowing protection for reputation.Footnote 50 Brennan recognized that under the actual malice rule, harms caused by some false statements that were not made with reckless disregard for the truth would go unremedied. But this was the price of freedom of expression, he wrote. The urgent situation in Alabama had called on the Court to take a fresh look at an entire area of law and to reexamine the principles and values of the First Amendment.

15.4 Freeing the Press

The Supreme Court saved the nation’s newspaper of record from ruin. The Sullivan decision not only reversed L. B. Sullivan’s judgment but turned back the segregationists’ “libel attack.” It freed the press to report fully and freely on the Civil Rights Movement, coverage that could have been undermined if the next wave of libel suits had gone through the courts without Sullivan’s protections.

After the Court handed down its opinion in Sullivan, media coverage of the Civil Rights Movement was indeed “robust and wide-open.”Footnote 51 Reporting on protests in Selma, Alabama, the following year helped facilitate the national consensus on civil rights that led to the passage of the Voting Rights Act of 1965. Scholars agree that the success of the Civil Rights Movement can be attributed in large part to direct action protests and media coverage of those protests. Sullivan was one of the most important Supreme Court decisions facilitating the advance of the Civil Rights Movement.Footnote 52

More broadly, Sullivan facilitated a sea change in journalism, permitting the press to fulfill its constitutional function of reporting on public affairs without fear of devastating libel judgments. Prior to the 1960s, the press had relied on the assertions of the government on critical issues such as national security. But with the Vietnam War, journalists began publishing unauthorized versions of the facts. Such reporting, and investigative journalism more generally, would not have been possible without Sullivan. The protections of Sullivan facilitated the rise of investigative reporting as a genre. “The allowance of room for honest mistakes of fact encouraged the press to challenge official truth on two subjects so hidden by government secrecy, Vietnam and Watergate, that no unauthorized story could ever have been ‘absolutely confirmable,’” in the words of journalist Anthony Lewis.Footnote 53 It was Sullivan that permitted the free flow of information “through the press so that the public would be informed about the government and its actions.”Footnote 54

If today’s opponents of Sullivan and related cases succeed, it would become substantially riskier for speakers, including the press, to comment on public affairs. Without the protections of Sullivan, the press would be greatly limited in its ability to engage in its “watchdog” function, monitoring the conduct of public officials and holding them accountable to their constituents. A rollback of Sullivan, moreover, could herald a return to the “libel warfare” that existed before 1964. As the Sullivan story suggests, fewer protections for speakers in libel law would undermine the ability of the press and citizens to engage in the “uninhibited, robust, and wide-open” discourse that is central to public deliberation in a democratic society. The Supreme Court in 1964, and the American public more broadly, saw how libel law could be used to persecute critics of the status quo speaking out on behalf of social justice – persecution that could easily occur today in the absence of Sullivan’s protections. Sullivan changed the course of history, and in our contentious times, its protections matter more than ever.

16 Returning FOIA to the Press

In the popular imagination, a right to information is foundational. Democracy depends on an informed electorate, and the press, as a representative of and an intermediary for the public, should be able to access the information it needs to tell the rest of us what our “[g]overnment is up to.”Footnote 1 Yet a right of the public or the press to access government information is not enshrined in our Constitution. While the U.S. Supreme Court has interpreted the First Amendment to guarantee some limited access to judicial proceedings, it has never expanded this right to include federal agency records.Footnote 2 For two hundred years of our nation’s history, in fact, nothing did.

That all changed in 1966 when Congress enacted the Freedom of Information Act (FOIA), which is now the signature government transparency law in the United States.Footnote 3 The press, specifically, was at the forefront of the decade-long advocacy struggle that led to the passage of FOIA. Journalists and their associations provided Congress with significant input during the drafting of the legislation.Footnote 4 In congressional hearings, moreover, elected representatives repeatedly articulated their vision that the press would vigorously use FOIA to the benefit of the public.Footnote 5 Still, Congress has never limited the use of the law to the press; indeed, FOIA provides that any person may request any agency record for any reason. The government must respond within twenty business days and provide the record unless it falls within one of nine enumerated exemptions.Footnote 6

Today, the federal government receives nearly a million FOIA requests a year.Footnote 7 Many celebrate this level of engagement as a sign of the law’s success. Yet the story looks different if we focus on the first-order FOIA users, namely the press (alongside watchdog groups, nonprofits, and community organizations), who are using the law to inform the broader public. When asked about FOIA’s implementation, journalists, who now make less than 3 percent of all federal government-wide requests, may cite instances of success but generally give the law’s implementation a failing grade.Footnote 8

What, then, are the law’s problems from the perspective of the press? Journalist FOIA requesters (or would-be requesters) typically encounter two sets of problems: first, extreme agency delay in responding to requests and, second, the practical inability of most reporters to obtain recourse when the agency wrongly denies their requests.Footnote 9 These problems are both long-standing and well known, and Congress has tried to address them through amendments to the law that have, for example, created new carrots and sticks for agencies to meet deadlines or established mediation services for requesters who are dissatisfied with the agency response.Footnote 10 Yet if these incremental reforms have made a difference, it is only at the margin.

In this chapter, I will lay out a case for structural, not incremental, reforms that have the potential to “return” FOIA to the press. That is to say, Congress could structurally reshape FOIA to better serve its first-order users, the news media, for the benefit of the public. To be clear, I would never advocate limiting FOIA rights to the press or other oversight requesters. But if FOIA isn’t working for those requesters, then it is not doing the government transparency work we want it to do. Moreover, if it’s not working for the press, then it’s probably also not working well for others who are seeking government-held information.

16.1 Rethinking Information Delivery

Any conversation about journalists’ use of FOIA must start with a conversation about delay. Delay is one of the most intractable problems in FOIA administration. Even for those requests designated as being on the “simple” rather than the “complex” track, government-wide average processing times in the last reported year were more than twice the statutory deadline, and some agencies’ averages far exceeded that.Footnote 11 A congressional report titled “FOIA is Broken” documented, among other problems, that “[m]any agency FOIA offices have abandoned the statutory requirement to make a determination within 20 working days.”Footnote 12 A recent Government Accountability Office (GAO) report described backlogged requests as “a perennial problem for many federal agencies,” noting that in fiscal year 2022 the government-wide backlog of requests had reached more than 200,000.Footnote 13

Delay is also the news media’s biggest complaint and the reason journalists most often cite for not using the law more frequently. For example, ProPublica, an outlet that does use FOIA to great effect on a regular basis, nonetheless reports that delays “now routinely last longer than most journalists can wait – or so long that the information requested is no longer useful.”Footnote 14 In a series of interviews that I conducted with journalists, reporters uniformly cited delay as a top concern in using FOIA.Footnote 15

There is no doubt a variety of factors that contribute to delay. Agencies often cite resource constraints as a key factor, and there are many structural reasons why agencies are likely to have underfunded FOIA offices.Footnote 16 And, to be sure, there may be some level of agency recalcitrance in fulfilling particularly hot button requests.Footnote 17 But Congress’s recent attempts to address delay have missed the mark; reforms have adjusted fee structures, reporting requirements, and other incentives,Footnote 18 implying that recalcitrance is the primary reason for delay and that if we simply punish late responses or reward timely ones, agencies’ performance will improve.

Yet my research suggests there is another, much greater contributing factor that cannot be overlooked: the volume of non-oversight requesters. In the most comprehensive empirical account ever compiled, detailed in my book, Saving the Freedom of Information Act, I documented that the vast majority of requesters are not using FOIA for public oversight purposes but rather to advance private interests.Footnote 19 To be sure, these private interests are sometimes very compelling, and using FOIA for such purposes is neither illegitimate nor unlawful. Still, my look inside various FOIA offices revealed that FOIA processing is largely designed for and caters to whatever kind of request is dominating FOIA practice at a given agency. That is to say, agencies are essentially specializing in serving non-oversight requesters simply because they make up the vast majority of requesters.

To begin, some agencies, particularly law enforcement and benefits agencies, are inundated by first-person requests, or requests made by individuals who are seeking information or files about themselves. Take, for example, the Department of Homeland Security (DHS), which now receives more than half of the federal government’s total requests every year, outpacing every other agency by an order of magnitude and clocking in at more than 500,000 requests.Footnote 20 Nearly all – more than 95 percent – of the requests DHS receives consist of noncitizens’ first-person requests for their own immigration records, typically because they are needed in conjunction with either a pending or threatened deportation case or an application for a new visa or for citizenship.Footnote 21 Similarly, at the Federal Bureau of Prisons (FBOP), more than half of all requests are first-person in nature, with most individuals in this category requesting their own medical records.Footnote 22 Many other agencies also experience high volumes of first-person requests, making first-person requests the most frequent type of FOIA request government wide.Footnote 23

Agencies that receive high volumes of first-person requests have processes that specialize in serving those requesters. One top official explained that the DHS is, in his words, “trying to build a system that speaks to ninety percent of the requests that we get” and that the agency is “trying to drive down the response time for routine requests as far as possible.”Footnote 24 At the Bureau of Prisons, a top FOIA official in charge of agency FOIA policy echoed this sentiment: “I put a lot of emphasis in processing simple requests quickly because it is one of the few things we have a lot of control [over] with our metrics.”Footnote 25 This strategy is oftentimes very visible. At U.S. Citizenship and Immigration Services (USCIS) – the component agency of the DHS that receives the highest volume of requests – certain personnel do nothing but process noncitizens’ requests for immigration files. Those individuals, who make up the vast majority of the agency’s 250 or so FOIA processors, aren’t even trained or qualified to answer any other types of requests, such as ones from reporters.Footnote 26

Designing FOIA operations to best serve the largest FOIA constituency at a given agency is an entirely rational strategy. Agencies’ FOIA performances are judged by the metrics they have to report, such as aggregate statistics on the number of requests received and processed, average processing times, and types of responses.Footnote 27 The best way to improve performance is naturally to focus on the bulk of routine and predictable requests, not on the comparatively tiny fraction of requests from journalists, which are often more topical and unique.

This phenomenon is not limited to agencies with high volumes of first-person requests. At other agencies, typically large regulatory agencies like the Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC), the Environmental Protection Agency (EPA), or the Food and Drug Administration (FDA), FOIA offices spend the vast majority of their time processing requests from commercial requesters seeking routine, discrete records such as inspection reports, financial filings, or government contract information.Footnote 28 To compound this dynamic, at many of these agencies with high-volume commercial requesting, a significant subset of those commercial requesters are businesses I classify as information resellers, which are businesses that request a high volume of records from the federal government and resell them, at a considerable profit, to private parties.Footnote 29 FOIA offices with these kinds of commercial requesters may have impressive performance statistics, particularly regarding the speed of their responses, but only because each request requires looking up a single record.Footnote 30 When those comprise 75, 85, or 95 percent of the requests received, agencies have little incentive to do anything but prioritize these requests and hire and train processors who specialize in addressing them.

In short, the sheer volume of non-oversight requesters necessarily affects journalists’ and watchdog groups’ requests in a negative way. These requesters not only create huge numbers of FOIA requests that strain agency resources but also distort the priorities of agency FOIA offices to incentivize catering to these much more frequent uses. As a consequence, the agencies lose, or fail to attain, the knowledge and skills necessary to serve the news media. That is to say, journalists’ requests are likely to face worse outcomes in FOIA processing simply because they do not fit neatly into the process the agency has designed for more routine and predictable information requests.

The unfortunate reality, though, is that FOIA serves these other interests poorly, too. In the cases of individuals with a pending law enforcement proceeding or benefits application, FOIA may not provide the records they need in time to help them in their underlying case.Footnote 31 For businesses that want a database of all facilities inspection reports, building such a repository by requesting those records one at a time through individualized letter writing is highly inefficient.Footnote 32 These requesters are only turning to FOIA because there is no better alternative.

To return FOIA to the press, Congress could and should mandate that agencies consider alternative information delivery mechanisms for sets of records routinely needed by the public. While no one should be denied the option to avail themselves of FOIA, they wouldn’t have to rely on FOIA if they had better alternatives, such as public access databases with affirmatively available records or individual portals for personal information or discovery in administrative proceedings. Examining the constituencies currently served by FOIA reveals the possibilities of serving those constituencies better outside of the FOIA system, saving FOIA for the first-order uses imagined.

16.2 Rethinking Oversight

The second big structural problem for journalists seeking public information is that agencies’ FOIA violations are relatively insulated from independent review or practical consequence. Put differently, the right to file a federal lawsuit to challenge agency denials under the Act is simply inadequate as an oversight mechanism.

When FOIA was originally enacted in 1966, Congress understood the importance of independent oversight of agency decisions to withhold records, and it focused on judicial review as the remedy for that concern. As a result, unlike in other administrative law contexts, Congress provided that courts should review agency decisions to withhold records de novo, without any deference to the agency’s position.Footnote 33 And when the Supreme Court ruled that federal courts’ powers to review were limited in some areas of national security in EPA v. Mink, Congress legislatively overruled the court and reinstated true de novo review in the statute.Footnote 34 In other words, Congress doubled down on the idea that the best protection against an executive agency’s wrongful decision to withhold records is a full, independent adjudication by the courts.

The idea of de novo judicial review sounds good on paper. But in practice, judicial review has proven woefully inadequate. To begin with, getting into court is quite difficult. Hiring a lawyer is expensive, and litigation is resource-intensive. Most oversight requesters, including reporters and news media organizations, cannot afford legal fights over records. And the changing nature of news media means there are fewer and fewer legacy outlets that would potentially have the kind of resources required to litigate denials on behalf of their reporters. One study by James Hamilton documented that FOIA use generally is declining among smaller local news outlets.Footnote 35

The fact that few reporters can go to court to challenge an agency’s failure to comply with the law is particularly troubling because reporters who have brought FOIA suits have observed the power of independent review. In a series of interviews I conducted with journalists who are using FOIA particularly effectively, many stressed the value of going to court. Science journalist and New York University Professor Charles Seife said that he only started finding FOIA valuable when he found lawyers willing to fight his FOIA cases pro bono, including in a law school clinic.Footnote 36 Independent journalist Seth Freed Wessler was so motivated by the success of litigating some of his requests that he cofounded a nonprofit dedicated to linking freelance reporters with pro bono counsel in FOIA cases.Footnote 37 The New York Times provides another perfect example of the power of litigation. The newsroom’s top lawyer David McCraw told me that he often sues agencies over their long delays simply to force the agency to respond.Footnote 38 Just filing a case can make a difference, even without the court making a decision.

But the truth is, these reporters are outliers. Federal litigation is slow, and it can sometimes take years to reach a conclusion, compounding the problems of delay. And the problem may be getting worse over time. A recent report by the Transactional Records Access Clearinghouse (TRAC) documented that FOIA litigation was facing longer and longer delays with a pending backlog of FOIA cases dragging on for years.Footnote 39

Access to the courts and the length of the litigation process are not the only problems with judicial review. Even those requesters who make it into court and go through the lengthy litigation process find they do not always receive a truly independent federal court decision. Despite the mandate of de novo review, many FOIA scholars, including myself, have documented the various ways in which courts nonetheless defer to agency positions by, for example, invoking a special “substantial weight” standard for reviewing government affidavits in the national security context or by using various procedural shortcuts only in FOIA litigation that advantage the government, such as curtailing discovery.Footnote 40

The US experience stands in stark contrast to a plethora of other countries around the world that have successfully implemented independent administrative oversight frameworks rather than relying on judicial review.Footnote 41 These bodies are typically styled as information commissions, and some of them have been operating for decades.Footnote 42

For example, Mexico’s information commission, known as INAI for its initials in Spanish, is one of the world’s most celebrated among such institutions.Footnote 43 During a nine-month research stay in Mexico on a Fulbright grant, I studied INAI and its role in Mexico’s transparency system.Footnote 44 I concluded that five pillars of its work are central to its success.Footnote 45 First, it operates a National Transparency Platform, a one-stop portal for requesters to submit, track, and appeal requests, along with a repository of previously released information and all records required to be made proactively available by government entities.Footnote 46 This platform also facilitates all back-end work by government bodies and INAI. Second, it operates as an adjudication machine, deciding some 20,000 cases a year very quickly and ruling for the requester more than three-quarters of the time.Footnote 47 Third, it engages in affirmative monitoring of compliance by following the enforcement of its own orders, sampling responses to unappealed requests to review, and auditing compliance with affirmative disclosure obligations.Footnote 48 Fourth, it engages in concerted outreach and education, inside and outside of government, promoting a culture of understanding the fundamental human right to information as being inextricably linked with the exercise of other basic rights.Footnote 49 And finally, the leadership body – the seven members of the commission itself – sets a tone and an expectation around transparency that touches everything the institution does.Footnote 50 This well-funded institution is staffed with 800 employees and has separate state counterparts in every state in the country.Footnote 51

My interviews with journalists who interact with INAI demonstrate the potential of an information commission to return transparency laws to the press. Uniformly, the reporters I spoke with praised INAI, despite occasional qualifications. One reporter summarized it this way: “I do think it’s a very strong tool that we have as citizens, and as journalists, and academics. And I think it mostly works … I feel it is super important to have INAI.”Footnote 52 Another said: “I think the fact that there’s a centralized institution through which you can submit all requests is amazing.”Footnote 53 When I asked one journalist if she was satisfied with INAI, she said, “[T]he truth is, despite everything, yes, I am satisfied. You can’t deny that it works well … if you see journalism in Mexico in the last 10 years, the key [to success] has been the transparency system.”Footnote 54

A couple of journalists I talked to had experiences making information requests in both the United States and Mexico. They highlighted some important differences. For example, they saw the simplicity of the process in Mexico as a huge advantage, both in making requests and in appealing decisions. One reporter said, “I’m surprised to see [that] other people’s requests [are] often just a sentence that describes what they’re asking for without reference to law or anything, and sometimes that sentence will be a little bit hard to interpret, or a little bit … maybe they’re using informal language, and then I’ll look at the response and it will be like a very good response … Whereas in the United States, I feel like it would be an automatic denial.”Footnote 55 Another journalist, who makes similar requests in Guatemala, Mexico, and the United States, ranked Mexico as the best of the three by far.Footnote 56

Journalists routinely use INAI’s appeal process. One journalist said he appeals nearly every time he doesn’t receive everything he wanted, and he estimated that he wins the appeal 90 percent of the time.Footnote 57 Another similarly reported appealing essentially every unsatisfactory response but estimated a lower success rate, around half of the time.Footnote 58 Still, there was broad agreement that the process was both fast and easy to engage with.Footnote 59

The news media also praised INAI’s role in facilitating proactive transparency, or acting as an archive or document repository. One journalist described her process of searching through past requests and responses to find information she needed for stories. She downloads databases of all past requests to a certain body for a certain period of time, then looks through them for key terms, and studies the data that was already released or uses that data to formulate her own, better-informed request.Footnote 60 Another journalist also cited the National Transparency Platform as crucial, particularly in ensuring that proactive disclosures are available from state and local institutions.Footnote 61

To be sure, journalists lodged complaints about some of INAI’s failures. One cited his perception that INAI does not sufficiently weigh public interest in disclosure as allowed by the law.Footnote 62 More than one noted that even once they won an appeal at INAI, sometimes the responding government entity did not comply with INAI’s order.Footnote 63 One journalist had even brought a lawsuit to challenge an order determining that compliance was achieved.Footnote 64 Another asserted that, despite the ease of the process, it still advantaged sophisticated requesters and represented parties.Footnote 65 Still, the overwhelmingly positive assessment of INAI and the repeated drumbeat of its indispensability in newsgathering were heartening themes of my interviews.

Unfortunately, INAI eventually became a victim of its own success. After public spats with the commission, former Mexican President Andrés Manuel López Obrador engaged a years-long campaign against INAI, culminating in recent constitutional reforms led by President Claudia Sheinbaum that will eliminate the commission entirely.Footnote 66 While citing costs and inefficiencies as the impetus for reform, López Obrador and his successor took aim only after INAI acted as a meaningful check on government power, demonstrating, perhaps, the very power of the model itself.

One way to think about an information commission like INAI is that it acts as a public support or even a public subsidy to ensure that high-quality journalism continues. Subsidies or public funding for the news media, particularly local journalism, have been considered by policymakers, academics, and advocates.Footnote 67 The investment in maintaining public information, in facilitating broad access to requests and to appeals, and in monitoring compliance with transparency laws government wide is a way to support journalism without direct monetary grants or other direct forms of subsidy. It is, in short, a way to return public records requests to the press.

In the United States, many of us hoped that the Office of Government Information Services (OGIS), which Congress created as part of the 2007 amendments to FOIA, would serve this sort of role.Footnote 68 Unfortunately, despite some strengthening of that institution over time, it has never been given the resources or power necessary to fulfill the kind of role I envision. To begin, it does not have the power to issue binding orders but, rather, was designed to make policy recommendations and offer mediation services to resolve disputes between requesters and agencies. But recommendations are not orders, and at the end of the day, OGIS has no power to compel agencies to comply with the law. Moreover, OGIS is decidedly not an independent body. It is housed in the National Archives, itself an executive branch agency, and has already been beholden to some administration politics during its short life. Finally, it operates on a shoestring budget and with a tiny staff, woefully insufficient for the kind of demand we would expect for the services of a full-fledged information commission.

We should consider the formation of an information commission to administer and enforce FOIA obligations in the United States. I have previously described how such a body is possible within our current legal constraints and traditions and how it could be designed to withstand political pressure and facilitate access to information for the press and beyond.Footnote 69

The time to return FOIA to the press is now. We are seeing the dangers of unchecked executive power around the world.Footnote 70 Scholars, policymakers, and advocates are increasingly focused on questions of democratic and constitutional renewal. While FOIA is a statutory right, it has rightly been described as quasi-constitutional or foundational. Accordingly, the reforms needed to return FOIA to the press are not small ones: They, too, are foundational.

Footnotes

11 Reinvigorating the Press Clause Through Negative Theory

1 See Vince Blasi, The Checking Value in First Amendment Theory, 2 Am. B. Found. Res. J. 521, 538–39 (1977) (“The central value of the checking function is that the abuse of official power is an especially serious evil …”).

2 See RonNell Andersen Jones, Press Speakers and Listener Rights, 90 U. Colo. L. Rev. 499, 537–43 (2019).

3 Erin Carroll, Obstruction of Journalism, 99 Denv. L. Rev. 407, 412 (2022).

4 Footnote Id. at 409, 415.

5 See generally Margaret Sullivan, Ghosting the News: Local Journalism and the Crisis of American Democracy (2020).

6 Helen Norton, Distrust, Negative First Amendment Theory, and the Regulation of Lies, 22-07 Knight First Amend. Inst. 3 (Oct. 19, 2022), https://knightcolumbia.org/content/distrust-negative-first-amendment-theory-and-the-regulation-of-lies [https://perma.cc/L3LZ-CAMA].

7 See Ronald A. Cass, The Perils of Positive Thinking: Constitutional Interpretation and Negative First Amendment Theory, 34 UCLA L. Rev. 1405, 1438–39 (1987).

8 See Pell v. Procunier, 417 U.S. 817 (1974) (rejecting such a theory to deny the press’s assertion of a Press Clause right to conduct face-to-face interviews of those in prison).

9 See Toni M. Massaro & Helen Norton, Free Speech and Democracy: A Pragmatic Primer for Twenty-first Century Reformers, 54 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 1631, 1658–62 (2021) (discussing pluralistic approaches to free speech theory).

10 Note that affirmative and negative free speech theories are different answers to the question of why the First Amendment protects certain rights while positive and negative rights instead reflect different answers to the question of how the First Amendment protects such rights.

11 See Cass, supra Footnote note 7, at 1439 (“The framers were not intent on promoting some well-defined conception of the good, whether individual or societal. They were responding to problems that already had arisen and that they feared might recur.”).

12 Floyd Abrams, The Press Is Different: Reflections on Justice Stewart and the Autonomous Press, 7 Hofstra L. Rev. 563, 579 (1979).

13 Potter Stewart, Or of the Press, 26 Hastings L.J. 631, 634 (1975).

14 Gene Roberts & Hank Klibanoff, The Race Beat: The Press, the Civil Rights Struggle, and the Awakening of a Nation 229–55 (2006).

15 376 U.S. 254 (1964).

16 See El Dia, Inc. v. Governor Rossello, 165 F.3d 106, 109 (1st Cir. 1999) (“It would seem obvious that using government funds to punish political speech by members of the press and to attempt to coerce commentary favorable to the government would run afoul of the First Amendment.”); see also Culver Smith, The Press, Politics, and Patronage: The American Government’s Use of Newspapers 1789–1875 4 (1977) (“Colonial newspapers, like those in England, had been subject to censorship by the government through privilege licenses that could be revoked.”).

17 See How Local Officials Seek Revenge on Their Hometown Newspapers, https://www.nytimes.com/2023/06/18/business/newspapers-public-notices.html; In a Small Rhode Island Town, A Big Issue About the First Amendment, https://www.bostonglobe.com/2023/08/29/metro/small-rhode-island-town-big-issue-about-first-amendment/.

18 See Pen Am. Ctr., Inc. v. Trump, 448 F. Supp. 3d 309, 316–17 (2020).

19 United States v. Alvarez, 567 U.S. 709 (2012).

20 See Transcript of Oral Argument, Alvarez, 567 U.S. at 27, 35–36 (where the challenger’s lawyer conceded that the law neither punished nor chilled valuable speech).

21 Alvarez, 567 U.S. at 723.

22 578 U.S. 266 (2016).

23 460 U.S. 575 (1983).

24 Footnote Id. at 585.

25 Footnote Id. at 588 (quoting NAACP v. Button, 371 U.S. 415, 433 (1963)).

26 Footnote Id. at 592.

27 Footnote Id. at 585 (“[W]e cannot countenance such treatment unless the State asserts a counterbalancing interest of compelling importance that it cannot achieve without differential taxation.”).

28 408 U.S. 665 (1972). To be sure, Branzburg is often described, and understandably so, as the majority’s rejection of the press’s claim to an affirmative right to newsgathering. My point here is that the majority also rejected the negative theory concerns raised by the challengers and by the dissent.

29 Footnote Id. at 699.

30 Footnote Id. 731 (Stewart, J., dissenting).

31 Footnote Id. at 740.

32 E.g., Revels v. Vincenz, 382 F.3d 870, 876 (8th Cir. 2004).

33 437 F.3d 410 (4th Cir. 2006).

34 Reply Brief of Appellants at *7, Baltimore Sun v. Ehrlich, 437 F.3d 410 (4th Cir. 2006).

35 Brief of Amicus Curiae Washington Post at *20–21, Baltimore Sun v. Ehrlich, 437 F.3d 410 (4th Cir. 2006).

36 Footnote Id. at *20.

37 Baltimore Sun, 437 F.3d at 420.

38 See supra Footnote notes 28Footnote 31 and accompanying text.

39 Reed v. Gilbert, 576 U.S. 155, 165 (2015) (announcing that, for Speech Clause purposes, the Court would apply strict scrutiny to all content- and speaker-based distinctions).

40 For an example, see Borreca v. Fasi, 369 F. Supp. 906, 910 (D. Haw. 1974) (applying strict scrutiny to, and preliminarily enjoining, a mayor’s decision to deny a reporter access to news conferences based on the mayor’s unhappiness with the reporter’s coverage).

41 See Helen Norton, The Government’s Speech and the Constitution 6–9 (2019).

42 See Footnote id. at 106–12, 159–69 (discussing examples).

43 See Helen Norton, A Framework for Thinking about the Government’s Speech and the Constitution, 2022 U. Ill. L. Rev. 1669, 1683.

44 Norton, supra Footnote note 41, at 159–62; see also David L. Bazelon, FCC Regulation of the Telecommunications Press, 1975 Duke L.J. 213, 214, 244–51 (1975) (detailing the negative theory concerns created “by a comprehensive system for the licensing of speakers” where those “who must obtain permission to engage in activity protected by the First Amendment are vulnerable to the various sub silentio pressures that prior approval permits” and documenting the Nixon administration’s efforts to apply such pressure to the Washington Post and other critics).

45 See Carroll, supra Footnote note 3 at 422–23 (discussing the ways in which government leaders sometimes urge their followers’ violent reprisals against the press).

12 The Constitutional Exceptionalism of Religion and the Press

I am grateful to Jack Balkin for the rich conversations that spurred this chapter and to Sandy Baron for organizing the forum that brought us together to discuss the future of the Press Clause. I am extraordinarily grateful, too, for the superb edits and suggestions provided by Sonja West and RonNell Andersen Jones and for the opportunity to be a part of this series.

1 U.S. Const. amend. I.

2 Civic groups that provide institutional organization of assemblies and petitions might be understood as an implied third.

3 Douglas Laycock is credited with inventing the most-favored-nation idea, though he opposes some of its later instantiations. Andrew Koppelman, The Increasingly Dangerous Variants of the ‘Most-Favored-Nation’ Theory of Religious Liberty, 108 Iowa L. Rev. 2237, 2242 (2023) (“MFN was invented by Professor Douglas Laycock”); Douglas Laycock, The Remnants of Free Exercise, 1990 Sup. Ct. Rev. 1, 49 (1990) (arguing “that religion [should] get something analogous to most-favored nation status. Religious speech should be treated as well as political speech, religious land uses should be treated as well as any other land use of comparable intensity, and so forth.”)

4 Locke v. Davey, 540 U.S. 712, 718–19 (2004); Footnote id. at 718–19 (“[T]he Establishment Clause and the Free Exercise Clause[] are frequently in tension.… [T]here are some state actions permitted by the Establishment Clause but not required by the Free Exercise Clause.”).

5 540 U.S. 712.

6 See Richard L. Hasen, From Bloggers in Pajamas to The Gateway Pundit: How Government Entities Do and Should Identify Professional Journalists for Access and Protection in The Future of Press Freedom: Democracy, Law, and the News in Changing Times 271 (RonNell Andersen Jones & Sonja R. West eds., 2025).

7 As discussed below, there are good reasons to treat the press at least as constitutionally exceptional as religion, if not more so, because there is no countervailing clause with respect to the press as there is with respect to religion in the Establishment Clause. I bracket the question of whether recent religion law exemptions are correct. For reasons I articulate elsewhere, I do not believe that the freedoms of speech or association generally support exemptions from public accommodations or employment antidiscrimination laws. See, e.g., Amanda Shanor & Sarah E. Light, Greenwashing and the First Amendment, 122 Colum. L. Rev. 2033 (2022); Amanda Shanor, LGBTQ+ Need Not Apply, Reg. Rev. (June 21, 2021), https://www.theregreview.org/2021/06/21/shanor-lgbtq-need-not-apply/; Amanda Shanor & Sarah E. Light, Anti-Woke Capitalism, the First Amendment, and the Decline of Libertarianism, 118 Nw. Univ. L. Rev. 347 (2023); Br. for First Amendment Scholars as Amici Curiae, 303 Creative LLC v. Elenis, 600 U.S. 570 (2023), https://www.supremecourt.gov/DocketPDF/21/21-476/234114/20220819171031826_Creative_Amicus_Brief_SCOTUS.pdf.

8 Emp. Div., Dept. of Hum. Res. of Or. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 882, 888 (1990); Footnote id. at 879 (“[T]he right of free exercise does not relieve an individual of the obligation to comply with a ‘valid and neutral law of general applicability on the ground that the law proscribes (or prescribes) conduct that his religion prescribes (or proscribes).’”); see also generally Gillette v. United States, supra, 401 U.S. at 461 (“Our cases do not at their farthest reach support the proposition that a stance of conscientious opposition relieves an objector from any colliding duty fixed by a democratic government.”).

9 Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye v. Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520, 532 (1993); see also Boerne (Lukumi applies to laws with “the object of stifling or punishing free exercise”).

10 See, e.g., Laycock, supra Footnote note 3, at, 4, 50 (arguing that “oppressive laws may be enacted through hostility, sheer indifference, or ignorance of minority faiths” and that “[e]xemptions for secular interests without exemptions for religious practice reflect a hostile indifference to religion.”).

11 Thomas Berg & Douglas Laycock, Protecting Free Exercise Under Smith and After Smith, SCOTUSblog (Jun. 19, 2021), https://www.scotusblog.com/2021/06/protecting-free-exercise-under-smith-and-after-smith/ (observing that as of June, 2021, “five justices [have] said that Smith was mistaken, and there may be more.”); Fulton v. City of Philadelphia, 593 U.S. 522, 545 (2021) (Alito, J., joined by Thomas & Gorsuch, JJ., concurring) (calling for the Court to revisit Smith); Footnote id. at 543 (Barrett, J., joined by Kavanaugh, J., concurring) (finding “textual and structural arguments against Smith … more compelling”).

12 Jim Oleske, Tandon Steals Fulton’s Thunder: The Most Important Free Exercise Decision Since 1990, SCOTUSBlog (April 15, 2021), https://www.scotusblog.com/2021/04/tandon-steals-fultons-thunder-the-most-important-free-exercise-decision-since-1990/.

13 Tandon v. Newsom, 593 U.S. 61 (2021); Oleske, supra Footnote note 12.

14 William Baude, Forward: The Supreme Court’s Shadow Docket, 9 N.Y.U. J. L. & Liberty 1 (2015); Stephen I. Vladeck, The Supreme Court Is Making New Law in the Shadows, N.Y. Times (Apr. 15, 2021), https://www.nytimes.com/2021/04/15/opinion/supreme-court-religion-orders.html.

15 Tandon, supra Footnote note 13, at 62.

16 Fulton v. City of Philadelphia, 593 U.S. 522 (2021).

17 Citing the need for a “more nuanced” approach, Justice Barrett filed a concurrence joined in full by Justice Kavanaugh and in part by Justice Breyer, in which all three disputed the “prevailing assumption” that, if Smith were overruled, strict scrutiny would apply to all generally applicable laws burdening religion. Footnote Id. at 543.

18 Fulton, supra Footnote note 16.

19 Note, Pandora’s Box of Religious Exemptions, 136 Harv. L. Rev. 1178 (2023); Koppelman, supra Footnote note 3, 108 Iowa L. Rev. 2237 (2023); Stephen I. Vladeck, The Most-Favored Right: COVID, the Supreme Court, and the (New) Free Exercise Clause, 15 N.Y.U. J.L. & LIBERTY 699, 734 (2022); Oleske, supra Footnote note 12; Cary Coglianese & Daniel E. Walters, A Trojan Horse from the Court’s Conservatives?, Reg. Rev. (June 21, 2021), https://www.theregreview.org/2021/06/21/coglianese-walters-trojan-horse-from-courts-conservatives/; Shanor, supra Footnote note 7. There is a broader literature on the most-favored-nation theory of religious exemptions. See Zalman Rothschild, Individualized Exemptions, Vaccine Mandates, and the New Free Exercise Clause, 131 Yale L.J.F. 1106 (2022); Mark Storslee, The COVID-19 Church-Closure Cases and the Free Exercise of Religion, 37 J.L. & Religion 72 (2022); Nelson Tebbe, The Principle and Politics of Equal Value, 121 Colum. L. Rev. 2397 (2021); Josh Blackman, The “Essential” Free Exercise Clause, 4 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 637 (2021); Ira C. Lupu & Robert W. Tuttle, The Radical Uncertainty of Free Exercise Principles: A Comment on Fulton v. City of Philadelphia, 5 Am. Const. Soc’y Sup. Ct. Rev. 221 (2021); Zalman Rothschild, Free Exercise’s Lingering Ambiguity, 11 Calif. L. Rev. Online 282 (2020); James M. Oleske, Free Exerciee (Dis)Honesty, 2019 Wisc. L. Rev. 689 (2019); Douglas Laycock & Steven T. Collis, Generally Applicable Law & the Free Exercise of Religion, 95 Neb. L. Rev. 1 (2016); James M. Oleske, Jr., Lukumi at Twenty: A Legacy of Uncertainty for Religious Liberty and Animal Welfare Laws, 19 Animal L. 295 (2013); Christopher C. Lund, A Matter of Constitutional Luck: The General Applicability Requirement in Free Exercise Jurisprudence, 26 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 627 (2003); Alan Brownstein, Protecting Religious Liberty: The False Messiahs of Free Speech Doctrine and Formal Neutrality, 18 J.L. & Pol. 119 (2002); Vikram David Amar & Alan E. Brownstein, “Most Favored-Nation” (“MFN”) Style Reasoning in Free Exercise Viewed Through the Lens of Constitutional Equality, Justia (May 21, 2021), https://verdict.justia.com/2021/05/21/most-favored-nation-mfn-style-reasoning-in-free-exercise-viewed-through-the-lens-of-constitutional-equality; Vikram David Amar & Alan E. Brownstein, Exploring the Meaning of and Problems with the Supreme Court’s (Apparent) Adoption of a “Most Favored Nation” Approach To Protecting Religious Liberty Under the Free Exercise Clause, Justia (Apr. 30, 2021), https://verdict.justia.com/2021/04/30/exploring-the-meaning-of-and-problems-with-the-supreme-courts-apparent-adoption-of-a-most-favored-nation-approach-to-protecting-religious-liberty-under-the-free-exercise-c.

20 Douglas Laycock, The Broader Implications of Masterpiece Cakeshop, 2019 BYU L. Rev. 167 (2019).

21 Coglianese & Walters, supra Footnote note 19.

22 Groff v. DeJoy, 600 U.S. 447 (2023). See also Bostock v. Clayton County, 590 U.S. 644 (2020) (suggesting a religious exemption might apply to religious employers who object to employing LGBTQ+ employees).

23 Hosanna-Tabor Evangelical Lutheran Church and School v. EEOC, 565 U.S. 171 (2012); Our Lady of Guadalupe School v. Morrissey-Berru, 140 S.Ct. 2049 (2020).

24 Carson v. Makin, 596 U.S. 767 (2022); Trinity Lutheran v. Comer, 582 U.S. 449 (2017).

25 Kennedy v. Bremerton School District, 597 U.S. 507 (2022).

26 Derek W. Black, When Religion and Public-Education Mission Collide, 132 Yale L.J.F. 559, 593, 596 (2022), https://www.yalelawjournal.org/pdf/F7.BlackFinalDraftWEB_gstabjb1.pdf.

27 Amar & Brownstein, “Most Favored-Nation” (“MFN”) Style Reasoning, supra Footnote note 19.

28 558 U.S. 310, 352 (2010) (quoting Austin v. Mich. Chamber of Commerce, 494 U.S. 652, 691 (1990) (Scalia, J. dissenting)).

29 Footnote Id. at 352–53 (“[E]ven assuming the most doubtful proposition that a news organization has a right to speak when others do not, the exemption would allow a conglomerate that owns both a media business and an unrelated business to influence or control the media in order to advance its overall business interest. At the same time, some other corporation, with an identical business interest but no media outlet in its ownership structure, would be forbidden to speak or inform the public about the same issue. This differential treatment cannot be squared with the First Amendment.”).

30 Sonja West, Favoring the Press, 106 Calif L. Rev. 91, 93–94 (2018).

31 Eugene Volokh, Freedom for the Press as an Industry, or for the Press as a Technology? From the Framing to Today, 160 U. Pa. L. Rev. 459, 462 (2012).

32 Prominent constitutional thinkers, including Justice Potter Stewart, Floyd Abrams, Vince Blasi, and Sonja West, have argued that “the press is ‘different’ from ‘everyone’; that it is, in a variety of circumstances, entitled to constitutional treatment distinct from that generally afforded those who exercise their freedom of expression.” Floyd Abrams, The Press Is Different: Reflections on Justice Stewart and the Autonomous Press, 7 Hofstra L. Rev. 563, 564 (1979); Vincent Blasi, The Checking Value in First Amendment Theory, 1977 Am. Bar Found. Rsch. J. 521 (1977); Sonja R. West, Press Exceptionalism, 127 Harv. L. Rev. 2434 (2014); Potter Stewart, “Or of the Press,”26 Hastings L.J. 631 (1975); Citizens United at 431 n.57 (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part); West, supra Footnote note 30, at 100 (“In other words, whether or not the Speech Clause allows for identity-based distinctions, the Press Clause is a clear endorsement of speaker categorization when it comes to the press. The Press Clause tells us that the government historically has, can, and sometimes must treat the press differently than other types of speakers.”).

33 Most state constitutions protected the freedom of the press. David A. Anderson, The Origins of the Press Clause, 30 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 455, 487 (1983). James Madison proposed another press clause that provided that “No State Shall violate the equal rights of conscience, or the freedom of the press, or the trial by jury in criminal cases,” but it was not adopted. Footnote Id. at 483–84. Cf. Jud Campbell, Natural Rights and the First Amendment, 127 Yale L. J. 246 (2017) (discussing founding-era natural law conceptions of the freedoms of speech and the press). It was not until the first half of the twentieth century the freedoms of speech and religion were incorporated against the states. Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652 (1925); Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.S. 296 (1940).

34 See generally Burt Neuborne, Madison’s Music (2015).

35 Prior to District of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570 (2008), the Second Amendment was widely viewed as extending only that far as well.

36 This argument resonates with but is distinct from David Anderson’s argument that the “case for constitutional protection of the press rests on its role as an organizer of democratic dialogue.” David Anderson, The Press and Democratic Dialogue, 127 Harv. L. Rev. F. 8 (2014), https://harvardlawreview.org/forum/vol-127/the-press-and-democratic-dialogue/.

37 See Sonja R. West, First Amendment Neighbors, 66 Ala. L. Rev. 357, 372–73 (2014).

38 Prior to the rise of politically polarized media, a handful of mainline broadcast news channels created a relatively shared space of belief about facts in the world.

39 Brown v. Hartlage, 456 U.S. 45, 60 (1982).

40 Anderson, supra Footnote note 33, at 464.

41 Footnote Id. at 463–64 (quoting Address to the Inhabitants of Quebec (1774), in Bernard Schwartz, The Bill of Rights: A Documentary History 223 (1971)).

42 Footnote Id. at 489 (quoting Schwartz, supra, at 229); see Footnote id. at 490 (“Throughout the formative period, the focus of discussion was on the role of the press in relation to the government.”).

43 See Koppelman, supra Footnote note 3 (analyzing different variants of MFN treatment in religion law and theory).

44 A question that has vexed press law, and for some augurs in favor of its unexceptional treatment, is the difficulty in defining “the press.” See Hasen, supra Footnote note 6 at 1 (“One of the potential impediments to having the government grant special access or protection to ‘the press’ is identifying who counts as a journalist.”). Defining religion faces similar difficulties, but this fact has not so far been understood to justify denying it exceptional treatment.

45 This might somewhat ameliorate the tendency of transparency laws to entrench economic interests, as David Pozen has found. David E. Pozen, Transparency’s Ideological Drift, 128 Yale L.J. 100 (2018).

46 Footnote Id. at 463–64 (quoting Address to the Inhabitants of Quebec (1774), in Bernard Schwartz, The Bill of Rights: A Documentary History 223 (1971)).

47 See Martha Minow, Saving the News: Why the Constitution Calls for Government Action to Preserve Freedom of Speech (2021).

13 The Other Press Clauses

1 U.S. Const. amend. I.

2 See David A. Anderson, The Origins of the Press Clause, 30 UCLA L. Rev. 455, 467 (1983) (noting that press clause protections were briefly debated, and speech rights were never proposed). See also Jud Campbell, Natural Rights and the First Amendment, 127 Yale L.J. 246, 250 (2017) (noting that “debates among the Founders” about the First Amendment “would seem to belie any broadly shared original understanding of speech and press freedoms”).

3 See, e.g., Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 704 (1972); Zurcher v. Stanford Daily, 436 U.S. 547, 565 (1978); Houchins v. KQED, Inc., 438 U.S. 1, 13 (1978). See also Sonja R. West, Awakening the Press Clause, 58 UCLA L. Rev. 1025, 1027 (2011) (reviewing these cases and observing that “a majority of the Court has, in essence, dismissed the clause as a constitutional redundancy”).

4 West, supra Footnote note 3, at 1027. This cuts against Chief Justice John Marshall’s assertion in Marbury v. Madison that “[i]t cannot be presumed that any clause in the constitution is intended to be without effect.” 5 U.S. 137, 174 (1803).

5 See, e.g., Ark. Const. art. II, § 6. See also Kan. Const. § 11; Minn. Const. art. I, § 3.

6 See, e.g., Ark. Const. art. II, § 6; Tenn. Const. § 19.

7 See, e.g., R.I. Const. art. I, § 20 (providing stand-alone protections for the press).

8 See App’x A, State Constitutional Free Expression Provisions, https://knightcolumbia.org/documents/2nb16t1vb4.

9 The two exceptions are Hawaii and South Carolina. See Haw. Const. art. I, § 4; S.C. Const. art. I, § 2.

10 See App’x A, State Constitutional Free Expression Provisions, supra Footnote note 8.

11 See, e.g., Cal. Const. art. I, § 2 (extending constitutional protection to journalists’ confidential sources and information).

12 See discussion infra Section 13.1.3.

13 See, e.g., Richmond Newspapers, Inc. v. Virginia, 448 U.S. 555, 580 (1980).

14 See, e.g., Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 690 (1972); Houchins v. KQED, Inc., 438 U.S. 1, 13 (1978). See also Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S.Ct. 876, 928 n.6 (2010) (Scalia, J., concurring) (arguing that “freedom of the press” means “everyone’s right to … publish”).

15 See Branzburg, supra Footnote note 14, at 690; Houchins, supra Footnote note 14, at 13.

16 See Penelope Muse Abernathy & Tim Franklin, The State of Local News 5 (2022) (“Since 2005, the country has lost more than a fourth of its newspapers (2,500) and is on track to lose a third by 2025.”).

17 See Kirstin McCudden, Another Record Year for Press-Freedom Violations in the US, Colum. Journalism Rev. (Jan. 12, 2022), https://www.cjr.org/analysis/2021-press-freedom-prior-restraint-arrests.php.

18 See, e.g., West, supra Footnote note 3, at 1032, 1045. See also Christina Koningisor, The De Facto Reporter’s Privilege, 127 Yale L.J. 1176, 1265 (2018) (presenting arguments in favor of revisiting Branzburg and recognizing a First Amendment-based reporter’s privilege).

19 Cf., e.g., Leonard W. Levy, Introduction to Freedom of the Press from Zenger to Jefferson xix, lvii (Leonard Levy ed., 1966) (arguing that the framers only intended the Press Clause to protect against prior restraints), with Anderson, supra Footnote note 2, at 455 (arguing that the drafters intended the press to operate as a meaningful check on government power and therefore sweep more broadly than a mere prohibition against prior restraint).

20 Anderson, supra Footnote note 2, at 491.

21 See, e.g., Sonja R. West, Press Exceptionalism, 127 Harv. L. Rev. 2434, 2453–62 (2014) (proposing a definition for who qualifies as the “press”); RonNell Andersen Jones & Lisa Grow Sun, Freedom of the Press in Post-Truthism America, 98 Wash. U.L. Rev. 419, 460–72 (2020).

22 See, e.g., RonNell Andersen Jones & Sonja R. West, The U.S. Supreme Court’s Characterizations of the Press: An Empirical Study, 100 N.C.L. Rev. 375, 379 (2022); RonNell Andersen Jones & Sonja R. West, Presuming Trustworthiness, 75 Fla. L. Rev. 799, 800 (2023).

23 There are important exceptions. See, e.g., Anderson, supra Footnote note 2, at 506–08 (chronicling the passage of state constitutional press protections); Sonja R. West, The “Press,” Then & Now, 77 Ohio St. L.J. 49, 65–71 (2016) (pointing to state constitutional press provisions for evidence of the “dual functions” of the Press Clause). For works examining specific state constitutional free expression provisions, see infra Footnote note 45.

24 For a discussion of previous scholarship addressing various aspects of state constitutional free expression protections, see infra Footnote note 45.

25 See, e.g., West, supra Footnote note 3, at 1063–68 (applying lessons of state legislative definitions of the press back to the federal context).

26 See supra Footnote notes 19Footnote 22 and accompanying text.

27 A possible third strand of scholarship that is relevant here explores how the lessons of state laboratories of democracy are relevant to federal constitutional debates. See, e.g., Joseph Blocher, What State Constitutional Law Can Tell Us About the Federal Constitution, 115 Penn St. L. Rev. 1035, 1036 (2011) (arguing that federal courts should look more often to the lessons of state constitutional law); Benjamin Silver, Nondelegation in the States, 75 Vand. L. Rev. 1211, 1215 (2022) (applying the “lessons of state nondelegation for the federal doctrine”).

28 See Stewart G. Pollock, Address, State Constitutions as Separate Sources of Fundamental Rights, 35 Rutgers L. Rev. 707, 716 (1983) (referring to the article as the “Magna Carta of state constitutional law”). Of course, there was ample previous state court precedent on this point, as well as previous scholarly exploration of independent state constitutional rights’ protections. See Randall T. Shepard, The Maturing Nature of State Constitution Jurisprudence, 30 Val. U.L. Rev. 421, 422 n.5 (1996) (describing this earlier work).

29 William J. Brennan, Jr., State Constitutions and the Protection of Individual Rights, 90 Harv. L. Rev. 489, 495–98 (1977).

30 Footnote Id. at 502.

31 See Fred R. Shapiro & Michelle Pearse, The Most-Cited Law Review Articles of All Time, 110 Mich. L. Rev. 1483, 1489 (2012) (showing that Brennan’s article is among the most cited).

32 See, e.g., West v. Thomson Newspapers, 872 P.2d 999, 1006 (Utah 1994) (outlining the leading methodological approaches). See also Jeffrey S. Sutton, 51 Imperfect Solutions: States and the Making of American Constitutional Law 174–90 (2018) (describing the various methodological approaches employed to interpret state constitutions).

33 There are many works addressing this topic. For some of the most prominent approaches, see, e.g., James A. Gardner, Interpreting State Constitutions: A Jurisprudence of Function in a Federal System 180–275 (2005); Sutton, supra Footnote note 32, at 174–90; G. Alan Tarr, Understanding State Constitutions (2005); Robert F. Williams, The Law of American State Constitutions 135–232 (2009). See also Goodwin Liu, State Constitutions and the Protection of Individual Rights: A Reappraisal, 92 N.Y.U.L. Rev. 1307, 1310 n.15 (2017) (describing this literature); Jonathan L. Marshfield, America’s Misunderstood Constitutional Rights, 170 U. Pa. L. Rev. 853, 873–74 (2022) (delineating between state constitutional “positivists,” “pragmatists,” and “constitutional universalists”).

34 See Thompson Newspapers, 872 P.2d at 1006 (describing these approaches).

35 Such debates take different forms. Some scholars have argued in favor of lockstep interpretation only in the context of specific constitutional protections. See, e.g., Michael E. Keasler, The Texas Experience: A Case for the Lockstep Approach, 77 Miss. L.J. 345, 367 (2007) (arguing in favor of lockstep interpretation for federal and state search and seizure protections). Others have argued in favor of lockstep interpretation only when state constitutional language closely tracks the federal text. See, e.g., Gardner, supra Footnote note 33, at 6–7 (critiquing courts for “often appropriat[ing] and adopt[ing] federal constitutional doctrine as the rule of decision for state constitutional provisions not only when the state constitutional text is identical to its federal counterpart, but even when it differs in potentially significant ways”). Still others have argued that lockstep interpretation is especially problematic in the context of interpreting state constitutional structure. See, e.g., Jonathan L. Marshfield, America’s Other Separation of Powers Tradition, 73 Duke L.J. 545, 549–51 (2023) (arguing against a Madisonian inter-branch competition separation of powers justification for state constitutions, and in favor of a “public accountability” rationale that is more faithful to state constitutional history, text, and design). And so on.

36 This chapter assumes that state court judges can and should construe state constitutional rights provisions independently, based on their own interpretive methods and precedents, and that there are a variety of acceptable methods of doing so. See Robert F. Williams, Why State Constitutions Matter, 45 New England L. Rev. 901, 905 (2011). Arguments against lockstep interpretation are especially strong where – as here – the federal and state constitutional texts diverge. See Gardner, supra Footnote note 33, at 6–7. In this context, forty-eight out of the fifty state constitutional press and speech provisions substantially diverge from the text of the First Amendment. App’x A, State Constitutional Free Expression Provisions (showing that Hawaii and South Carolina are the two exceptions).

37 See Williams, supra Footnote note 36, at 905.

38 See Liu, supra Footnote note 33, at 1308–09.

39 See supra Footnote note 33 and accompanying text.

40 See, e.g., Robert L. Bentlyewski, Abortion Rights Under State Constitutions: A Fifty-State Survey, 90 Fordham L. Rev. Online 201, 203 (2022) (finding that as of 2022, all but one of the state supreme courts to address the issue had recognized a state constitutional right to an abortion).

41 See, e.g., Hari M. Osofsky, Litigating Climate Change Infrastructure Impacts, 118 Nw. U.L. Rev. Online 149, 163 (2023); Quinn Yeargain, Decarbonizing Constitutions, 41 Yale L. & Pol’y Rev. 1, 6 (2023).

42 See Nina Totenberg, The Supreme Court Is the Most Conservative in 90 Years, NPR (July 5, 2022), https://www.npr.org/2022/07/05/1109444617/the-supreme-court-conservative.

43 See, e.g., Matthew Segal & Julie Murray, State Supreme Courts Offer the Best Chance to Advance Rights, Am. Civ. Liberties Union (May 2, 2023), https://www.aclu.org/news/civil-liberties/state-supreme-courts-offer-the-best-chance-to-advance-rights#:~:text=Each%20state%20has%20its%20own,or%20preserved%20under%20federal%20law. The Roberts Court has expanded First Amendment protections for certain speakers, especially corporate and religious speakers. See Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 558 U.S. 310 (2010); 303 Creative LLC v. Elenis, 600 U.S. 570 (2023). In this sense, the First Amendment context is distinct from contexts like reproductive rights or climate change, where the Court has actively contracted federal constitutional protection. See Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Org., 597 U.S. 215 (2022); West Virginia v. Environmental Protection Agency, 597 U.S. 697 (2022). But the Roberts Court has not expanded First Amendment protection for all speakers, and it has not expanded protections for the press. To the contrary, some of the strongest voices for expanded religious and corporate speech protections have argued in favor of contracting First Amendment protections for press speakers. See, e.g., Berisha v. Lawson, 141 S.Ct. 2424 (2021) (Thomas, J., dissenting from denial of cert.); Footnote id. at 2425 (Gorsuch, J., dissenting from denial of cert.).

44 For articles comparing free expression provisions across multiple states, see, e.g., Peter P. Miller, Freedom of Expression Under State Constitutions, 20 Stan. L. Rev. 318, 325–31 (1968); Todd F. Simon, Independent but Inadequate: State Constitutions and Protection of Freedom of Expression, 33 U. Kan. L. Rev. 305, 308 (1985); Kathryn Dix Sowle, A Matter of Opinion: Milkovich Four Years Later, 3 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 467, 519 (1994); Brady C. Williamson & James A. Friedman, State Constitutions: The Shopping Mall Cases, 1998 Wis. L. Rev. 883 (1998). For articles examining the meaning of state free expression provisions in a single state, see, e.g., Jeremy J. Bethel, Freedom of Expression in New York State: What Remains of People Ex Rel. Arcara v. Cloud Books, Inc.?, 28 Fordham Urb. L.J. 1797 (2001); Michael A. Giudicessi, Independent State Grounds for Freedom of Speech and of the Press: Article 1, Section 7 of the Iowa Constitution, 38 Drake L. Rev. 9, 26–28 (1988); Joseph H. Hart, Free Speech on Private Property – When Fundamental Rights Collide, 68 Tex. L. Rev. 1469, 1470 (1990); Anthony W. Kraus, Beyond the First Amendment: What the Evolution of Maryland’s Constitutional Free-Speech Guarantee Shows About Its Intended Breadth, 47 U. Balt. L.F. 83, 84 (2017); Seth F. Kreimer, The Pennsylvania Constitution’s Protection of Free Expression, 5 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 12, 13 (2002).

45 See, e.g., Kraus, supra Footnote note 44, at 97–98 (arguing in favor of construing Maryland’s free expression provisions more broadly than the First Amendment).

46 See discussion supra Footnote note 32 and accompanying text.

47 See Sutton, supra Footnote note 32, at 8 (noting that most litigants fail to raise state constitutional claims when available and arguing that this is a mistake).

48 See, e.g., Howard Cnty. Citizens for Open Gov’t v. Howard Cnty. Bd. of Elections, 201 Md. App. 605, 623 (2011); In re Letellier, 578 A.2d 722, 726, 17 Media L. Rep. 2169 (Me. 1990); State v. Turner, 550 N.W.2d 622, 628 (Minn. 1999).

49 See supra Footnote note 45 and accompanying text.

51 See infra Section 13.1.3.

52 See infra Section 13.2.1.

53 See infra Section 13.2.2.

54 U.S. Const. amend. I.

55 Footnote Id. See also West, supra Footnote note 3, at 1033–34 (arguing that the two semicolons suggest that the Speech and Press Clauses “were seen as sharing a commonality”).

56 West, supra Footnote note 3, at 1028.

57 See App’x A, State Constitutional Free Expression Provisions, supra Footnote note 8.

58 Haw. Const. art. I, § 4; S.C. Const. art. I, § 2.

59 See App’x A, State Constitutional Free Expression Provisions, supra Footnote note 8.

60 See App’x A, State Constitutional Free Expression Provisions, supra Footnote note 8.

61 See, e.g., Ky. Const. § 8; Pa. Const. art. I, § 7; Tenn. Const. art. I, § 19.

62 See, e.g., De. Const. art. 1, § 5; Ind. Const. art. I, § 9; Tenn. Const. art. I, § 19. See also Utah Const. art. 1, § 1 (providing that all persons have the right “to communicate freely their thoughts and opinions”).

63 Kan. Const. Bill of Rts. § 11.

64 Va. Const. art. I, § 12.

65 Miss. Const. art. III, § 13.

66 See Gulf Pub. Co. v. Lee, 434 So.2d 687, 696 (Miss. 1983).

67 Haw. Const. art. I, § 4; S.C. Const. art. I, § 2. See also R.I. Const. art. I, § 21 (combining speech, assembly, and petition protections).

68 R.I. Const. art. I, § 20 (freedom of the press); R.I. Const. art. I, § 21 (freedom of speech).

69 Haw. Const. art. I, § 4; Ind. Const. art. I, § 9; Or. Const. art. I, § 8; S.C. Const. art. I, § 2; Utah Const. art. I, § 15; W. Va. Const. art. III, § 7.

70 See App’x A, State Constitutional Free Expression Provisions, supra Footnote note 8.

72 See, e.g., Davenport v. Garcia, 834 S.W.2d 4, 7–8 (Tex. 1992) (contrasting the affirmative expression of state constitutional rights with negative prohibitions contained in the First Amendment); Robert v. City of Norfolk, 188 Va. 413, 420, 49 S.E.2d 697, 700 (1948) (same); Immuno AG. v. Moor-Jankowski, 77 N.Y.2d 235, 249, 567 N.E.2d 1270 (1991) (same).

73 Immuno AG. v. Moor-Jankowski, 77 N.Y.2d 235, 255 (1991).

74 Footnote Id. at 249.

75 Md. Const. Decl. of Rts. art. 40; Mass. Const. Pt. 1, art. XVI; N.H. Const. Pt. 1, art. 22; Vt. Const. CH I, art. XIII.

76 See App’x A, State Constitutional Free Expression Provisions, supra Footnote note 8.

77 See Footnote id. Some courts have held these provisions are rights-contracting. See, e.g., Ex Parte Tucci, 859 S.W.2d 1, 24 (Tex. 1993) (Philips, C.J., concurring) (arguing that the inclusion of such libel provisions “reflected the framers’ rejection of a broad commitment to a vigorous, untrammeled press”); Commonwealth v. Blanding, 20 Mass. 304, 304 (1825) (emphasizing that the state constitutional provision protects only against prior restraints on speech). Others have interpreted these provisions to be rights-expanding because they broadened the common law rule in force at the time that truth was not a defense to libel. See, e.g., People v. Croswell, 1804 WL 874, 391–92 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1804) (citing these truth-as-defense provisions as evidence of the drafters’ commitment to freedom of the press).

78 See Anderson, supra Footnote note 2, at 466–67 (describing two brief discussions on proposed press protections at the Constitutional Convention).

79 Footnote Id. at 467–75 (describing press and speech clause discussions during the state ratifying conventions). See also Leonard Williams Levy, Legacy of Suppression 4 (1960) (“[W]e know very little … about the original understanding of the First Amendment).

80 See Erwin Chemerinsky, Constitutional Law 1177 (2020) (“It is widely accepted that the First Amendment was meant, at the very least, to abolish such prior restraints on publication”).

81 See Campbell, supra Footnote note 2, at 250–51 (2017) (“After a century of academic debate, however, the meanings of speech and press freedoms at the Founding remain remarkably hazy.”)

82 Footnote Id. at 250–51 (describing these scholarly debates).

83 Footnote Id. at 254 (“Debates about expressive freedom also were wide ranging because the Founders often vehemently disagreed about which regulations of speech promoted the public good.”).

84 See John Dinan, Constitutional Amendment Processes in the 50 States, State Court Report (July 24, 2023), https://statecourtreport.org/our-work/analysis-opinion/constitutional-amendment-processes-50-states.

85 See Anderson, supra Footnote note 2, at 488–94.

86 See Bridges v. State of Cal., 314 U.S. 252, 264–65 (1941) (describing this history).

87 Levy, supra Footnote note 79, at 69 (quoting the Resolution of the Massachusetts House (1768).

88 Bernard Schwartz, The Bill of Rights 223 (1971) (reproducing Address to the Inhabitants of Quebec (1774)).

89 Anderson, supra Footnote note 2, at 464. Only two contained a speech clause. Footnote Id. at 508–09.

90 Footnote Id. at 489.

91 Schwartz, supra Footnote note 88, at 273 (reproducing the Pennsylvania Declaration of Rights, 1776). See also West, supra Footnote note 23, at 66–67 (noting that two press protections were contained in Pennsylvania’s Declaration of Rights, one in the “rights” section, and another in the “structure” section, and that these dual provisions support “two distinct purposes emanating out of a single concept of press freedom – protection of an expressive function and also a structural function”).

92 Footnote Id. at 235 (reproducing Virginia Declaration of Rights, 1776).

93 Footnote Id. at 378 (reproducing the New Hampshire Bill of Rights, 1783).

94 Anderson, supra Footnote note 2, at 460.

95 See Levy, supra Footnote note 79, at 192–97.

97 Footnote Id. at 194.

98 Footnote Id. at 195.

99 Anderson, supra Footnote note 2, at 535.

100 Levy, supra Footnote note 79, at 198–99.

101 See Anderson, supra Footnote note 2, at 505 (“[T]he evidence is contradictory, and we cannot know whether the Framers intended to limit the courts and the executive.”).

102 Footnote Id. at 535.

103 See U.S. Const. amend. I.

104 Four still ensure that the printing press will be available to those who wish to examine government, for example. See De. Const. art. 1, § 5; Ky. Const. § 8; Pa. Const. art. I, § 7; Tenn. Const. art. I, § 19. Two refer to the press as a “great bulwark of liberty.” N.C. Const. art. I, § 14; Va. Const. art. I, § 12. And one makes explicit that freedom of the press “can never be restrained except by despotic governments.” Va. Const. art. I, § 12.

105 See Anderson, supra Footnote note 2, at 490–92.

106 See U.S. Const. amends. I–XXVII; Alicia Bannon, Learning from State Constitutional Amendments, NYU J. of L & Pub. Pol. (Apr. 18, 2023), https://nyujlpp.org/quorum/bannon-learning-from-state-constitutional-amendments/#:~:text=State%20constitutions%20are%20also%20far,contain%20more%20than%207%2C000%20amendments.

107 See Bannon, supra Footnote note 106.

108 See, e.g., Gardner, supra Footnote note 33, at 1–22 (2005) (reviewing methodological questions that arise in the context of state constitutional interpretation).

109 This is not an exclusive list. For example, state courts have extended broader speech protections on private property. See Williamson & Friedman, supra Footnote note 44, at 887–93 (1998). They have also protected obscene speech more broadly. See, e.g., City of Portland v. Jacobsky, 496 A.2d 646, 653 (Me. 1985). This chapter focuses on the areas that have the greatest impact on protections for the press specifically.

110 See, e.g., New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 294 (1964) (Black, J., concurring) (“The half-million-dollar verdict does give dramatic proof, however, that state libel laws threaten the very existence of an American press virile enough to publish unpopular views on public affairs and bold enough to criticize the conduct of public officials.”); New York Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S. 713, 717 (1971) (“In my view, far from deserving condemnation for their courageous reporting, the New York Times, the Washington Post, and other newspapers should be commended for serving the purpose that the Founding Fathers saw so clearly. In revealing the workings of government that led to the Vietnam war, the newspapers nobly did precisely that which the Founders hoped and trusted they would do.”).

111 Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665 (1972), at 667–80.

113 Footnote Id. at 689–90.

114 Footnote Id. at 685–86.

115 Footnote Id. at 698–99.

116 Footnote Id. at 706.

117 Footnote Id. at 690. See also Zurcher v. Stanford Daily, 436 U.S. 547, 550–53 (1978) (declining to extend special protections against searches of newsrooms by police).

118 See Introduction to the Reporter’s Privilege Compendium, Rep. Comm. for Freedom of the Press (2021), https://www.rcfp.org/introduction-to-the-reporters-privilege-compendium/ (describing these precedents).

119 See Koningisor, supra Footnote note 18, at 1197–98.

120 See Mayze Teitler & Samuel Aber, The Law of the Reporter’s Privilege Is a Mess. A Federal Shield Law Could Help Fix It, Knight Inst. (Aug. 13, 2021), https://knightcolumbia.org/blog/the-law-of-the-reporters-privilege-is-a-mess-a-federal-shield-law-could-help-fix-it (summarizing this case law).

121 Cal. Const. art. I, § 2.

122 See Cal. Evid. Code § 1070; initially codified as Cal. Civ. Proc. Code § 1881 (1935).

123 Voter Information Guide, Primary Election, at 18 (June 3, 1980), https://repository.uclawsf.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1884&context=ca_ballot_props.

125 Playboy Enterprises, Inc. v. Superior Ct., 154 Cal. App. 3d 14, 20 (Ct. App. 1984) (“By constitutional amendment in 1980, provisions virtually identical to section 1070 were added to article I, section 2 of the California Constitution, elevating the newsperson’s protection to the constitutional level.”).

126 Voter Information Guide, supra Footnote note 123, at 19.

127 See, e.g., In re Grand Jury Proc. (Ridenhour), 520 So.2d 372, 374 (La. 1988); O’Neill v. Oakgrove Const., Inc., 71 N.Y.2d 521, 524 (1988); Scott v. News-Herald, 25 Ohio St.3d 243, 245 (1986); Matter of Contempt of Wright, 108 Idaho 418, 419 (1985); Zelenka v. State, 83 Wis.2d 601, 617, 266 N.W.2d 279, 286 (1978); Winegard v. Oxberger, 258 N.W.2d 847, 852 (Iowa 1977); Opinion of the Justs., 117 N.H. 386, 389 (1977).

128 See Rep. Comm. for Freedom of the Press, Shield Law Statute, Comparison, https://www.rcfp.org/privilege-sections/a-shield-law-statute/ (listing these laws). For protection extended through the rules of evidence, see, e.g., N.M. R. Evid. 11-514; Utah R. Evid. 509.

129 See, e.g., Vaughn v. State, 259 Ga. 325, 326 (1989); In re Letellier, 578 A.2d 722, 726 (Me. 1990); State v. Turner, 550 N.W.2d 622, 628 (Minn. 1999).

130 See, e.g., Opinion of the Justs., 117 N.H. 386, 389 (1977).

131 See, e.g., McKevitt v. Pallasch, 339 F.3d 530, 532–33 (7th Cir. 2003) (critiquing generous lower court readings of Branzburg). See also Erik Ugland, The New Abridged Reporter’s Privilege: Policies, Principles, and Pathological Perspectives, 71 Ohio St. L.J. 1, 4 (2010) (describing this shift in the federal courts’ approach to the reporter’s privilege).

132 Of course, state privileges don’t extend protection in the context of federal subpoenas. However, such subpoenas are rarer. See RonNell Andersen Jones, Avalanche or Undue Alarm? An Empirical Study of Subpoenas Received by the News Media, 93 Minn. L. Rev. 585, 654 (2008) (showing that media organizations receive substantially more subpoenas from state governments than from the federal government).

133 See, e.g., Pell v. Procunier, 417 U.S. 817, 822, 834 (1974); Saxbe v. Washington Post Co., 417 U.S. 843, 850 (1974); Houchins v. KQED, Inc., 438 U.S. 1, 7–8, (1978).

134 KQED, 438 U.S. at 14.

135 Footnote Id. at 3–5.

136 Footnote Id. at 9.

137 Richmond Newspapers, Inc. v. Virginia, 448 U.S. 555, 580 (1980).

138 Footnote Id. at 575.

139 See Rep. Comm. for Freedom of the Press, The Roots of Access Rights, https://www.rcfp.org/open-court-sections/a-the-roots-of-access-rights/ (describing the evolution of constitutional right of access law in the various circuits).

140 See, e.g., See Christopher Dunn, Column: Rediscovering the First Amendment Right of Access, N.Y.C.L. Union (Aug. 4, 2011), https://www.nyclu.org/en/publications/column-rediscovering-first-amendment-right-access-new-york-law-journal (describing a handful of court decisions extending constitutional access rights to administrative proceedings like immigration hearings).

141 Cal. Const. art. I, § 3; Fla. Const. art. I, § 24; La. Const. art. XII, § 3; Mont. Const. art. II, § 9; N.H. Const. pt. 1, art. 8; N.D. Const. art. XI, § 6. Another two states contain more narrow provisions providing access to state financial records and expenditures. See Ill. Const. art. VIII, § 1; Mich. Const. art. IX, § 23.

142 La. Const. Ann. art. XII, § 3.

143 See, e.g., Herrmann v. Superior Ct. of Imperial Cnty., 75 Cal. App. 5th 535, 543, 290 Cal. Rptr. 3d 597, 603 (2022); Bd. of Trustees, Jacksonville Police & Fire Pension Fund v. Lee, 189 So. 3d 120, 125 (Fla. 2016).

144 U.S. Const. art. I, § 5.

145 See Idaho Const. art. III, § 12; Mo. Const. art. III, § 19; Nev. Const. art. IV, § 15; Or. Const. art. IV, § 14; Tex. Const. art. III, § 16.

146 Ala. Const. § 57.

147 Richmond Newspapers, Inc. v. Virginia, 448 U.S. 555, 580 (1980).

148 App’x B, State Constitutional Open Government Provisions, https://knightcolumbia.org/documents/1aod4m2wyq. These clauses, too, are generally framed in broad terms, providing that courts shall be open to “every person.” Footnote Id.

149 Seattle Times Co. v. Ishikawa, 97 Wash. 2d 30, 37 (1982).

150 See discussion supra Footnote notes 140Footnote 141 and accompanying text.

151 Mo. Const. art. III, § 19.

152 See Jason Hancock, Bill Carving Some Legislative Records out of Missouri Sunshine Law Advances in Senate, Missouri Independent (Feb. 27, 2023), https://missouriindependent.com/2023/02/27/bill-carving-some-legislative-records-out-of-missouri-sunshine-law-advances-in-senate/.

153 Ky. Const. § 77.

154 KUTV, Inc. v. Wilkinson, 686 P.2d 456, 461–62 (Utah 1984) (“In addition, for purposes of our own constitutional direction that “[n]o law shall be passed to abridge or restrain the freedom of speech or of the press,” Utah Const. art. I, § 15, we add a fourth test pertaining to during-trial publicity.”)

155 283 U.S. 697, 715 (1931).

156 Footnote Id. at 716.

157 New York Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S. 713, 714 (1971).

159 Respublica v. Dennie, 1805 WL 911, at *3 (Pa. 1805).

160 Dailey v. Superior Ct. of City & Cnty. of San Francisco, 112 Cal. 94, 97 (1896).

162 Ariz. Const. art. II, § 6.

163 Phoenix Newspapers, Inc. v. Superior Ct. In & For Maricopa Cnty., 101 Ariz. 257, 259 (1966).

164 See State v. Coe, 101 Wash. 2d 364, 374 (1984).

165 Marx & Haas Jeans Clothing Co. v. Watson, 168 Mo. 133, 67 S.W. 391, 393 (1902). See also Lindsay & Co. v. Montana Fed’n of Lab., 37 Mont. 264, 96 P. 127, 131 (1908) (reading state constitution to prohibit all prior restraints).

166 See discussion supra Footnote notes 77Footnote 78 and accompanying text.

167 New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 280 (1964).

168 Footnote Id. at 282.

169 418 U.S. 323, 344–47 (1974).

170 See Berisha v. Lawson, 141 S.Ct. 2424, 2425 (2021) (Thomas, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari) (critiquing this line of cases in part for extending the definition of public figure too far).

171 See Penelope Muse Abernathy, The State of Local News (2023), https://localnewsinitiative.northwestern.edu/projects/state-of-local-news/2023/report/.

172 Berisha v. Lawson, 141 S.Ct. 2424, 2425–30 (2021) (Gorsuch, J., dissenting).

173 See Footnote id. (garnering only two votes); Counterman v. Colorado, 600 U.S. 66, 143 S.Ct. 2106, 2109 (2023)(affirming Sullivan).

174 See discussion supra Footnote notes 29Footnote 31 and accompanying text.

175 See New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 280 n.20 (1964) (listing these decisions).

176 See Footnote id. Further, some of these state court decisions did address the state press and speech clauses in the context of actual malice. See, e.g., Coleman v. MacLennan, 98 P. 281, 284 (Kan. 1908).

177 See New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964).

178 See, e.g., Beach v. Shanley, 62 N.Y.2d 241, 255, 465 N.E.2d 304 (1984) (“This State has long provided one of the most hospitable climates for the free exchange of ideas.”) (Wachtler, J., concurring).

179 Olman v. Evans, 750 F.2d 970 (D.C. Cir. 1984), cert. denied, 471 U.S. 1127 (1985).

180 Footnote Id. at 971.

181 Footnote Id. at 979–84.

182 Milkovich v. Lorain J. Co., 497 U.S. 1 (1990).

183 Footnote Id. at 19–20.

184 See Kraus, supra Footnote note 44, at 94.

185 See, e.g., Immuno AG. v. Moor-Jankowski, 77 N.Y.2d 235, 261 (1991); West v. Thomson Newspapers, 872 P.2d 999, 1014 (Utah 1994); Dow v. New Haven Indep., Inc., 41 Conn. Supp. 31, 44 (Ct. Super. Ct. 1987).

186 Immuno AG. v. Moor-Jankowski, 77 N.Y.2d 235, 249 (1991).

188 Footnote Id. at 249–52.

189 Beattie v. Fleet Nat. Bank, 746 A.2d 717, 724 (R.I. 2000).

190 West v. Thomson Newspapers, 872 P.2d 999, 1014 (Utah 1994).

191 See, e.g., Beach v. Shanley, 62 N.Y.2d 241, 255, 465 N.E.2d 304 (1984) (“This State has long provided one of the most hospitable climates for the free exchange of ideas.”) (Wachtler, J., concurring).

192 See, e.g., Robert I. Berdon, Freedom of the Press and the Connecticut Constitution, 26 Conn. L. Rev. 659, 669 (1994) (describing the problem of litigants not raising possible state constitutional press claims).

193 See Jessica Bulman-Pozen & Miriam Seifter, The Right to Amend State Constitutions, 133 Yale L.J. Forum 191, 195–201 (2023) (describing these amendment rights).

194 See App’x A, State Constitutional Free Expression Provisions, supra Footnote note 8.

195 Immuno AG. v. Moor-Jankowski, 77 N.Y.2d 235, 249 (1991).

196 See App’x A, State Constitutional Free Expression Provisions, supra Footnote note 8.

197 Kraus, supra Footnote note 44, at 95 (advancing this argument in the context of Maryland’s free expression provision).

198 See supra Footnote note 142 and accompanying text.

199 See, e.g., Ky. Const. § 8; Pa. Const. art. I, § 7; Tenn. Const. art. I, § 19.

200 Va. Const. art. I, § 12.

201 See discussion supra Footnote notes 71Footnote 73 and accompanying text.

202 See Christina Koningisor and Jacob Noti-Victor, Innovation Policy and the Press, in The Future of Press Freedom: Democracy, Law, and the News in Changing Times 437 (RonNell Andersen Jones & Sonja R. West eds., 2025).

203 R.I. Const. art. I, § 20 (freedom of the press); R.I. Const. art. I, § 21 (freedom of speech).

204 See West, supra Footnote note 3, at 1028.

205 See also Ark. Const. art. II, § 6 (never mentioning speech protections at all).

206 See Marshfield, supra Footnote note 33, at 886–93 (describing these debates).

207 See The Book of the States, General Information on State Constitutions (as of Jan. 1, 2022), https://bookofthestates.org/tables/general-information-on-state-constitutions-as-of-january-1-2022/.

208 See discussion supra Footnote notes 29Footnote 32 and accompanying text.

209 See Marshfield, supra Footnote note 33, at 876–77 (noting that there have been 233 state constitutional conventions between 1776 and 2020, and drafting records exist for 114 of them).

210 See Footnote id.

211 See Dinan, supra Footnote note 84 (comparing the 27 amendments of the U.S. Constitution to the more than 7,000 amendments of state constitutions).

212 See Marshfield, supra Footnote note 33, at 860.

213 See supra Footnote notes 122Footnote 127 and accompanying text.

214 See, e.g., Near v. State of Minnesota ex rel. Olson, 283 U.S. 697, 716 (1931).

215 Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 704–05 (1972).

216 See Koningisor, supra Footnote note 18, at 1202.

217 See West, supra Footnote note 3, at 1063–68 (reviewing these various legislative approaches).

218 Footnote Id. at 1063.

219 See discussion supra Section 13.1.3.

220 See supra Footnote notes 43Footnote 44 and accompanying text.

221 See supra Section 13.1.3.

14 The Long Shadow of Food Lion

Thanks to the Knight First Amendment Institute for inviting me to contribute to this important project. I am also grateful to RonNell Andersen Jones, Enrique Armijo, Rebecca Aviel, Evelyn Douek, Sarah Haan, Daphne Keller, Christina Koningisor, Matthew Schafer, David Schulz, Amanda Shanor, Mia Speier, Alexander Tsesis, Sonja West, and Marshall Van Alstyne for their thoughtful comments, with special thanks to Professors Andersen Jones and West for their organization of this Symposium. Nina Christensen, Karina Condon, and Charlotte Rhoad provided valuable research support.

1 194 F.3d 505, 510 (4th Cir. 1999).

3 Footnote Id. at 520–22. By “newsgathering,” I mean the act of “seeking out news of public interest for the purpose of disseminating it to an audience.” Erik Ugland, Demarcating the Right to Gather News: A Sequential Interpretation of the First Amendment, 3 Duke J. Const. L. & Pub. Pol’y 113, 137 (2008).

4 Zoom interview with Susan Barnett and Lynne Dale, former producers, ABC “Primetime Live” (Jan. 8, 2024) [hereinafter Barnett/Dale Interview]; Zoom interview with Nathan Siegel (Jan. 11, 2024) [hereinafter Siegel Interview].

5 Much of my work in this area was done in conjunction with my colleague, Justin Marceau. See, e.g., Alan K. Chen & Justin Marceau, Truth and Transparency: Undercover Investigations in the Twenty-First Century (2023); Alan K. Chen & Justin Marceau, Developing a Taxonomy of Lies Under the First Amendment, 89 U. Colo. L. Rev. 655 (2018); Justin Marceau & Alan K. Chen, Free Speech and Democracy in the Video Age, 116 Colum. L. Rev. 991 (2016); Alan K. Chen & Justin Marceau, High Value Lies, Ugly Truths, and the First Amendment, 69 Vand. L. Rev. 1435 (2015). See also Alan K. Chen, Investigative Deception Across Social Contexts, https://knightcolumbia.org/content/investigative-deception-across-social-contexts; Alan K. Chen, Cheap Speech Creation, 54 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 2405 (2021).

6 As such, they are distinct from two other important tools of information gathering and disclosure – investigative reporting and whistleblowing. For an explanation of the differences among these methods, see Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 214–15.

7 For a more extensive definition, see Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 18.

8 Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4. See also Marceau & Chen, Video Age, supra Footnote note 5, at 1029 (“A recording provides a self-authenticating and easily reproduced memorialization of one’s encounters or experiences.”).

9 Brooke Kroeger, Undercover Reporting: The Truth about Deception 15–30 (2012).

10 J. Cutler Andrews, The North Reports the Civil War 6–34 (1985).

11 Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 36–74.

12 Jean Marie Lutes, Front-Page Girls: Women Journalists in American Culture and Fiction, 1880–1930 2 (2006) (“for men, participatory journalism was a choice; for women, it was one of the few ways to break out of the women’s pages.”). Unfortunately, the high-profile stories produced by women conducting undercover investigations did little to eradicate these types of gender biases in the profession. Amanda Svachula, When the Times Kept Female Reporters Upstairs, N.Y. Times (Sept. 20, 2018), https://www.nytimes.com/2018/09/20/insider/times-womens-section-female-reporters.html (noting that between 1955 and 1971, The New York Times ran a separate section on “Food, Fashions, Family, and Furnishings” written by women and directed at a female audience).

13 Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 4–6.

14 Nellie Bly, Ten Days in a Mad-House (1887).

15 Upton Sinclair, The Jungle (1906).

16 Kroeger, supra Footnote note 9, at 84.

17 Anthony Arthur, Radical Innocent: Upton Sinclair 49 (2006). Even reporters conducting undercover investigations more recently have resorted to similar tactics. Kroeger, supra Footnote note 9, at 172–76 (describing how Pulitzer Prize-winning Chicago Tribune reporter William Gaines, posing as a janitor to investigate a local private hospital, wrote notes on paper towels that he stashed away until he could safely recover them).

18 Kroeger, supra Footnote note 9, at 83.

19 Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 7.

20 Footnote Id. at 54–55.

21 Footnote Id. at 56–58.

22 Television News Magazines, in 4 Encyclopedia of Journalism 1385 (Christopher H. Sterling ed., 2009).

23 Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 58.

24 Television News Magazines, supra Footnote note 22.

25 Havens Realty Corp. v. Coleman, 455 U.S. 363, 373–74 (1982). See also Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 10–12.

26 James L. Fox, “Salting” the Construction Industry, 24 Wm. Mitchell L. Rev. 681, 683–84 (1998). See also Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 15–16.

27 See, e.g., Hoffa v. United States, 385 U.S. 293, 303 (1966). See also Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 16–18.

28 Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 12–14, 30–31. For example, undercover investigations have been used by animal rights activists and anti-abortion advocates, among others.

29 Alexander Meiklejohn, Free Speech and Its Relation to Self-Government 88–89 (1948).

30 Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at xiii–xvii.

31 RonNell Andersen Jones & Sonja R. West, The Disappearing Freedom of the Press, 79 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 1377, 1382–84 (2022)

32 Penelope Muse Abernathy, The State of Local News: The 2023 Report, Executive Summary, https://localnewsinitiative.northwestern.edu/projects/state-of-local-news/2023/report/#executive-summary.

33 See infra Footnote note 200 and accompanying text.

34 Greg Munno, FOIA Suits Jump in 2014, The FOIA Project, Dec. 22, 2014, https://foiaproject.org/2014/12/22/foia-suits-jump-in-2014/ (reporting that between 2005 and 2012, traditional media brought between three and nine FOIA suits per year, but than in 2014, no legacy media outlet other than The New York Times filed a FOIA lawsuit).

35 Andersen Jones & West, supra Footnote note 31, at 1388.

36 For a thoughtful response to the objectivity issue, see A. G. Sulzberger, Journalism’s Essential Value, Colum. Journalism Review, May 15, 2023, https://www.cjr.org/special_report/ag-sulzberger-new-york-times-journalisms-essential-value-objectivity-independence.php.

37 Andersen Jones & West, supra Footnote note 31, at 1386–87. See also Threats to Freedom of Press: Violence, Disinformation & Censorship, May 11, 2023, https://www.unesco.org/en/threats-freedom-press-violence-disinformation-censorship (reporting that according to the United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization, a journalist somewhere in the world is killed every four days).

38 Erin Carroll, Obstruction of Journalism: A New Way to Combat Violence Against Journalists, Colum. Journalism Review, Jan. 13, 2022, https://www.cjr.org/analysis/obstruction-journalism-violence.php.

40 Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

41 The narrative about the initiation of the investigation comes from my Zoom interview of Barnett and Dale. See Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

43 Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4. Coincidentally, as discussed above, Upton Sinclair also first began his undercover investigation of the meatpacking industry focused on labor practices, but also changed direction to instead examine food safety and sanitation.

44 Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

49 See, e.g., Society of Professional Journalists, Society of Professional Journalists – 1996 Code of Ethics, https://spjnetwork.org/quill2/codedcontroversey/ethics-code-2009.pdf [hereinafter 1996 SPJ Code of Ethics] (“Avoid undercover or other surreptitious methods of gathering information except when traditional open methods will not yield information vital to the public.”).

52 Food Lion, Inc. v. Cap. Cities/ABC, Inc., 984 F. Supp. 923, 927 (M.D.N.C. 1997), aff’d in part, rev’d in part, 194 F.3d 505 (4th Cir. 1999).

53 Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

55 Food Lion, 194 F.3d at 511.

56 Kirkus Reviews, Feb. 15, 2021 (“‘By writing these reporters back into history,’ Todd writes, ‘I aim to highlight the double standard that labels women as ‘stunt reporters’ while men are ‘investigative journalists,’ even as they do the same work.’”) (reviewing Kim Todd, Sensational: The Hidden History of America’s “Girl Stunt Reporters” (2021)), https://www.kirkusreviews.com/book-reviews/kim-todd/sensational-stunt/.

57 James L. Aucoin, The Evolution of American Investigative Journalism 3–4 (2005). In states that have enacted Ag Gag laws, the legislative histories have revealed some colorful insults directed at undercover investigators, who have been called “jack wagon[s],” Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Herbert, 263 F. Supp. 3d 1193, 1198 (D. Utah 2017), “vigilantes,” and been compared to “marauding invaders.” Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Otter, 44 F. Supp. 3d 1009, 1024 (D. Idaho 2014).

58 Barry Meier & Bill Carter, Undercover Tactics by TV Magazines Fall under Attack, N.Y. Times (Dec. 23, 1996), www.nytimes.com/1996/12/23/business/undercover-tactics-by-tv-magazines-fall-under-attack.html.

59 Food Lion, 194 F.3d at 512.

61 Restatement (Second) of Torts §§552–53 (1995).

62 Moreover, it is unclear that any state recognizes an independent common law tort action for resume fraud. Rather, resume fraud appears to come up almost exclusively in the context of serving as a defense to wrongful termination and employment discrimination claims. See, e.g., Cicchetti v. Morris Cnty. Sheriff’s Off., 194 N.J. 563, 579 (2008).

63 Indeed, in the context of its evaluation of Food Lion’s trespass claim, the court observed “if we turned successful resume fraud into trespass, we would not be protecting the interest underlying the tort of trespass – the ownership and peaceable possession of land.” 194 F.3d at 518.

64 United States v. Alvarez, 567 U.S. 709 (2012).

65 Footnote Id. at 719, 723 (plurality opinion). See also Footnote id. at 734–36 (Breyer, J., concurring in the judgment) (stating general agreement with the majority’s framework).

66 567 U.S. at 723.

67 Chen & Marceau, High Value Lies, supra Footnote note 5, at 1492 n.313.

68 Wasden, 878 F.3d at 1201.

69 Footnote Id. at 1201–02 (emphasis added).

70 Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Herbert, 263 F. Supp. 3d 1193, 1206 (D. Utah 2017).

71 Restatement (Second) of Torts §652B (1995).

72 See, e.g., Grygiel v. Monches Fish & Game Club, Inc., 328 Wis. 2d 436, 461 (2010).

73 Belluomo v. KAKE TV & Radio, Inc., 3 Kan. App. 2d 461 (1979); People v. Segal, 358 N.Y.S.2d 866 (Crim. Ct. 1974).

74 Keyzer v. Amerlink, Ltd., 173 N.C. App. 284 (2005), aff’d, 360 N.C. 397 (2006); Am. Transmission, Inc. v. Channel 7 of Detroit, Inc., 239 Mich. App. 695 (2000). See also First Amendment – “Ag-Gag” Laws – Eighth Circuit Upholds Law Criminalizing Access to Agricultural Production Facilities under False Pretenses. – Animal Legal Defense Fund v. Reynolds, 8 F.4th 781 (8th Cir. 2021), 135 Harv. L. Rev. 1166, 1169 (2022).

75 Chen, Investigative Deception, supra Footnote note 5.

76 People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, Inc. v. N. Carolina Farm Bureau Fed’n, Inc., 60 F.4th 815 (4th Cir. 2023) (cleaned up); Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Kelly, 9 F.4th 1219 (10th Cir. 2021); Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Herbert, 263 F. Supp. 3d 1193 (D. Utah 2017). The author discloses that he serves or served as counsel to the plaintiffs in most of the Ag Gag cases cited in this chapter.

77 Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Reynolds, 8 F.4th 781 (8th Cir. 2021) (“Reynolds I”); Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Wasden, 878 F.3d 1184 (9th Cir. 2018).

78 Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Reynolds, 89 F.4th 1065, 1067 (8th Cir. 2024) (“Reynolds II”).

79 United States v. Alvarez, 567 U.S. 709, 719, 723 (2012) (plurality opinion).

80 Restatement (Second) of Torts §652B (1995).

81 Marian K. Riedy & Kim Sperduto, At-Will Fiduciaries? The Anomalies of a “Duty of Loyalty” in the Twenty-First Century, 93 Neb. L. Rev. 267, 272 (2014). A related, but distinct concern, might be that an undercover investigator might intentionally or inadvertently reveal an employer’s trade secrets. There are, of course, already many legal restrictions against stealing trade secrets, and this chapter is not suggesting the privilege would extend to exemption from such laws. Even beyond legal restrictions, the best practices for undercover investigations could explicitly prohibit even the unintentional public disclosure of trade secrets.

82 Food Lion, Inc. v. Cap. Cities/ABC, Inc., 951 F. Supp. 1224, 1230 (M.D.N.C. 1996). For the biblical citation, see Matthew 6:24 (New American Standard Bible).

83 Restatement (Second) of Torts §652B (1995).

84 Restatement (Second) of Torts §652D (1995).

85 Typically, employee privacy concerns relate to intrusion by the employer, not by fellow employees. But in this context, there are conceivable privacy interests that may be implicated by an undercover investigation, so I address them here.

86 Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

87 See, e.g., Grygiel v. Monches Fish & Game Club, Inc., 328 Wis. 2d 436, 461 (2010).

88 Food Lion, 194 F.3d at 522.

89 Chen & Marceau, High Value Lies, supra Footnote note 5, at 1502–05; Nathan Siegel, Publication Damages in Newsgathering Cases, 19 Comm. Law, Summer 2001, at 11, 15 (2001).

90 Complaint, Food Lion, Inc. v. Capital Cities/ABC, Inc., No. 92 CVS 5513 (Forsyth Co. Super. Ct. Sept. 17, 1992) (copy on file with author).

91 This information was obtained from the Bloomberg docket database for Food Lion, Inc. v. Capital Cities/ABC, et al., U.S. District Court for the Middle District of North Carolina, No. 6:92-cv-00592 [hereinafter Bloomberg Docket].

93 As one indication of the battle’s intensity, the Bloomberg trial docket trial has 671 entries. Footnote Id.

94 Food Lion, Inc. v. Cap. Cities/ABC, Inc., 964 F. Supp. 956, 964 n.5 (M.D.N.C. 1997), aff’d on other grounds, 194 F.3d 505 (4th Cir. 1999).

95 Footnote Id. at 962.

96 Bloomberg Docket, supra Footnote note 91.

97 194 F.3d at 511.

98 Footnote Id. at 517. The trial court required Food Lion to elect whether to receive damages under the state statutory claim or the fraud claim. Food Lion elected to receive $1,400 under the latter. Footnote Id. at 511.

100 Footnote Id. at 511.

101 Food Lion cross-appealed on the denial of publication damages, but the court affirmed the district court’s decision to reject that remedy. Footnote Id. at 522–24.

102 Footnote Id. at 512–13. In a partial dissent, Judge Niemeyer disagreed with the majority on this point. Footnote Id. at 524 (Niemeyer, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).

103 194 F.3d at 522.

104 Footnote Id. at 517.

105 Desnick v. Am. Broad. Companies, Inc., 44 F.3d 1345 (7th Cir. 1995).

106 Footnote Id. at 1351.

107 Footnote Id. at 1352.

108 Compare Wasden, 878 F.3d at 1196 (holding that a trespass does not occur when an investigator secures consent to enter a business property by deception); Food Lion, 194 F.3d at 518 (same); Desnick, 44 F.3d at 1352 (same) with Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Reynolds, 8 F.4th 781, 786 (8th Cir. 2021). Two federal judges have dissented in Ag Gag cases, taking the position that misrepresentation vitiates consent to enter land. See Kelly, 9 F.4th at 1250 (Hartz, J., dissenting); Wasden, 878 F.3d at 1211 (Bea, J., dissenting in part and concurring in part).

109 194 F.3d at 516.

111 Footnote Id. at 518.

112 Footnote Id. at 517 (emphasis added). The Fourth Circuit also overturned the jury’s fraud verdict on Food Lion’s common law and statutory fraud claims. Footnote Id. at 512–13, 519–20.

113 194 F.3d at 520–22 (citing Cohen v. Cowles Media Co., 501 U.S. 663, 669 (1991); Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 684 (1972)).

114 194 F.3d at 521.

115 New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 278 (1964).

116 See generally Cody Carlson, The Ag Gag Laws: Hiding Factory Farm Abuses from Public Scrutiny, The Atlantic, Mar. 20, 2012, https://www.theatlantic.com/health/archive/2012/03/the-ag-gag-laws-hiding-factory-farm-abuses-from-public-scrutiny/254674/.

117 See, e.g., Reynolds I, 8 F.4th at 786. Dissenting judges in some of the other cases asserted this same position. Kelly, 9 F.4th at 1250 (Hartz, J., dissenting); Wasden, 878 F.3d at 1211 (Bea, J., dissenting in part and concurring in part).

118 Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Herbert, 263 F. Supp. 3d 1193 (D. Utah 2017).

119 Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Kelly, 9 F.4th 1219 (10th Cir. 2021).

120 194 F.3d at 518.

122 Footnote Id. at 516.

123 Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

124 Footnote Id. See also Food Lion, Inc. v. Cap. Cities/ABC, Inc., 964 F. Supp. 956, 964 (M.D.N.C. 1997), aff’d on other grounds, 194 F.3d 505 (4th Cir. 1999).

125 Siegel Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

126 Food Lion, Inc. v. Cap. Cities/ABC, Inc., 951 F. Supp. 1224, 1230 (M.D.N.C. 1996).

127 Dalton v. Camp, 353 N.C. 647, 653 (2001).

128 Riedy & Sperduto, supra Footnote note 81, at 272.

130 516 U.S. 85 (1995).

131 Footnote Id. at 93.

132 Footnote Id. at 94–95 (quoting Restatement (Second) of Agency §226, at 498) (emphasis by the Court).

133 Food Lion, 194 F.3d at 514.

135 Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 36–74. We argue in favor of a journalistic ethics standard grounded in the liberal theory and interpretation and activism theories, which both match well with a utilitarian model that weighs the value of the information discovered against any social harms that might be caused by an undercover investigation. Having said this, I do not take the counterarguments on the ethics of undercover investigations lightly. After all, utilitarian arguments can be highly subjective and tied to the value judgments of the person making them. One person may value newsgathering more highly than property and privacy interests, even in a business setting, while another may simply disagree. This makes it difficult to center an ethical claim on any form of general consensus. On the other hand, at least utilitarian arguments are transparent about their justifications, enabling society and individuals ultimately to make their own judgments.

136 See, e.g., Ethical Journalism: A Handbook of Values and Practices for the News and Editorial Departments – Pursuing the News, N.Y. Times, www.nytimes.com/editorial-standards/ethical-journalism.html#. The Times does not indicate an initial publication date for the Handbook though it references a Newsroom Integrity Statement, published in 1999.

137 Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 60–62.

138 1996 SPJ Code of Ethics, supra Footnote note 49.

139 Society of Professional Journalists, Society of Professional Journalists – 1973 Code of Ethics, https://spjnetwork.org/quill2/codedcontroversey/ethics-code-1973.pdf.

140 1996 SPJ Code of Ethics, supra Footnote note 49.

141 Jacqueline Sharkey, Taking the Fight to the Classroom, 20 Am. Journalism Rev. 12 (1998); Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

142 Sharkey, supra Footnote note 141, at 12.

146 Seth Stern, Is It Time to Revisit Undercover Journalism?, Freedom of the Press Foundation (Oct. 31, 2023), https://freedom.press/news/is-it-time-to-revisit-undercover-journalism/

150 See Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

152 Siegel Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

153 Stern, supra Footnote note 146.

154 People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, Inc. v. N. Carolina Farm Bureau Fed’n, Inc., 60 F.4th 815 (4th Cir. 2023) (cleaned up).

155 Stern, supra Footnote note 146.

156 Erik Wemple, Verdict Upends Project Veritas’s Journalism Defense in Infiltration Case, Wash. Post (Sept. 23, 2022), https://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/2022/09/23/project-veritas-democracy-partners-verdict/.

160 Sonja R. West, Awakening the Press Clause, 58 UCLA L. Rev. 1025, 1027 (2011).

162 Press-Enterprise Co. v. Superior Ct, 478 U.S. 1 (1986); Richmond Newspapers, Inc. v. Virginia, 448 U.S. 555 (1980) (plurality opinion).

163 Cohen v. Cowles Media Co., 501 U.S. 663 (1991).

164 Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665 (1972).

165 Footnote Id. at 680.

166 Footnote Id. at 682.

168 Footnote Id. at 681. It’s also worth noting that there is a seamless connection between Branzburg and undercover investigations that has heretofore gone unrecognized. To the extent that no constitutional privilege exists to protect confidential informants, the law places greater pressure on journalists to find other ways to gather and disseminate information of broad public concern. Undercover investigations might at least partially fill that information gap, but only if there is some constitutional protection for conducting them.

169 Cohen v. Cowles Media Co., 501 U.S. 663 (1991).

170 Footnote Id. at 668–69.

171 Footnote Id. at 669.

172 See, e.g., Bruno & Stillman, Inc. v. Globe Newspaper Co., 633 F.2d 583, 595–96 (1st Cir. 1980); Silkwood v. Kerr-McGee Corp., 563 F.2d 433, 436–37 (10th Cir. 1977).

173 Branzburg, 408 U.S. at 681.

174 People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, Inc. v. N. Carolina Farm Bureau Fed’n, Inc., 60 F.4th 815, 825–26 (4th Cir. 2023) (cleaned up); Animal Legal Def. Fund v. Wasden, 878 F.3d 1184, 1190 (9th Cir. 2018).

175 Blake D. Morant, The Endemic Reality of Media Ethics and Self-Restraint, 19 Notre Dame J.L. Ethics & Pub. Pol’y 595, 618 (2005) (“As a generalized rule, self-regulation diminishes the need for external regulation of the [news media] industry.”).

176 Footnote Id. at 609.

177 See, e.g., The Fla. Star v. B.J.F., 491 U.S. 524 (1989); Cox Broad. Corp. v. Cohn, 420 U.S. 469 (1975).

178 Morant, supra Footnote note 175, at 609.

179 Footnote Id. at 609–11.

180 For a comprehensive discussion of these ethical debates, see Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 36–74.

181 See, e.g., Ethical Journalism, supra Footnote note 136.

182 There is an ongoing and important scholarly debate about the meaning of the Press Clause. Some legal scholars have argued for a more functional approach to applying the Press Clause, meaning that the constitutional protections extend to any person engaged in newsgathering, rather than only those who work for the institutional press. See, e.g., Ugland, supra Footnote note 3, at 137; Linda L. Berger, Shielding the Unmedia: Using the Process of Journalism to Protect the Journalist’s Privilege in an Infinite Universe of Publication, 39 Hous. L. Rev. 137, 137 (2003). Under that view, the Press Clause could be read to protect undercover investigations by the institutional media and other actors. Others contend that a functional approach is too broad, erasing the distinction between the Speech and Press Clauses, and paradoxically undermining the rights of the press and the distinct role the press plays in promoting democracy. See, e.g., West, supra Footnote note 160, at 1032. This view, of course, is more consistent with the First Amendment’s text.

183 See West, supra Footnote note 160, at 1056 (observing that a narrower reading of the Press Clause’s scope might actually lead to more expansive, albeit not unlimited, constitutional protection for the press).

184 N.C. Gen. Stat. Ann. § 99A-2

185 People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, Inc. v. N. Carolina Farm Bureau Fed’n, Inc., 60 F.4th 815, 821 (4th Cir. 2023) (cleaned up).

186 Ashutosh Bhagwat, Producing Speech, 56 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1029, 1065 (2015).

187 See, e.g., Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5; Chen, Investigative Deception, supra Footnote note 5; Marceau & Chen, Video Age, supra Footnote note 5; Chen & Marceau, High Value Lies, supra Footnote note 5.

188 Eugene Volokh, Freedom for the Press as an Industry, or for the Press as a Technology? From the Framing to Today, 160 U. Pa. L. Rev. 459, 524 (2012).

189 Chen & Marceau, Truth and Transparency, supra Footnote note 5, at 264–65.

191 Footnote Id. at 265.

197 Chen & Marceau, High Value Lies, supra Footnote note 5, at 1463.

198 Of course, employers may require their employees to sign nondisclosure agreements that may address this confidentiality concern. Whether an undercover investigation privilege might render such agreements unenforceable is beyond the scope of this chapter.

199 Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

200 See supra Footnote notes 44Footnote 47 and accompanying text.

201 Barnett/Dale Interview, supra Footnote note 4.

15 The Enduring Significance of New York Times v. Sullivan

1 New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 273 (1964). This chapter draws heavily on my book Actual Malice: Civil Rights and Freedom of the Press in New York Times v. Sullivan (2023).

2 Michael M. Grynbaum, Trump Renews Pledge to “Take a Strong Look” at Libel Laws, N.Y. Times (Jan. 10, 2018), https://www.nytimes.com/2018/01/10/business/media/trump-libel-laws.html.

3 Michael M. Grynbaum, Trump Sues CNN for Defamation, Seeking $475 Million, N.Y. Times (Oct. 3, 2022), https://www.nytimes.com/2022/10/03/business/media/trump-cnn-lawsuit.html.

4 Bruce D. Brown & Gabe Rottman, Sarah Palin’s Fight Against The New York Times Shows the Free Press Isn’t Safe, Time (Oct. 19, 2022, 4:04 PM), https://time.com/6223268/sarah-palin-wants-weaker-protections-for-the-press/.

5 Berisha v. Lawson, 141 S.Ct. 2424, 2424–25 (2021) (Thomas, J., dissenting); Footnote id. at 2425–30 (Gorsuch, J., dissenting); Adam Liptak, Two Justices Say Supreme Court Should Reconsider Landmark Decision, N.Y. Times (July 2, 2021), https://www.nytimes.com/2021/07/02/us/supreme-court-libel.html; see also McKee v. Cosby, 139 S.Ct. 675, 676 (2019) (Thomas, J., concurring).

6 Tah v. Global Witness Publishing, Inc., 991 F.3d 231, 251 (D.C. Cir. 2021) (Silberman, J., dissenting). Jeremy W. Peters, Sarah Palin’s Libel Claim Against The Times Is Rejected by a Jury, N.Y. Times (Feb. 15, 2022), https://www.nytimes.com/2022/02/15/business/media/new-york-times.html; Lawrence Hurley, Supreme Court Turns Away Coal Baron’s Defamation Claim, NBC News (Oct. 10, 2023, 9:51 AM), https://www.nbcnews.com/politics/supreme-court-turns-away-coal-barons-defamation-claim-news-companies-rcna118036.

8 Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 300.

9 Kimmerle v. N.Y. Evening J., Inc., 186 N.E. 217, 218 (N.Y. 1933).

10 William Blake Odgers, A Digest of the Law of Libel and Slander with the Evidence, Procedure, Practice, and Precedents of Pleadings, Both in Civil and Criminal Cases 21 (1896).

11 Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 267.

12 Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568, 572 (1942); Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U.S. 250, 266 (1952).

13 David L. Lewis, The Public Image of Henry Ford: An American Folk Hero and His Company 106 (1987); Henry Ford Files $1,000,000 Libel Suit; Resents Chicago Tribune’s Charge of Anarchy in Connection with Enlistment of His Employees, N.Y. Times, Sept. 8, 1916, at 18.

14 Roosevelt, Winning Libel Suit, Is Awarded 6 Cents, San Francisco Call, June 1, 1913, at 1.

15 Barbas, supra Footnote note 1, at 23.

16 Footnote Id. at 24.

17 David Wallace, Massive Resistance and Media Suppression: The Segregationist Response to Dissent during the Civil Rights Movement (2013).

18 Barbas, supra Footnote note 1, at 36; Gene Roberts & Hank Klibanoff, The Race Beat: The Press, the Civil Rights Struggle, and the Awakening of a Nation 185–91 (2006).

19 Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 260.

22 Sullivan appears to have permitted white mobs to assault protesters, turning his police on them only after they had attacked the protesters. Police Thwart Negro Services at Capitol, Montgomery Advertiser, Mar. 7, 1960, at 1; Claude Sitton, Negroes Dispersed in Alabama March; Attacked by Whites, N.Y. Times, Mar. 7, 1960, at 1.

23 Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 256.

24 Alabama Governor Sues for $1,000,000, N.Y. Times, May 31, 1960, at 20.

25 The offending articles were Harrison E. Salisbury, Fear and Hatred Grip Birmingham, N.Y. Times, Apr. 12, 1960, at 1, 28, and Race Issues Shakes Alabama Structure, N.Y. Times, Apr. 13, 1960, at 1, 33.

26 Barbas, supra Footnote note 1, at 85.

27 Footnote Id. at 98–99.

28 Samantha Barbas, New York Times v. Sullivan: Perspectives from History, 30 Geo. Mason L. Rev. F. 1 (2023), https://lawreview.gmu.edu/forum/new-york-times-v-sullivan-perspectives-from-history/.

29 Alex Jones & Susan Tifft, The Trust: The Private and Powerful Family behind the New York Times 320 (1999).

30 James Goodale, Is the Public “Getting Even” with the Press in Libel Cases?, 188 N.Y.L.J. 29 (1982).

31 Freedom Forum Institute, Silencing the Press, NewseumED, https://newseumed.org/tools/video-page/silencing-press (last visited June 30, 2024).

32 Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 255.

33 $500,000 Damages Awarded Sullivan by Times Suit Jury, Montgomery Advertiser, Nov. 4, 1960, at 1.

34 Brief for Trib. Co. as Amicus Curiae Supporting Petitioner at 12, New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964) (No. 39).

35 John Herbers, Libel Actions Ask Millions in South: 17 Suits by Public Officials Are Pending in Courts, N.Y. Times, Apr. 4, 1964, at 12.

36 Barbas, supra Footnote note 1, at 154.

37 Libel or Revenge?, 2 Colum. Journalism Rev. (Fall 1963), at 2.

38 Abernathy v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964).

39 Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 276.

40 Brief for the Petitioner at 2, New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964) (No. 39).

44 Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 286.

45 Barbas, supra Footnote note 1, at 200–15.

46 Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 273.

47 Footnote Id. at 270.

48 Footnote Id. at 282.

49 Footnote Id. at 271.

50 Footnote Id. at 279.

51 Footnote Id. at 270–71.

52 Anders Walker, Neutral Principles: Rethinking the Legal History of Civil Rights, 1934–1964, 40 Loy. U. Chi. L.J. 385 (2009).

53 Anthony Lewis, Make No Law: The Sullivan Case and the First Amendment 158 (1991).

16 Returning FOIA to the Press

Portions of this chapter were adapted from a Keynote Address given by the author at the Access and Accountability Conference at Yale University in 2021.

1 Nat’l Archives & Recs. Admin. v. Favish, 541 U.S. 157, 171–72 (2004).

2 See generally, e.g., Gannett Co. v. DePasquale, 443 U.S. 368 (1979); Richmond Newspapers, Inc. v. Virginia, 448 U.S. 555 (1980); Globe Newspaper Co. v. Super. Ct., 457 U.S. 596 (1982); Press-Enterprise Co. v. Super. Ct. (1984).

3 5 U.S.C. § 552.

4 See Margaret B. Kwoka, Saving the Freedom of Information Act 23–25 (2021).

6 5 U.S.C. § 552(a)(6)(A)(i); Footnote id. § 552(b).

7 U.S. Dep’t of Just., Off. of Info. Pol’y, Summary of Annual FOIA Reports for Fiscal Year 2022, at 2 (2023), https://www.justice.gov/oip/page/file/1581856/dl?inline [hereinafter OIP Report].

8 Kwoka, supra Footnote note 4, at 3, 175–78; Paul McMasters, FOIA: It’s Always There, Soc’y of Pro. Journalists (Oct. 1996), https://www.spj.org/foiabout.asp; Delayed, Denied, Dismissed: Failures on the FOIA Front, ProPublica (July 21, 2016), https://www.propublica.org/article/delayed-denied-dismissed-failures-on-the-foia-front. Cf. Jake Lucas, How Times Reporters Use the Freedom of Information Act, N.Y. Times (July 21, 2018), https://www.nytimes.com/2018/07/21/insider/information-freedom-reporters-pruitt.html (while purporting to describe successful uses of FOIA, quoting one frequent requester reporter as saying, “FOIA is basically useless if you don’t file a lawsuit to force the government to act.”).

9 FOIA Project Staff, FOIA Suits Rise Because Agencies Don’t Respond Even as Requesters Wait Longer to File Suit, FOIA Project (Dec. 15, 2019), https://foiaproject.org/2019/12/15/foia-suits-rise-because-agencies-dont-respond-even-as-requesters-wait-longer-to-file-suit [hereinafter FOIA Suits Rise]; Nat’l Archives & Recs. Admin., 2020–2022 Freedom of Information Act Federal Advisory Committee Final Report and Recommendations 25 (2022), https://www.archives.gov/files/ogis/assets/foiaac-final-report-and-recs-2022-07-05.pdf; Knight Found., Forecasting Freedom of Information 8 (2017), https://knightfoundation.org/wp-content/uploads/2020/03/FOI-final-unlink.pdf.

10 See FOIA Improvement Act of 2016, Pub. L. No. 114-185, 130 Stat. 538 (2016); OPEN Government Act of 2007, Pub. L. No. 110-175, 121 Stat. 2524 (2007).

11 OIP Report, supra Footnote note 7, at 12.

12 Staff of H.R. Comm. on Oversight & Gov’t Reform, 114th Cong., FOIA Is Broken: A Report iv (2016), https://oversight.house.gov/wp-content/uploads/2016/01/FINAL-FOIA-Report-January-2016.pdf.

13 FOIA Backlogs Hinder Government Transparency and Accountability, U.S. Gov’t Accountability Off. (Mar. 14, 2024), https://www.gao.gov/blog/foia-backlogs-hinder-government-transparency-and-accountability.

14 Delayed, Denied, Dismissed, ProPublica, supra Footnote note 8.

15 Kwoka, supra Footnote note 4, at 175–76.

16 Margaret B. Kwoka, An Information Commission, 112 Geo. L.J. 841, 855–57 (forthcoming 2024).

17 U.S. Dep’t of Interior, Off. of Inspector Gen., No. 2019-ER-057, Lack of Tracking and Unclear Guidance Identified in the U.S. Department of the Interior’s Awareness Review Process for Freedom of Information Act Requests (2022), https://www.oversight.gov/sites/default/files/oig-reports/DOI/Final-Report-FOIAAwareness.pdf.

18 See, e.g., OPEN Government Act of 2007, Pub. L. No. 110-175, 121 Stat. 2527 (2007) (codified as amended at 5 U.S.C. § 552(a)(4)(A)(viii)(I) (2007)) (providing that “an agency shall not assess any search fees (or in the case of a requester described under clause (ii)(II) of this subparagraph, duplication fees) under this subparagraph if the agency has failed to comply with any time limit under paragraph (6).”)

19 Kwoka, supra Footnote note 4, at 136–48.

20 OIP Report, supra Footnote note 7, at 3. While DOJ has yet to compile a government-wide summary report for FY 2023, DHS’s own FY 2023 Annual FOIA report shows even higher numbers of total requests received. U.S. Dep’t of Homeland Sec., Fiscal Year 2023 Freedom of Information Act Report to the Attorney General of the United States and the Director of the Office of Government Information Services 13 (Mar. 2024), https://www.dhs.gov/sites/default/files/2024-03/23_0325_fy23-FOIA_Annual_Report.pdf.

21 Kwoka, supra Footnote note 4, at 172 (describing a characterization made by James Holzer, Deputy Chief FOIA Officer at DHS, that 96 percent of the agency’s FOIA requests are first-person). My own data gathering suggested the same. At the three largest components of DHS, the percentage of first-person requests in the data I sampled was even higher. See Footnote id. at 81 (providing figures suggesting first-person requests made up approximately 99 percent of requests at USCIS, 98 percent at ICE, and 97 percent at CBP).

22 Footnote Id. at 103.

23 See Footnote id. at 93–115 (documenting many such examples).

24 Kwoka, supra Footnote note 4, at 172–73.

25 Footnote Id. at 173.

27 5 U.S.C. § 552(e). See also Annual FOIA Reports, U.S. Dep’t of Just., Off. of Info. Pol’y, https://www.justice.gov/oip/reports-1.

28 See generally Margaret B. Kwoka, FOIA, Inc., 65 Duke L. J. 1361 (2016) (documenting the variety of commercial uses of FOIA, including at these named agencies).

29 See Footnote id. at 1376–77.

30 See, e.g., U.S. Sec. & Exch. Comm’n, FOIA Annual Report 10 (2023), https://www.sec.gov/files/arfoia23.pdf (reporting that the SEC took a median of four days to process simple requests and twenty-seven days to process complex requests in fiscal year 2023).

31 Margaret B. Kwoka, First-Person FOIA, 127 Yale L.J. 2204, 2244, 2249 (2018). See also generally Nightingale v. U.S. Citizenship & Immigr. Servs., 507 F. Supp. 3d 1193 (N.D. Cal. 2020).

32 Kwoka, supra Footnote note 28, at 1389–91, 1430.

33 5 U.S.C. § 552(a)(4).

34 Margaret B. Kwoka, Deferring to Secrecy, 54 B.C. L. Rev. 185 (2013); EPA v. Mink, 410 U.S. 73 (1973); Freedom of Information Act, Pub. L. No. 93-502, 88 Stat. 1561 (1974) (codified as amended at 5 U.S.C. § 552).

35 James T. Hamilton, FOIA and Investigative Reporting: Who’s Asking What, Where, When – And Why It Matters, in Troubling Transparency: The History and Future of Freedom of Information 116, 121–23 (David E. Pozen & Michael Schudson eds., 2018).

36 Telephone Interview with Charles Seife, Professor, N.Y.U. (Feb. 15, 2019).

37 Telephone Interview with Seth Freed Wessler, Freelance Investigative Reporter (Apr. 10, 2019).

38 Telephone Interview with David McCraw, Deputy Gen. Counsel, N.Y. Times, and Al-Amyn Sumar, First Amendment Fellow, N.Y. Times (May 3, 2019).

39 FOIA Suits Rise, supra Footnote note 9.

40 Kwoka, supra Footnote note 34; Meredith Fuchs, Judging Secrets: The Role Courts Should Play in Preventing Unnecessary Secrecy, 58 Admin. L. Rev. 131, 163–68 (2006); Susan Nevelow Mart & Tom Ginsburg, [Dis-]Informing the People’s Discretion: Judicial Deference Under the National Security Exemption of the Freedom of Information Act, 66 Admin. L. Rev. 725 (2014).

41 Margaret B. Kwoka & Michael Karanicolas, Overseeing Oversight, 54 Conn. L. Rev. 655, 659 (2022).

42 Footnote Id. at 679–88.

43 Vivek Ramkumar & Diego de la Mora, Mexico’s Battle for Transparency, U.S. News & World Rep. (Feb. 13, 2016), https://www.usnews.com/news/best-countries/articles/2016-02-13/mexicos-battle-for-transparency; Paul Lagunes & Oscar Pocasangre, Dynamic Transparency: An Audit of Mexico’s Freedom of Information Act, 97 Pub. Admin. 162, 162–63 (2019).

44 My work at INAI was conducted pursuant to a cooperative work agreement between myself and INAI, as well as two rulings by The Ohio State University Institutional Review Board that my interviews both of government officials and journalists were exempt from IRB approval procedures. See Letter from INAI, Propuesta de Proyecto de Cooperación con Margaret Kwoka (Oct. 24, 2022) (on file with author); Letter from Ohio State University, Office of Responsible Research Practices to Margaret Kwoka, Study No. 2022E0709 (Aug. 4, 2022); Letter from Ohio State University, Office of Responsible Research Practices to Margaret Kwoka, Study No. 2022E0696 (Aug. 4, 2022).

45 Margaret B. Kwoka, Transparency Guardians (2024) (unpublished manuscript) (on file with author).

46 Plataforma Nacional De Transparencia (PNT), https://www.plataformadetransparencia.org.mx.

47 INAI, Informe De Labores 58 (2022), https://micrositios.inai.org.mx/informesinai. A subset of those decisions are ones in which the requester wins in part.

48 See generally Footnote id.; see also Interview with Ileana Hidalgo Rioja, Secretaria del Acceso de la Informacion [Secretary of Access to Information], INAI, in Mexico City, Mex. (Mar. 9, 2023), at 6–7 (transcript on file with author).

49 Ley Federal de Transparencia y Acceso a la Información Pública (Federal Law of Transparency and Access to Public Information), at art. 43. Cf. Estrena INAI la serie ‘Derecho a saber’ que se transmitirá en el canal del Congreso, El Heraldo de México (Mar. 23, 2022), https://heraldodemexico.com.mx/nacional/2022/3/23/estrena-inai-la-serie-derecho-saber-que-se-transmitira-en-el-canal-del-congreso-389703.html.

50 As INAI’s YouTube channel shows, the commissioners often make public appearances as part of their role. See INAI, YouTube, https://www.youtube.com/@ifaimexico/videos.

51 INEGI, Censo Nacional de Transparencia, Acceso a la Información Pública y Protección de Datos Personales 2023, at 19, 22 (May 2024), https://www.inegi.org.mx/contenidos/programas/cntaippdpf/2023/doc/cntaippdpf_2023_resultados.pdf.

52 Interview with Alejandra Ibarra Chaoul, Periodista & Autora, in Mexico City, Mex. (May 24, 2023), at 8 (transcript on file with author).

53 Interview with Anonymous Journalist, in Mexico City, Mex. (May 12, 2023), at 16 (transcript on file with author).

54 Zoom Interview with Gabriela Villegas Ramirez, Journalist, Univision Texas (May 30, 2023), at 5 (interview conducted in Spanish; transcript on file with author). See also Interview with Efraín Tzuc Salinas, Periodista de Datos, Quinto Elemento Lab, in Mexico City, Mex. (May 30, 2023), at 9 (“I think that the Institute [INAI] is important that it exists.”) (interview conducted in Spanish; transcript on file with author).

55 Anonymous Journalist, supra Footnote note 53, at 3–4.

56 Gabriela Villegas Ramirez, supra Footnote note 54, at 5.

57 Efraín Tzuc Salinas, supra Footnote note 54, at 4–5.

58 Interview with Iván Benumea Gómez, Coordinador del Programa de Justicia Fiscal [Coordinator of the Tax Justice Program], FUNDAR, in Mexico City, Mex. (June 8, 2023), at 3 (interview conducted in Spanish; transcript on file with author) (author’s translation).

59 Efraín Tzuc Salinas, supra Footnote note 54, at 4–5; Iván Benumea Gómez, supra Footnote note 58, at 3.

60 Anonymous Journalist, supra Footnote note 53, at 1.

61 Gabriela Villegas Ramirez, supra Footnote note 54, at 7.

62 Iván Benumea Gómez, supra Footnote note 58, at 3.

63 Alejandra Ibarra Chaoul, supra Footnote note 52, at 2; Iván Benumea Gómez, supra Footnote note 58, at 4; Efraín Tzuc Salinas, supra Footnote note 54, at 6.

64 Efraín Tzuc Salinas, supra Footnote note 54, at 8.

65 Alejandra Ibarra Chaoul, supra Footnote note 52, at 7.

66 See James Wagner & Emiliano Rodríguez Mega, Why Mexico Is Eliminating Independent Watchdog Agencies, N.Y. Times (Nov. 28, 2024), https://www.nytimes.com/2024/11/28/world/americas/mexico-senate-watchdog-agencies.html.

67 See, e.g., Local Journalism Sustainability Act, H.R. 3940, 117th Cong. (2021); S. 2434, 117th Cong. (2021) (proposing tax credits for supporting local media as well as payroll tax credits for journalism outlets to pay employees); Christina Koningisor & Lyrissa Lidsky, First Amendment Disequilibrium, 110 Va. L. Rev. 1, 67 (2024) (suggesting a variety of creative funding models for the press, including philanthropic support and public funding); Press Release, MacArthur Foundation, $48 Million in Support of Local News, Initial Seeding of Press Forward Collaborative (Dec. 18, 2023), https://www.macfound.org/press/press-releases/macarthur-announces-$48-million-in-support-of-local-news-initial-seeding-of-press-forward-collaborative (announcing a grant program for local media). Authors in this series have made similar suggestions. See, e.g., Lili Levi, Countering the Mosaic of Threats to Press Functions, in The Future of Press Freedom: Democracy, Law, and the News in Changing Times 79 (RonNell Andersen Jones & Sonja R. West eds., 2025).

68 Kwoka & Karanicolas, Oversight, supra Footnote note 41, at 675–78.

69 Kwoka, supra Footnote note 16, at 873–85.

70 See Int’l Inst. for Democracy & Electoral Assistance, The Global State of Democracy 2022: Forging Social Contracts in a Time of Discontent (2022), https://www.idea.int/democracytracker/sites/default/files/2022-11/the-global-state-of-democracy-2022.pdf (exploring global trends putting democracy at risk and setting out policy recommendations to “reinvigorate” democratic reform).

Accessibility standard: Unknown

Accessibility compliance for the HTML of this book is currently unknown and may be updated in the future.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge-org.demo.remotlog.com is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×