Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-smtgx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-09-13T14:53:28.717Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Insult and Injury: Toward a Comprehensive Account of Discrimination

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 August 2025

Christine Bratu*
Affiliation:
Philosophisches Seminar, Georg-August-University Göttingen, Göttingen, Germany
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Standard conceptions of discrimination cannot account for all that is morally wrong about discrimination, as they cannot explain how individual acts of discrimination wrong not only their direct target but also all members of the targeted social group. In response to this lacuna, I develop a comprehensive account according to which discrimination consists of two interdependent wrongs: to discriminate against B, A must, first, treat B worse than C in a way that is grave enough to make this differential treatment morally wrong; and second, A must do so in a way that is disrespectful to B and to the social group B is perceived to belong to.

Information

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Inc

1. Introduction

Imagine the following situation:

(Committee) The philosophy department at X University wants to hire a new associate professor. B, a young white woman, is by far the most qualified candidate for the position. During the search committee’s final discussion, A, a tenured professor with considerable standing within the department, states the following: “B is obviously a bad choice. Sure, her publications are very impressive, she received a number of prestigious grants, and the students appreciate her as a dedicated teacher. But she seems so meek and timid, just like a little girl—she just doesn’t have what it takes to be part of our department!” Because of A’s disparaging comment, B does not get the job. Instead, the search committee hires C, a male candidate, whose gender does not come up even once during the search committee’s discussion.

Since B is the most qualified candidate, she is unjustifiably wronged by not being offered the job. To make matters worse, the decisive factor in her rejection is a well-known stereotype about (white) women in professional contexts, namely, that they are not sufficiently assertive. Aside from being false, this stereotype is belittling and brings in considerations that, given B’s demonstrable qualifications, should be irrelevant in the situation. Also, B is treated differently than C, whose gender is not alluded to during the committee’s discussion. In light of all this, “Committee” should be considered a clear-cut case of (sexist) discrimination.Footnote 1

Now imagine, if you will, that you find yourself in the situation of a member of the search committee who identifies as a woman. As a woman, how would A’s sexist comment and the committee’s decision to go along with it make you feel? I, for one, would have two interconnected gut reactions: First and foremost, I would feel outrage on behalf of B who is clearly and blatantly being discriminated against in virtue of her gender. But in addition, I would also feel offended personally. Something like the following would be very much on my mind: “What the heck?! This is so unfair toward B! How dare A say such things in front of me and the other women here? And how do the others dare to just go along with it? This sexist tripe is such an insult to all of us!” I would walk away from the situation feeling outraged because A’s comment and the search committee’s decision wronged not only B, but also every other person who identifies as a woman, including myself. My outrage would be nuanced, though. Specifically, I would not feel that I and every other woman had been wronged just as badly as B had (if I did this, I would be making the whole situation about myself), but insist that B had been wronged in a particularly egregious way. But overall, I would feel that B was entitled to some form of compensation for the unfair treatment she suffered and that all women, including B and myself, were owed an apology by A.

At the heart of this gut reaction lies the intuition that a discriminatory action x that targets some person B who is perceived to belong to some social group G primarily wrongs its direct target B, but it somehow also wrongs every other member of G. Let us call this intuition the all-of-us intuition. My main aim in this article is to develop a comprehensive conception of discrimination that takes this intuition into account. To be clear, even though I contend that the gut reaction I just sketched is one that many people experience in comparable situations (which makes it a good candidate for being taken seriously), I do not believe that philosophical theorizing is slavishly bound to the intuitions we happen to have. Rather, I claim that by accommodating this particular intuition we achieve a more comprehensive understanding of all that is wrong with discrimination and of why it is so important to fight it. Footnote 2 Moreover, my conception allows us to identify instances of discrimination more easily than its competitors and, I will argue, it also provides us with a novel answer to the challenge of indirect discrimination.

I proceed as follows: in Section 2, I introduce two prominent conceptions of discrimination and show that neither of them can do justice to the all-of-us intuition. Analyzing the different ways in which these two conceptions fail, I set out in detail what is needed to accommodate this intuition properly. In Section 3, I present my own comprehensive conception of discrimination and argue that, in contrast to other conceptions on offer, it can do justice to the all-of-us intuition. I also point out other significant ways in which my account differs from others and explain why it is important to accommodate the all-of-us intuition in the first place. In Section 4, I explore two other considerations in favor of my comprehensive conception. The first of these concerns its applicability, while the second centers on the issue of indirect discrimination. In Section 5, I discuss and ultimately dismiss two possible objections that would try to show my account to be under-inclusive rather than comprehensive. Section 6 concludes.

Two more clarifications before I begin. First, philosophers working on the issue disagree about whether discrimination is always at least pro tanto morally problematic or whether there can be morally neutral instances of discrimination, in other words, whether “discrimination” always has some negative evaluative meaning or whether we can also use this term in a purely descriptive way (see Wasserman, Reference Wasserman and Chadwick1998, Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 25, Eidelson, Reference Eidelson2015, 14, Altman, Reference Altman and Zalta2020, 1.2). Those who claim the latter note that it often seems to be a genuinely open question whether some action x that discriminates between B and C is also morally wrong. For instance, is it morally problematic, even pro tanto, to discriminate between people who are shortsighted and those with 20/20 vision when it comes to issuing pilot licenses? In contrast, those who argue for a moralized understanding of “discrimination” insist that, since as philosophers we are mostly interested in the morally problematic instances of discrimination, we might as well use the term in a way that reflects this interest (see Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 4). I share this sentiment and, thus, the understanding of discrimination I argue for is a moralized one. I invite those who disagree with such an approach on conceptual grounds to simply understand my contribution as one to the debate about the wrongs of discrimination rather than as one to the debate about what constitutes discrimination in the first place.

Second, these debates commonly distinguish between instances of direct and indirect discrimination (see Altman, Reference Altman and Zalta2020; Khaitan, Reference Khaitan and Lippert-Rasmussen2018). I discuss indirect discrimination in Section 4 and, unless otherwise indicated, I use “discrimination” to refer to direct discrimination.

2. Two Competing Conceptions of Discrimination

As mentioned, I contend that the account of discrimination presented here allows us to understand discrimination in a more comprehensive way than other philosophical accounts on offer. As an in-depth survey of all alternative proposals would far exceed the limits of this article, I focus on the views presented by Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen and Deborah Hellman. Lippert-Rasmussen’s definition of discrimination in particular serves as a blueprint for most of the ongoing debate.Footnote 3 Showing that his account cannot do justice to the all-of-us intuition therefore is tantamount to showing that most of the contemporary debate about discrimination, too, fails to do so. In contrast, Hellman’s view is useful because, while it ultimately cannot accommodate the all-of-us intuition either, the way it falls short contains lessons for taking the intuition into account successfully.

Let us start with Lippert-Rasmussen’s conception of discrimination.

DiscriminationLippert-Rasmussen: A discriminates against B in relation to C by x-ing if (1) there is a property P such that (A believes that) B has P and (A believes that) C does not have P; (2) A treats B worse than C by x-ing; (3) it is because (A believes that) B has P and (A believes that) C does not have P that A treats B worse than C by x-ing; (4) P is the property of being a member of a certain “socially salient” group G (to which C does not belong); and (5) x-ing is a relevant type of act etc. and there are many acts etc. of this type, and this fact makes people with P (or some subgroup of these) worse off relative to others, or x-ing is a relevant type of act etc. and many acts etc. of this type would make people with P worse off relative to others, or A’s x-ing is motivated by animosity toward individuals with P or by the belief that individuals who have P are inferior to or ought not to intermingle with others. (Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 46–47, modified)

The general idea behind this conception is that discriminatory actions are instances of differential treatment that come about because of their targets’ (perceived) membership in some social group. Let us take a look at each condition. (1) stipulates that the target must belong to a specific social group or must be taken by the perpetrator to belong to a specific social group. Lippert-Rasmussen thereby wants to make room for what we might call misdirected discrimination, that is, instances of discrimination in which the perpetrator targets a person because they mistakenly believe them to belong to some social group. Intuitively, it should still count as discrimination if a person is not hired in virtue of being taken to be gay, for example, even if they are not. (4) spells out the social groups Lippert-Rasmussen is interested in, which he calls “socially salient.” According to him, a group is socially salient “if perceived membership of it is important to the structure of social interactions across a wide range of social contexts” (Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 30). On this conception, dentists do not count as a socially salient group because there are few social interactions structured around being a dentist aside from those related to oral health care and perhaps some professional perks (invitations to annual conventions and the like). In contrast, women constitute a socially salient group because being perceived as a woman matters on the job market, in one’s dating life, for one’s health care and safety, etc. (3) states that discriminatory actions occur because of their targets’ perceived group membership. According to Lippert-Rasmussen this means that the target’s group membership is part of the agent’s motivating reason for x-ing, for instance, when racist employers refuse to hire Black people because they falsely believe Black people to be incompetent or because they are afraid of them (Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 72–73). (5) is best understood as Lippert-Rasmussen’s attempt to tweak his definition to accommodate two recalcitrant examples. The first one concerns “a man who, despite falling in love with another man who reciprocates his love, rejects the latter’s advances because he is a man” (Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 26). According to Lippert-Rasmussen, “it seems very strained to say that he discriminates against such a person” (Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 27), just as it would seem strained to say that gay people discriminate against straight people and vice versa. But since being male or being gay or straight are socially salient properties and since being romantically rejected in favor of someone else certainly counts as a way of being treated worse than somebody else, both cases would qualify as discrimination on clauses (1)–(4). To prevent this, Lippert-Rasmussen adds the first part of (5) as he holds that even if gay people are regularly romantically rejected by straight people and vice versa, this alone does not make these two groups worse off relatively to each other. On its own, the first part of (5) would be too demanding, though, as it would exclude one-off cases of morally troublesome differential treatment caused by group-related animus. For instance, imagine that “just one Catholic employer in a Protestant, fiercely anti-Catholic society refuses to hire Protestant applicants simply as a result of animosity toward Protestants” (Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 27). Since this employer is just one person, his refusal to hire Protestant applicants would not result in Protestants being significantly worse off. Lippert-Rasmussen, however, insists that cases like this should count as instances of discrimination. He therefore has to add the second part of (5). Finally, (2) captures Lippert-Rasmussen’s belief that discrimination involves the differential treatment of the person targeted. On his view, there can be cases of discrimination that, while not morally neutral, do not rise to the level of a moral wrong. According to Lippert-Rasmussen, an act of discrimination meets this level when it runs counter to what he calls desert-accommodating prioritarianism, that is, when by x-ing A has either not maximized the general well-being or done so in a way that did not prioritize the well-being of those worse-off or more deserving (cf. Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 166).Footnote 4

Let us now turn to Hellman’s “meaning-based view of wrongful discrimination” (Hellman, Reference Hellman and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 97).Footnote 5 On the most general, nonmoralized level, A, by x-ing, discriminates against B vis-à-vis another person C if A treats B differently from C on the basis of B having or lacking some trait or property P constitutive of some social group G (Hellman, Reference Hellman and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 98).Footnote 6 Hellman does not state explicitly how we are to understand the notion that a person is treated differently on the basis of having or lacking some group-related property, but it seems fair to assume that she adopts an understanding similar to Lippert-Rasmussen’s condition (3).Footnote 7 If we rely on this assumption, A, by x-ing, treats B differently from C on the basis of B having or lacking some property P if B’s having or lacking P is part of A’s motivating reason for x-ing.

Hellman claims that discriminatory actions of this general variety only turn wrongful in their distinctive way once they become demeaning. According to her, demeaningly discriminatory actions necessarily involve “an expressive dimension and a power dimension” (Hellman, Reference Hellman and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 102): they must express that their target has lower status, that is to say, that the target can legitimately be treated worse than what the “bedrock moral principle” of “equal moral worth” (Hellman, Reference Hellman2008, 6) prescribes. Even though Hellman elaborates neither on the metaethical assumptions behind this principle nor on its specific content, it is clear that, on her understanding, a person’s equal moral worth constitutes an immutable, objective moral standard for how people are to be treated. In addition to this symbolic dimension, there must be “a certain efficacy” (Hellman, Reference Hellman2008, 35) to these expressions, so that demeaningly discriminatory actions end up lowering their targets’ status and thus subordinate them. At first glance, Hellman’s insistence on efficacy might seem incongruous: if the principle of equal moral worth immutably and objectively prescribes how people are to be treated, how could A possibly have sufficient social power negatively to affect B’s (immutable, objectively given) status? The most plausible solution to this puzzle is that, for Hellman, lowering a person’s status does not imply a change to how a person can legitimately be treated (i.e., a change to the topography of their normative landscape) but to how they are de facto treated (i.e., to how other people navigate this topography). Hellman insists on this power dimension because, according to her, discrimination involves a putdown (see Hellman, Reference Hellman2008, 35), which I take to mean a tangible worsening of the target’s situation. Hellman assumes that, on their own, none of the other elements of wrongful discrimination—that is, A treating B differently from C and A expressing that B can legitimately be treated worse than objectively required—constitutes such a putdown. By adding the power dimension, Hellman wants to make sure that wrongful discrimination packs the necessary punch. Hellman has recently expanded her account of wrongful discrimination by allowing for the possibility that its demeaning element pertains not only to its direct target B but to the whole social group G constituted by having P. Bearing this expansion in mind, her account can be summarized as follows:

DiscriminationHellman: A wrongfully discriminates against B in relation to C by x-ing if (1) A treats B differently from C by x-ing; (2) there is a property P constitutive of being a member of social group G, and B (but not C) having or lacking P is part of A’s motivating reason for x-ing; (3) by x-ing, A expresses that B has lower status or that members of G have lower status, that is to say, that B or members of G can legitimately be treated worse than objectively required; and (4) A has sufficient social power such that, by expressing that B has lower status or that members of G have lower status, A makes it the case that B or members of G are treated worse than objectively required.

The last issue I want to address regarding Hellman’s account is the notion of expression stipulated by (3). How can an instance of differential treatment—such as not giving someone a job they deserve, not letting them enter a facility otherwise open to the general public, etc.—acquire any meaning, let alone the very specific meaning of expressing that the target can legitimately be treated worse than objectively required? Hellman does not spell this out (I will do so in Section 3), but she is adamant that it does not depend on “whether or not the people who enacted” this treatment “intend to express this meaning and whether or not those affected by it interpret it in this way” (Hellman, Reference Hellman and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 100); rather, “culture and context play a significant role in determining” it (Hellman, Reference Hellman2008, 38). According to her, the meaning of any action is determined by society’s common ground, that is, by the explicit as well as the implicit background beliefs most members of said society share. Occasionally, this will make the correct assessment of an action’s meaning complex or even impossible, for instance, when there are no society-wide but only highly localized interpretations of the action (Hellman, Reference Hellman and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 101). But often enough, we will be able to determine an action’s meaning through rigorous interpretive work (see Hellman, Reference Hellman2008, 41). For instance, against the common ground of white supremacy, “the meaning of segregation in the Jim Crow South was clear” (Hellman, Reference Hellman and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 101) as degrading Black people. Hellman’s account is therefore not just a meaning based view, but an objective meaning based view of wrongful discrimination (Hellman, Reference Hellman and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 100) as only those instances of differential treatment become instances of wrongful discrimination that express, given a society’s common ground, that their target has lower status.

With these clarifications in place, let us now turn to the question whether Lippert-Rasmussen’s and Hellman’s conceptions can do justice to the all-of-us intuition. To answer it, I first need to establish what doing justice to the all-of-us intuition amounts to. I contend that it implies three things: (i) First, to do justice to the all-of-us intuition, a conception of discrimination must make sense of the idea that a discriminatory action wrongs its direct target, that is, the person it is perpetrated against. Otherwise, it cannot explain why, in cases like “Committee,” we feel outrage on behalf of B. (ii) Second, and involving more complications, it must accommodate the idea that a discriminatory action also wrongs every member of the social group G to which B is perceived to belong. This is necessary to bear out the observation that, as fellow women in “Committee,” we would also feel offended on our own behalf and entitled to an apology. (iii) Third, such a conception of discrimination must capture the idea that the wrong incurred by the direct target is somehow more troublesome than the one incurred by each of their fellow group members.Footnote 8 This is crucial to make sense of the observation that while, as fellow women in “Committee,” we would feel some outrage on our own behalf, our moral opprobrium would center on how candidate B was treated. As I see it, there are two ways to achieve (iii): either by arguing that the wrong incurred by B is worse than the one suffered by each of their fellow group members or by claiming that B is wronged in more ways than their fellow group members.

If (i)–(iii) correctly state what it takes for a conception of discrimination to do justice to the all-of-us intuition, then it is clear that Lippert-Rasmussen’s view will not necessarily do so. According to him, an instance of group-related differential treatment x amounts to wrongful discrimination if x leads to a reduction in well-being incompatible with desert prioritarianism. But while Lippert-Rasmussen is adamant that x is an instance of wrongful discrimination only if it harms either those who are already worst off or those undeserving of such harm, he does not say anything over and above this about how the harm caused by x has to be distributed. The structure of his definition suggests that some of this harm will likely befall x’s direct target B as, per Lippert-Rasmussen’s condition (2), B is to be treated worse by x than some other person C, thus making it likely that x will fulfill implication (i) of the all-of-us intuition. But nothing in his definition necessitates that x will also fulfill (ii), that is, that x will also harm every other member of B’s (presumed) social group G.Footnote 9 Admittedly, nothing in Lippert-Rasmussen’s definition precludes this, either, and there may well be instances of differential treatment that meet his definition and that result in a distribution of harm which bears out (ii).Footnote 10 But since his definition remains silent on this issue, it remains a matter of chance whether an instance of wrongful discrimination according to Lippert-Rasmussen lives up to the all-of-us intuition or not.

Let us see if Hellman’s conception fares any better. At first glance, her view seems more promising as its conditions (3) and (4) explicitly allow for instances of discrimination in which the differential treatment constitutive of discrimination is demeaning to all members of G. Let us call these cases instances of group-demeaning discrimination. Assuming that demeaning constitutes a moral wrong, it follows that in group-demeaning instances of discrimination, the discriminatory action in question wrongs all members of G. In such cases, Hellman’s conception therefore fulfills (ii). And her conception also fulfills (i), the demand that a discriminatory action wrongs its direct target B, because as a member of G, B too is demeaned by x and therefore wronged by it. In fact, in such cases, B is wronged at all only in virtue of social group G being demeaned. This is because, according to Hellman, the differential treatment constitutive of discrimination does not as such contribute to discrimination’s moral valence—discrimination becomes morally problematic only insofar as it is demeaning. Put differently, in cases of group-demeaning discrimination, the only morally troublesome thing that happens to B is that their social group is being demeaned and they along with it. But while instances of group-demeaning differential treatment enable Hellman’s conception to kill two birds with one stone, so to speak, the way they allow it to fulfill both (ii) and (i) entails that it necessarily fails to live up to (iii). Because in group-demeaning instances of discrimination, the only wrong suffered by B is the same wrong as the one suffered by their fellow group members, that is, the demeaning of their shared social group. Thus, on Hellman’s view, there is no way of claiming that B is wronged worse or more often than their fellow group members.Footnote 11 So while it successfully makes sense of the idea that an individual instance of discrimination wrongs more people than its direct target alone, Hellman’s view cannot explain how an individual instance of group-demeaning discrimination, while wronging all members of the social group targeted, wrongs its direct target first and foremost.

3. “Discrimination” Ameliorated

In the previous section, I argued that, each in its own way, both Lippert-Rasmussen’s and Hellman’s conceptions of (wrongful) discrimination fail to reliably do justice to the all-of-us intuition. Nevertheless, there is much to learn from both views. Hellman’s account provides us with a solution to the puzzle posed by (ii), namely, the idea that the all-of-us intuition implies that an individual discriminatory action wrongs every member of the targeted social group. No discriminatory action can bear out this idea simply in virtue of the differential treatment it involves. In “Committee,” for instance, B is certainly wronged by the search committee passing her over in favor of C, yet it is simply not the case that in passing B over, the search committee has also passed over every other woman. But as we can glean from Hellman’s conception, there is also a morally dubious expressive element to discrimination, and this expressive element can very well wrong more than one person and possibly even a whole social group. In contrast, Lippert-Rasmussen’s conception provides us with a way to address (iii), that is, the idea that every discriminatory action wrongs its direct target first and foremost because for him discrimination necessarily includes the mistreatment of the specific person at whom it is directed. My contention is that by putting Hellman’s and Lippert-Rasmussen’s insights together, we can create a conception of discrimination that succeeds in doing justice to all aspects of the all-of-us intuition. Specifically, I claim that we should adopt the following conception:

Discriminationameliorated: A discriminates against B in relation to C by x-ing if (1) there is a property P constitutive of being a member of social group G and B is reasonably perceived to have P and thus be a member of G; (2) A treats B worse than C by x-ing and thereby wrongs B; and (3) by x-ing, A expresses that members of G have lower status, that is, that members of G can legitimately be treated worse than objectively required.

The influence of both Lippert-Rasmussen and Hellman should be obvious: Conditions (1) and (2) take their cue from Lippert-Rasmussen: (1) takes up his idea that discrimination focuses on social groups, which he articulates in his conditions (1) and (4), where he also makes room for cases of misdirected discrimination; (2) radicalizes his condition (2) as it stipulates that the differential treatment involved in discrimination has to amount to a moral wrong. In contrast, condition (3) is inspired by Hellman’s condition (3), though only by its group-related aspects.

These similarities notwithstanding, my conception differs from theirs in some important respects, which I outline now before I turn to the question of how my conception fares with regard to the all-of-us intuition. The first difference is that, on my view, we do not need to know anything about the agent’s motivating reasons—specifically, whether they were guided by any beliefs about their target’s group-membership or by group-related animus—to determine whether their action was an instance of discrimination or not. This is so because, on my conception, the agent’s de facto motivating reasons or intentions are not constitutive of discrimination at all. In the next section, I explain why I believe this omission to be advantageous for my view; for now, I merely seek to explain how I can afford to make it.

A critic might remark that, by disregarding the agent’s motivating reasons, I run the risk of missing the most important point about discrimination, which is that discrimination is a group-related phenomenon, that discrimination is about social groups (see Altman, Reference Altman and Zalta2020). So far, all accounts of discrimination have captured this group relatedness by insisting that the target’s group membership figure prominently in the agent’s motivating reasons. If we leave this part out, as I propose we do, do we not rob ourselves of the ability to distinguish between instances of differential treatment of a personal variety and instances that are group related and therefore rightly called discrimination? I would reply that my account does not do away with the group relatedness of discrimination: it just spells it out in a different way. Specifically, on my understanding, discrimination is about social groups insofar as discriminatory actions express something negative about the status of the social group they target.

Another difference is that I omit Hellman’s power dimension. While I very much agree with her idea that discriminatory actions express something negative about how their targets can legitimately be treated, I do not believe that these expressions must be accompanied by sufficient social power to then make it the case that the targets are de facto treated worse than what is objectively required. Others have already argued that it seems counterintuitive to rule out that people with little or no social power are able to discriminate simply on conceptual grounds (see Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 138). I thus consider this omission an asset of my view. I am able to make this omission because, in contrast to Hellman, I stipulate that the differential treatment involved in discrimination has to amount, by itself, to a moral wrong. As I argued earlier, Hellman only insists on the power dimension to ensure that discriminatory actions are indeed wronging their targets. Since condition (2) of my conception already takes care of this (as does, as will become clear presently, my condition (3)), there is no need for me to accept Hellman’s controversial condition (4).

My stipulation that the differential treatment involved in discrimination has to amount to a moral wrong is my third divergence from Lippert-Rasmussen’s and Hellman’s conceptions. This stipulation is necessary not, as one might expect, to strengthen condition (2), but to get condition (3) and, more specifically, its idea of expressive meaning off the ground. Like Hellman, I contend that those instances of differential treatment that will amount to discrimination express that members of the social group targeted can legitimately be treated worse than objectively required. But how are we to understand that an action acquires this specific expressive meaning? Unfortunately, Hellman herself has little to say on this matter. All she suggests is that certain types of action, for example, spitting at someone, can acquire this meaning by convention. While true, this is not very helpful as there are many and varied ways of differential treatment that can constitute discrimination (e.g., passing someone over for a job, not letting them enter a facility which is otherwise open to the public, paying them less for their work than other people, etc.) and it seems unlikely that all of them have acquired the necessary degrading meaning by convention. Therefore, I want to suggest that we rely on a different theory of expressive meaning according to which “an agent’s action expresses a principle when it would be objectively reasonable for observers to attribute to the agent an attitude of endorsement regarding that principle” (Shin, Reference Shin2009, 166; see also Anderson & Pildes, Reference Anderson and Pildes2000, Bratu, Reference Bratu2023). Given this theory of expressive meaning, A’s action x can express that members of the targeted social group can legitimately be treated worse than they objectively can only if, on the basis of A’s x-ing, it is reasonable to assume that A believes that members of the targeted social group can legitimately be treated worse than they objectively can. But it is only reasonable to assume that A believes that members of the targeted social group can legitimately be treated worse than they objectively can on basis of A’s x-ing, if x is in fact an action by which A treats a member of the targeted social group worse than they should objectively be treated, that is, if by x-ing A wrongs B. Otherwise, A’s action and the belief that (presumably) accompanies it would not be adequately connected.Footnote 12 If discriminatory actions are supposed to express that their targets can legitimately be wronged, as I claim in condition (3) of my definition (or, for that matter, Hellman in condition (4) of hers), the actions that are supposed to do this expressing need to be some kind of wrong. Condition (2) of my definition reflects this necessity. With one exception (to which I will return presently), I remain open about the specific nature of the wrong at play in (2). I can do so because, as will become clear shortly, the precise way in which the differential treatment called for by (2) wrongs its target does not matter for my conception; also, this openness allows my conception of discrimination to be compatible with different background theories of morality. Thus, the differential treatment constituted by x could be wrong because it is unfair (as is B’s being passed over for the job she is qualified for in “Committee”), because it fails to maximize overall well-being in a desert-accommodating way (see Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 166), because it illegitimately curtails B’s deliberative freedom or sustains conditions of social subordination or denies B access to basic goods (see Moreau, Reference Moreau2020, 153) or whichever background theory of morality turns out to be correct. All that matters is that the wrong called for in condition (2) occurs in such a way that it acquires the expressive meaning called for in condition (3), namely that members of G can legitimately be subjected to this kind of wrong and thus be treated worse than objectively required.

Elsewhere I argued that we should call the expression of this specific content—that a person can legitimately be treated worse than they objectively can and thus has less moral status than they in fact do (cf. Bratu, Reference Bratu2023)—disrespectful. Footnote 13 I also argued that we should consider disrespect a moral wrong because people have the right not to have their moral status publicly called into question as this exposes them to the risk of future mistreatment. If we accept this, the following picture of discrimination emerges: every discriminatory action packs not just one, put two punches as it combines two distinct, but interrelated moral wrongs—first, an instance of differential treatment which, given some underlying theory of morality, amounts to a moral wrong and, second, an instance of wrongful disrespect. Put differently, discrimination is a compound wrong that consists of two distinct wrongs: discriminatory actions wrong their targets not only in some tangible way (for instance, by not hiring them even though they are the most qualified candidate, by restricting their access to areas otherwise open to the public, etc.), they also wrong them by trying to legitimize this wrongful behavior by expressing that it is permissible (when in fact it is not). Discrimination is therefore never only an injury, it always adds an insult. And in fact, the insult discrimination involves is particularly pernicious because, on my understanding, discriminatory actions do not just disrespect their direct target, they also disrespect the whole social group the target is reasonably perceived to belong to, that is, every member of their social group. Another way to spell out this idea is to draw on Kate Manne’s distinction between those actions that function as the “legislative branch” of some hierarchical and oppressive world view and those that function as its “law enforcement branch.” According to Manne, the former try to justify said world view, while the latter enforce its norms (cf. Manne, Reference Manne2018, 78f.). If what I argued is correct, discriminatory actions blur this distinction as they simultaneously serve in both branches.

On this picture, there is nothing truly special about discriminatory actions since other kinds of action also instantiate the wrongs constitutive of discrimination. There are many instances of differential treatment that wrong their targets in some way or other, just as there are other types of harmful action, for instance, hate speech, that wrong their targets by disrespecting them.Footnote 14 What’s the point then of having a philosophical concept specifically dedicated to discrimination, or so a critic might ask. I contend that having such a concept is useful because, even though discriminatory actions are not the only ones that can be disrespectful, the way they express their disrespect is particularly pernicious. As I defined it earlier, (group-related) disrespect always consists in an expression, specifically in the expression that we can legitimately treat members of some social group worse than we in fact can. Discriminatory actions express this content, but in addition they also treat a member of the targeted social group worse than they can legitimately be treated and thus as if their disrespectful statement was true. Put differently, discriminatory actions do not just proclaim “look, we can do xyz to people like them,” but in doing xyz to them, they also show that xyz can (descriptively speaking) be done to them. By combining their disrespectful statement with a matching action, discriminatory actions thus ostensibly provide those who witness them with evidence that backs up their pernicious message. Obviously, this evidence is deeply flawed as normative claims can never be justified by simply pointing to the status quo (not to mention that, given the correct moral theory, no social group can legitimately be treated worse than othersFootnote 15); but as social beings, we all are social cognizers and thus tend to treat what other people do as at least indicative for how to navigate the world. In short, discriminatory actions do not only express disrespect, they also make it seem like their disrespectful content was true which in turn raises the risk of their content being taken seriously. For this alone, disrespectful actions deserve a philosophical concept tailor-made to identify them.

But my account of discrimination does not only help to pick out actions that exhibit the pernicious combination of wrongs just described; in addition and in contrast to Lippert-Rasmussen’s and Hellman’s, it can also make sense of the all-of-us intuition. On my view, every discriminatory action x involves two wrongs: a wrongful instance of differential treatment and a wrongful instance of group-related disrespect. The former only wrongs x’s direct target B; the latter, in contrast, wrongs every member of the social group G B is reasonably perceived to be a member of, including B. Since B is wronged, both by being treated worse than C and by being disrespected as a member of G, (i) holds. Since every member of G is wronged, given that expressing x’s belittling meaning violates their right not to have their rightful moral status publicly called into question, (ii) holds as well. Finally, since B is wronged twice while their fellow social group members are wronged only once, there is a sense in which the wrong incurred by B is more troublesome than that incurred by every other member of G; thus, (iii) holds as well. Against the backdrop of my view, the all-of-us intuition elicited by “Committee” therefore makes perfect sense: as B is passed over unfairly in favor of C, it is reasonable for us to feel outrage on B’s behalf. It is also reasonable for us to feel outrage on behalf of all other women, including ourselves (provided we identify as women), given that the blatantly sexist way B is passed over is disrespectful to all women. But even though all women are disrespected in “Committee,” B is also cheated out of a job she was best qualified for, which is why our outrage should center on the wrongs perpetrated against B rather than the one perpetrated against us.

The one way my conception of discrimination could fail to live up to the all-of-us intuition is if the differential treatment wronging target B (which condition (2) calls for) was identical to the wrong vis-à-vis all members of the social group targeted (which condition (3) calls for), that is, if the differential treatment wronging B was itself an instance of disrespect toward the social group B is reasonably perceived to be a member of. In such a case, in which the wrong suffered by B was the same one as the one suffered by every other member of B’s presumed social group, my conception of discrimination would meet the same fate as Hellman’s and fall short of fulfilling implication (iii) of the all-of-us intuition as it would be impossible to claim that B had been wronged worse or in more ways by the discriminatory action than their fellow group members. Therefore, I am forced to make an exception to my general parsimony regarding the kinds of wrong we can insert in condition (2) and insist that it cannot be an instance of disrespect toward B’s presumed social group. But, as I will argue in section 5, this exception will allow us to make an important distinction.

Let us sum up. I argued that the all-of-us intuition helps us understand that individual discriminatory acts are even worse than hitherto acknowledged as they wrong not only their direct target but everybody in the targeted social group. Conceptions like Lippert-Rasmussen’s and Hellman’s that focus on just one aspect of the compound wrong discrimination consists in are thus not just in breach of some random conceptual intuition—they fail to give us a comprehensive account of the moral wrong intrinsic to discrimination and therefore risk trivializing it. This is problematic in terms of advocacy. As emancipatory-minded philosophers, we want to present the strongest possible case against discrimination and, arguably, we are better able to do so if we draw on a conception of discrimination that shows how every individual instance of discrimination attacks not just its direct target but every member of their (presumed) social group. But more importantly, as philosophers, we strive to paint a comprehensive picture of moral reality and in the case of discrimination we cannot do this without taking the all-of-us intuition into account.

4. What Else? Other Considerations in Favor of a Comprehensive Account

As noted, the main advantage of my understanding of discrimination is that it allows us to see and to advocate against all that is intrinsically wrong with it. But there are two additional advantages to my account.

First, my conception makes it easier to identify individual instances of discrimination than the intention-based (to use Mari Mikkola’s helpful term; see Mikkola, Reference Mikkola2016, 192) accounts of Lippert-Rasmussen and Hellman. For them, an action only turns discriminatory if the agent’s motivating reasons for it include some belief about or desire concerning the target’s social group membership (such as a false belief about women being meek or a desire to put them in their “proper place”). Such intention-based accounts make it difficult to identify discriminatory actions, since to do so, we need reliable information about what is in its agent’s head, so to speak, which is notoriously hard to come by. Interestingly, this difficulty has led some feminist philosophers to call into question the very usefulness of discrimination as a conceptual tool or to at least think of it as ideal theorizing. For instance, Iris Marion Young argues that we should think about women’s situation in terms of oppression rather than of discrimination, since the latter focuses on “perpetrators and intents” and therefore “becomes very difficult to prove” (Young, Reference Young1990, 196).Footnote 16

In contrast, my conception of discrimination requires no mindreading to assess whether an action is discriminatory or not. All we need is information about whether said action wrongs its target and whether it does so in a way that is disrespectful toward their (presumed) social group. Admittedly, accessing this type of information will not always be easy either. It requires considerable knowledge concerning how a specific action will likely be interpreted given society’s common ground. And this, in turn, requires considerable knowledge of a society’s history, culture, public discourse, and so forth. Still, I contend that acquiring this type of information is easier than divining another person’s motivating reasons, since it can be found in the public domain, that is, in history books, newspaper articles, blogs, etc., rather than stored away in people’s minds.

A critic might be willing to grant the point about my account’s greater accessibility, but wonder whether it might be just as much a bug as it is a positive feature. Specifically, they might wonder whether getting rid of the intention requirement renders my account too comprehensive.Footnote 17 A similar dynamic can be found in the debate about racism, where some want to reserve the term “racist” to actions that are caused by “particularly hateful beliefs and attitudes toward members of a racial group” (Anderson, Reference Anderson2010, 47) in order to avoid the proliferation of racist actions that would presumably result from a nonintention-based understanding of the term. In reply to this, I would point out two things. First, whether my account does in fact entail that many more actions would have to be considered discriminatory is an open question rather than a foregone conclusion. The answer depends on how many wrongful actions also acquire the necessary disrespectful meaning. Second and more importantly, even if it turns out that on my comprehensive conception there is more discrimination than on an intention-based one, this increase is not per se problematic because, as the debate about indirect discrimination shows (see the next point), we are already willing to accept that discrimination can occur without its perpetrators being motivated by bigoted beliefs or motives concerning the targeted social group. The fact that we are willing to accept indirect discrimination as a kind of discrimination proves that we are not wedded to an intention-based understanding of discrimination.

This brings me to the second additional advantage of my comprehensive conception, which concerns, precisely, indirect discrimination. I contend that my conception does a better job of making sense of and addressing what Lippert-Rasmussen calls the “indirect discrimination definition challenge” (Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 55). To show this, I first have to clarify what I mean by “indirect discrimination” and the challenge raised by it.

Consider “Ambivalent,” the case of an employer who genuinely does not harbor any prejudices or animosity toward women but who, for purely financial reasons, does not want to hire people who are likely to request time off due to childcare responsibilities. Given the prevailing gendered division of labor, this policy will in all likelihood result in women not being hired, which intuitively should count as an instance of gender-based discrimination. Intention-based accounts of (direct) discrimination like Lippert-Rasmussen’s or Hellman’s cannot reflect this intuition since, by stipulation, the agent’s motivating reasons are devoid of any bigoted beliefs or desires. This assessment is problematic not only because it is counterintuitive, but also because it clashes with existing law. Assuming that in societies marred by prejudices and social exclusion, discrimination “often takes a form where it exists independently of discriminatory intentions” (Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 55), lawmakers around the world have tried to accommodate cases like “Ambivalent” by introducing the concept of indirect discrimination which occurs without “any bias or discriminatory intention on part of the agent” (Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 55; see also Khaitan, Reference Khaitan and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 31). In reaction to these legal developments, philosophers have devised their own understanding of the phenomenon. A paradigmatic example is Altman’s conception, which stipulates that an action or policy indirectly discriminates against some socially salient group G if and only if it disproportionately disadvantages members of G relative to members of other socially salient groups even though it neither explicitly targets nor is intended to disadvantage members of G qua being members of G (see Altman, Reference Altman and Zalta2020; for a slight variation, see Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 72).

My claim is that definitions like this one fall short of doing justice to the challenge posed by indirect discrimination because, in effect, cases like “Ambivalent” elicit not one, but two intuitive reactions. Yes, they strike us as discriminatory, but they do not do so in a straightforward way. Instead, much like the famous rabbit–duck illusion and other reversible figures, our intuitive assessment of such cases oscillates depending on whether we focus on the operating intention behind these allegedly discriminatory actions (and, specifically, on the agents’ lack of bigoted beliefs and motives) or on the predictably uneven distribution of burdens and disadvantages they result in. To illustrate the point, imagine a person trying to make up their mind about “Ambivalent.” If they concentrate on the fact that the employer in question never hires a woman, they will in all likelihood consider the case to be one of gender-based discrimination. If, in contrast, they conceptualize it as a case in which an employer is just trying to keep their business afloat, they might even consider the employer’s reluctance to hire potentially unreliable people justified. In any case, their deliberation will be just that: a complex, multilayered deliberation and not a snap judgement. To incorporate this second intuition, we need an understanding of discrimination that not only allows us to identify cases like “Ambivalent” as (some kind of) discrimination but one that also takes into account that these are hard cases, cases in which we have to squint a little to see their discriminatory nature, so to speak.

As they are tailor-made to identify cases like “Ambivalent” as instances of indirect discrimination, conceptions like Altman’s evidently do justice to the first intuition, but precisely because they are tailor-made for such cases, they necessarily fall short of doing justice to the second. On conceptions like this, evaluating cases like “Ambivalent” will never be hard: they are by definition examples of indirect discrimination and there is no squinting required to see this.

On my comprehensive conception, matters are less straightforward: “Ambivalent” qualifies as an instance of discrimination if the employer wrongs their target and if they do so in a way that expresses disrespect toward the social group their target is perceived to belong to. Since the employer’s hiring practices dismiss a great number of people without even considering their qualifications, they certainly wrong at least those women who would have been qualified to fill the vacant positions. The first condition is thus met. When it comes to the second condition, though, things are less obvious. To establish whether the employer’s actions express disrespect, we need to ask ourselves how they would reasonably be interpreted, that is, which intentions people would reasonably ascribe to the employer. If the employer seems truthful and reasonably self-aware, one should simply believe what the employer tells them about their intentions as they are obviously best positioned to know about their own mental states. By this standard, the employer’s refusal to hire women would not express anything disrespectful about women: they would not mean anything else by it but just try to avoid additional costs. Yet circumstances conspire to undermine the employer’s credibility because, first, many people still harbor sexist prejudices either explicitly or implicitly and, second and more importantly, the employer’s willingness to bring about a situation that starkly disadvantages women fits right into this pattern. In light of this additional evidence, one would be justified in distrusting the employer’s avowed intentions and in believing that what they really intend to do is to keep women in their “proper place” (i.e., the home), which renders their actions disrespectful and, consequently, discriminatory.Footnote 18 But even though “Ambivalent” on my account ultimately turns out to be an instance of discrimination, we need to weigh conflicting evidence to reach this conclusion (i.e., the employer’s testimony and its presumptive first-person authority versus statistical evidence about prevailing sexist beliefs and the fact that the employer’s actions fit well with a sexist mindset). This accounts for the duck–rabbit quality typical of cases like “Ambivalent.”

I contend that these three features are present in all cases discussed in the literature under the label of indirect discrimination: that an agent wrongs their target by unfairly disadvantaging them; that there is an innocuous way to interpret their action (based on their own description of the matter) as well as one that renders it disrespectful toward the social group the target is perceived to belong to (based on the pervasiveness of stereotypes about said social group and on the fact that the agent is willing to unfairly disadvantage members of said group); and that the agent’s willingness to bring about this disadvantage ultimately renders more reasonable the interpretation of their action that implies disrespect. If this is so, then my account can satisfy both intuitions: it can identify such cases as instances of discrimination albeit not in a straightforward way.

5. Objections

I want to close by discussing two objections that would try to show that my comprehensive conception is in fact not comprehensive enough as it excludes cases that intuitively should count as discrimination. Each objection takes aim at a different condition of my conception. The first centers on condition (3) and thus on my claim that, to be discriminatory, an action must express that the members of the targeted social group have lower status. What about actions that wrong their targets and are performed by their agents out of group-centered animus or contempt but fail to express this negative stance in any way a critic might ask. To see what the critic is driving at, consider “Committee2,” in which A, again, dismisses B’s application and does so because he passionately hates women. In fact, A turned into a misogynist after B had ended their relationship. While nobody knows about A’s hateful stance toward women, the fact that B has left him and that their separation left him shattered is well established. Under these circumstances, people will reasonably interpret A’s dismissal of B as an instance of personal (rather than group related) spite that expresses contempt of B as a person, but not of women as a social group. This would make his action an instance of unjust differential treatment but not, on my account, of discrimination. Yet since B’s dismissal is in fact driven by misogyny against all women, this assessment is false, or so a critic might contend.

I admit that, intuitively, cases like “Committee2” seem to be prime examples of discrimination and that intention-based accounts like Lippert-Rasmussen’s and Hellman’s capture this intuition nicely. But as I stated in the introduction, I consider my conception to be ameliorative and thus am willing to accept a certain number of counterintuitive implications as long as these are offset by other theoretical benefits. As I stressed in section 3, the biggest theoretical benefit of a comprehensive conception like mine, which is tailored toward the all-of-us intuition rather than to the one elicited by “Committee2,” is that it identifies actions that are morally problematic in a particularly pernicious way in that they not only wrong their direct target but also try to legitimize this kind of wrongful behavior by expressing falsehoods about how a whole social group can legitimately be treated. They thus include the risk of an untold number of future wrongs. In contrast, definitions that seek to capture cases like “Committee2” focus more on the perpetrator. Specifically, they aim to identify those instances of wrongful group-based mistreatment that are perpetrated by “true believers,” that is, by people motivated by bigoted group-centered beliefs or motives—something my account is unable to do. Put bluntly, while my account strives to detect particularly bad actions, intention-based conceptions want to detect particularly bad actors. In my opinion, there is value to both approaches. From the point of view of improving matters for those suffering from group-based mistreatment, however, mine seems more tailored to the target because to prevent further group-based mistreatment, it is more important to identify (and consequently prevent) those instances that try to justify this kind of mistreatment rather than those that are perpetrated out of a particular motivation, however, despicable. So even though my comprehensive conception of discrimination cannot identify cases like “Committee2” as instances of discrimination and therefore falls short of accommodating a plausible intuition, it does so in order to focus on actions that, from a practical point of view, matter more.

A critic might take these comments to heart and on their basis try to craft a second objection that centers on my condition (2). If I am so concerned about actions that try to legitimize the mistreatment of certain social groups, then what about actions that do just that by being disrespectful toward some social group, but do not in addition wrong any of its members? To illustrate this idea, consider “Committee3,” in which A, again, makes a number of sexist remarks about women and their (alleged) lack of qualifications. In the end, though, A votes for B because he wants the department to hire a (supposedly) weak candidate so that his own authority will not be threatened. In this case, B and all other women have certainly been disrespected, but since B has not been passed over unfairly, she has not been wronged in any additional way.Footnote 19 On my account, A’s comments will not count as discriminatory, as they fall short of condition (2). But what is a hiring committee where people openly make sexist remarks if not discriminatory, or so a critic might ask.

My reply to this second objection somewhat resembles my reply to the first. Again, I concede that it seems intuitive to describe A’s comments in “Committee3” as discriminatory and that my account cannot accommodate this intuition. But again, this failure does not strike me as problematic but instead as the result of focusing on a distinction that morally matters. Because even though group-based disrespectful actions are, as noted, particularly pernicious, group-based disrespectful actions that also wrong one of the group’s members in some additional way are worse. To see this, compare the situation of B in “Committee” and in “Committee3”: obviously, in both cases, B and all women are the target of disrespect—but in “Committee,” B is also unfairly cheated out of a job she is qualified for. An account of discrimination that did away with condition (2), as the critic’s comment suggests, would not be able to pick up on this difference. This difference, however, matters a great deal, particularly to B, and a useful conception of discrimination should reflect this. Rather than accommodating the intuition elicited by “Committee3,” I would therefore discount it by pointing out that while the critic rightly detects a similarity between “Committee” and “Committee3” (both depict instances of group-related disrespect), they fail to pay sufficient attention to an important difference (in one of them the direct target is wronged twice).

6. Conclusion

In this article, I pursued two related goals. First, I sought to alert philosophers working on the topic of discrimination to the all-of-us intuition. Accommodating this intuition is important because it points us to ways in which discrimination is morally troublesome which the debate has so far paid little attention to. Specifically, it allows us to see that each individual act of discrimination not only wrongfully mistreats its direct target, it also wrongfully disrespects each member of the social group the direct target is perceived to belong to. Second, I developed a conception of discrimination comprehensive enough to capture the all-of-us intuition. And this, precisely, is the main consideration speaking in favor of my comprehensive conception. It is able to capture all that is intrinsically wrong with discrimination and thus gives us a more accurate picture of moral reality and allows us to make a stronger case for fighting discrimination. In addition, my account makes it easier to identify instances of discrimination than intention-based conceptions do because it requires only sufficient knowledge of society’s common ground rather than an ability to read other people’s minds. It also helps us understand why cases of what has been discussed under the heading “indirect discrimination” are in fact instances of discrimination proper, albeit ones that are hard to detect. Admittedly, like most philosophical conceptions, mine, too, fails to capture all intuitions people might have of the matter. But its counterintuitive implications, I argued, are offset by its ability to bring into focus something of greater moral importance. My hope is that ameliorating our conception of discrimination in the manner I have described here allows us to see more clearly all the havoc the real-life phenomenon it refers to wreaks and to understand why it is so urgent to fight it.

Acknowledgments

I thank Anna Wehofsits, Hauke Behrendt, and two anonymous reviewers for their immensely helpful comments on earlier drafts of this article. I am also grateful for the opportunity to present this article at the colloquium on discrimination, organized by Eva von Redecker, at the XXV. German Congress of Philosophy in Erlangen, during my guest professorship in philosophy of gender at Bielefeld University, at a workshop on equality and social hierarchies, organized by Luise Müller, at FU Berlin and at colloquia at Erlangen and Göttingen universities—thanks to all participants for their constructive feedback. Special thanks to Aline Dammel for her help with the final manuscript.

Christine Bratu is a professor of philosophy at the University of Göttingen, Germany. Her research focuses on feminist, moral, and political philosophy.

Footnotes

1 This is not the worst example of discrimination one could think of. I am choosing it because, in my opinion, it is bad enough to make clear that we need to engage with the issue of discrimination, but not so bad as to make such engagement overly distressing.

2 As I consider achieving certain practical aims more important than doing justice to all possible conceptional intuitions, I follow an ameliorative approach to concept building (see Haslanger, Reference Haslanger2012, 386).

3 To see this, it is helpful to compare Lippert-Rasmussen’s definition of discrimination with those Andrew Altman (Reference Altman and Zalta2020) and Frej Klem Thomsen (Reference Thomsen and Lippert-Rasmussen2018) provide in their overview articles. For, in their efforts to present us with a definition of discrimination that is general enough for everybody to accept, both authors end up with accounts that seem to be taken right out of Lippert-Rasmussen’s book.

4 Obviously, to assess whether x maximized general well-being or not, we need a baseline to which we can compare x. According to Lippert-Rasmussen, we “should compare the actual outcome [of the discriminatory action, C.B.] to the one that would have obtained if the discriminatory act had not been performed and no [sic] else had performed discriminatory acts in the future” (Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 158). Lippert-Rasmussen defends his “No-Discrimination Baseline Account” at length in his book, but as this issue is not relevant for what I am arguing here, I will not go into the details of his defense.

5 Unlike Lippert-Rasmussen, Hellman does not provide us with a detailed definition. The following is my attempt to reconstruct such a definition from the ample material she provides.

6 Hellman cites a person’s gender or race as examples for properties that constitute social group membership (Hellman, Reference Hellman and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 98). Obviously, there is a live debate about which properties are in fact necessary in order to be, say, a woman or a Black person. As I understand her, Hellman does not want to take a stand on these issues; instead, her point is that, given the correct understanding of what makes a person a woman or Black (whichever that may be), having that property renders her part of the social group of women or Black people.

7 This assumption is fair because such a causal understanding is accepted by many prominent voices in the literature on discrimination, for instance by Lippert-Rasmussen. Admittedly, Hellman devotes a whole chapter of her book to the question whether it is the thought that counts, where it seems that she is arguing against understanding discrimination in a way that relies on the agent’s mental or volitional states (see Hellman, Reference Hellman2008, 143). But here and elsewhere (see Hellman, Reference Hellman and Lippert-Rasmussen2018, 105) it transpires that Hellman is trying to make a different point, namely that the agent’s mental and volitional states are irrelevant to whether their action is demeaning or not. I return to Hellman’s objective-meaning based theory of demeaning presently.

8 Implications (i)–(iii) are to be understood as pro tanto statements, that is, as statements that spell out the normative implications of a discriminatory action considered in isolation. Put differently, the all-of-us intuition is meant be compatible with situations in which it turns out that A’s discriminatory action x is, all things considered, justifiable (for instance, because it is the only way to avoid grave harm to many people) or ends up harming every other member of G worse than B (for instance, because it turns out that, previously, B had engaged in discrimination herself, so that A’s action, albeit wrong, somehow serves to level the playing field). I thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out to me.

9 This holds true even for Lippert-Rasmussen’s condition (5), since (5) only calls for all discriminatory actions vis-à-vis members of G taken together making matters worse for G as a social group in contrast to every discriminatory action making matters worse for every member of G, as called for by implication (ii) of the all-of-us-intuition.

10 Lippert-Rasmussen envisions that this might happen by way of social stigma, as the harmful social stigma that often comes with differential treatment can easily carry over from the person it affects directly to the social group they (presumably) belong to (see Lippert-Rasmussen, Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2014, 168–169).

11 In recent years, a number of authors have proposed pluralist accounts (cf. Moreau, Reference Moreau2020, chapter 5) of the wrong of discrimination. For instance, Tarunabh Khaitan and Sandy Steel argue that “[d]iscriminatory actions are … doubly wrongful” (Khaitan, Reference Khaitan2014, 168) because they violate both the particular duty “not to disadvantage others on the basis of normatively irrelevant characteristics” (Khaitan & Steel, Reference Khaitan, Steel, Collins and Khaitan2017, 199) and the general duty “not to contribute to relative group disadvantage” (Khaitan & Steel, Reference Khaitan, Steel, Collins and Khaitan2017, 200). Sophia Moreau echoes this idea in her Faces of Inequality when she writes that many instances of discrimination contain both “personal wrongs” such as unduly restricting a person’s deliberative freedom and “group wrongs” like sustaining the subordination of a social group. At first glance, such pluralist accounts seem well-suited to accommodate the all-of-us-intuition or at least to avoid falling short of it in the same way Hellman’s account does. But for various reasons, all of these authors refrain from cashing out the morally troublesome aspect of discrimination that concerns groups as a fully fledged wrong, that is, as a wrong vis-à-vis each individual member of the social group in question which grants each of them a moral claim to restitution or, at least, an apology. Khaitan and Steel stress that the general duty not to contribute to relative group disadvantage is “owed not to anyone in particular, but generally to the group in question, or even to one’s society” (Khaitan & Steel, Reference Khaitan, Steel, Collins and Khaitan2017, 200), presumably to avoid granting every member of the social group targeted a legal claim to restitution. The same goes, so I suspect, for Moreau’s insistence that a group wrong “does not generate any distinct claim on the part of any particular members of this group for any special form of restitution” (Moreau, Reference Moreau2020, 166). This shows that neither Khaitan and Steel nor Moreau accept the all-of-us intuition; consequently, their proposals fail to accommodate it.

12 Note that the theory of expressive meaning I favor is compatible with Hellman’s. On Hellman’s understanding, an action such as spitting at someone’s feet expresses disdain because people have decided that, in that context, this is what it means. But if in said context there is a common understanding that spitting at someone’s feet means that they somehow matter less, it will also be reasonable to assume that people who spit at other people’s feet do so because they believe their targets to matter less—which is what needs to be the case for an action to express disdain on my account of expressive meaning. But while my theory includes every action that counts as demeaning on Hellman’s, it can also identify actions as expressing disdain that did not acquire this meaning by convention, but in virtue of the beliefs we can reasonably ascribe to their agents. This reply might raise a different worry, though, namely whether my approach to expressive meaning is still compatible with Hellman’s insistence that the meaning of any particular action is determined by culture and context alone, not by an agent’s mental states (such as their intentions or beliefs). I contend that it is compatible because, on my view, it is not what the agent de facto intends or believes that determines what their action means but what it would be reasonable to assume that the agent intends or believes—and what we can reasonably assume an agent to intend or to believe is, in turn, established by drawing on a society’s common ground. So contrary to possible first impressions, my approach, too, is based on an objective theory of expressive meaning. One thing that follows from such an objective theory is that people cannot dispel the suspicion of having committed an act of discrimination simply by stating that they did not mean to express any disdain by acting in the way that they did. Because on an objective theory of expressive meaning, what A’s actions mean is not determined by what A meant by them but by how they can reasonably be interpreted. Admittedly, A’s de facto intentions factor into such an interpretation—that A says that they did not mean to express any disdain by x-ing is one piece of evidence we should take into account when trying to interpret x. But there may well be countervailing pieces of evidence, for instance, if A is known to be a liar or if it is implausible to assume that A was not aware that x-ing is commonly taken to express disdain. All that is to say that we cannot turn a discriminatory action into a more innocuous case of differential treatment simply by disavowing its disdainful undertones.

13 My understanding of disrespect resembles what Jeremy Waldron writes about hate speech because, according to Waldron, hate speech is “the expressed denial” of the fundamental insight that all people “have an elementary entitlement to justice” (Waldron, Reference Waldron2012, 82f.). Put this way, hate speech is just one particular way in which people are disrespectful.

14 Re’em Segev has recently argued in favor of general accounts of discrimination that “consider all of the moral reasons [that speak for and against some discriminatory action, C.B.] and hold that the content of these reasons is in no way unique to discrimination” (Segev, Reference Segev2021, 256). On Segev’s understanding, my account is not general because, even though the wrong-making features of discrimination are shared by other types of action, it does not present us with an all-things-considered evaluation for every discriminatory action but confines itself to spelling out why discriminatory actions are pro tanto wrong. Consequently, on my understanding, it can be the case that an individual action turns out to be an instance of discrimination and thus pro tanto wrong, while, at the same time, being overall morally justified. Contrary to Segev, I do not consider such a result “unhelpful” (Segev, Reference Segev2021, 268). In my opinion, we increase our moral understanding of the world not only when we grasp how everything shakes out in the end, but also by learning about the individual steps that add up to the final result.

15 As I said earlier, I want my comprehensive conception of discrimination to be compatible with different background theories of morality. But I assume that any sensible theory of morality will insist that ceteris paribus all people have equal moral status and therefore matter equally.

16 A critic might question how seriously we should take Young’s worry since, in everyday life, we ascribe intentions to people all the time. For instance, when we plan lectures, we do so by making assumptions about what our students might be interested in; also, many legal concepts (such as murder or perjury) imply that we are more or less competent in figuring out what people had in mind when acting in a specific way. In my opinion, we should grant both the critic’s and Young’s point: Even though we ascribe intentions to people on a regular basis and often do so competently (or at least confidently), a philosophical theory, especially one about a contentious issue such as discrimination, fares better if it does not rely on such ascriptions. It is to be expected that people accused of discrimination will often deny having the requisite intentions, as such accusation comes with a lot of social stigma. On an intention-based theory of discrimination, we then have to assess the credibility of such denials which, albeit not impossible, is additional work. We can avoid this additional work by not relying on intentions in the first place. I thank an anonymous reviewer for urging me to clarify this point.

17 Interestingly, a critic might also make the opposing point, namely, that dropping the intention requirement makes my conception too narrow. I discuss this objection in Section 5.

18 A critic might reply that, contrary to what I claim here, people would never be justified in calling the employer’s credibility into question since we know for a fact (given how the case is presented) that they are truthful in their statement about their intentions. I would reject this as a case of unhelpful ideal theorizing: in real-world cases, no one ever definitively knows an agent’s intentions. As they cannot hope for an all-knowing philosopher to reliably tell them what ultimately motivates other agents, people are justified in basing their assessment on publicly available information, that is, on what the agents tell them about their motives or how well it fits with widespread patterns of thought and behavior.

19 Might we not say that B has been wronged by being hired for the wrong reason, that is, for (presumably) being meek rather than for being the most qualified candidate? I do not think so. I admit that it would probably hurt B’s feelings if she ever found out the real reason for being hired (and rightly so), but the moral norm guiding our hiring decisions is not fine-grained enough to pick up on this as it is purely outcome- and not intention based. Ceteris paribus, we should hire the candidate who is most qualified for the job. If this happens, as it does in “Committee3,” B is not wronged by the committee’s decision, regardless on the reasoning it was based on. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on this point.

References

Altman, A. (2020). Discrimination. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/discrimination/.Google Scholar
Anderson, E. (2010). The imperative of integration. Princeton University Press.10.1515/9781400836826CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, E., & Pildes, R. (2000). Expressive theories of law: A general restatement. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 148, 15031575. https://doi.org/10.2307/3312748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratu, C. (2023). Toward an expressive account of disrespect. Inquiry. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2023.2211431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eidelson, B. (2015). Discrimination and disrespect. Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198732877.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haslanger, S. (2012). Resisting reality. Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199892631.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hellman, D. (2008). When is discrimination wrong? Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hellman, D. (2018). Discrimination and social meaning. In Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of the ethics of discrimination (pp. 97107). Routledge.Google Scholar
Khaitan, T. (2014). A theory of discrimination law. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Khaitan, T. (2018). Indirect discrimination. In Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of the ethics of discrimination (pp. 3041). Routledge.Google Scholar
Khaitan, T., & Steel, S. (2017). Wrongs, group disadvantage, and the legitimacy of indirect discrimination law. In Collins, H., & Khaitan, T. (Eds.), Foundations of indirect discrimination law (pp. 197221). Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (2014). Born free and equal? Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (2018). The philosophy of discrimination: An introduction. In Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of the ethics of discrimination (pp. 8396). Routledge.Google Scholar
Manne, K. (2018). Down girl: The logic of misogyny. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mikkola, M. (2016). The wrong of injustice. Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190601072.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moreau, S. (2020). Faces of inequality: A theory of wrongful discrimination. Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780190927301.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Segev, R. (2021). General versus special theories of discrimination. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 18, 265298.10.1163/17455243-20203273CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shin, P. (2009). The substantive principle of equal treatment. Legal Theory, 15, 149172. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1352325209090090.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomsen, F. K. (2018). Direct discrimination. In Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of the ethics of discrimination (pp. 1929). Routledge.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. (2012). The harm in hate speech. Cambridge University Press.10.4159/harvard.9780674065086CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wasserman, D. (1998). Discrimination, concept of. In Chadwick, R. (Ed.), Encyclopediaof applied ethics (pp. 805814). Academic Press.Google Scholar
Young, I. M. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton UniversityPress.Google Scholar