Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-smtgx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-10-04T13:39:17.521Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Behavioral Genetics and Human Agency: How Selectively Deterministic Theories of Free Will Drive Unwarranted Opposition to Behavioral Genetic Research and Undermine Our Moral and Legal Conventions, Part II

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 September 2025

Damien Morris*
Affiliation:
Social, Genetic & Developmental Psychiatry Centre, King’s College London, United Kingdom
*
Corresponding author: Damien Morris; Email: damien.morris@kcl.ac.uk

Abstract

This article argues that a pervasive but confused theory of free will is driving unwarranted resistance to behavioral genetic research and undermining the concept of personal responsibility enshrined in our moral and legal conventions. We call this the theory of ‘free-will-by-subtraction’. A particularly explicit version of this theory has been propounded by the psychologist Eric Turkheimer, who has proposed that human agency can be scientifically quantified as the behavioral variation that remains unexplained after known genetic and environmental causes have been accounted for. This theory motivates resistance to research that suggests genetic differences substantially account for differences in human behavior because that is seen to reduce the scope of human freedom. In academic philosophy, free-will-by-subtraction theory corresponds to a position called ‘libertarian incompatibilism’, which holds that human beings are not responsible for behavior that has antecedent causes yet maintains that free will nonetheless exists because some fraction of human behavioral variation is self-caused. However, this position is rejected by most professional philosophers. We argue that libertarian incompatibilism is inconsistent with a secular materialist outlook in which all human behavior is understood to have antecedent causes whether those causes are known to science or not — an outlook Turkheimer shares. We show that Turkheimer sustains this contradiction by adopting an untenable position we call ‘epistemic libertarianism’, which holds that antecedent causes of our behavior only infringe on our freedom if we know about them. By contrast, the overwhelming majority of secular materialist philosophers support a position called ‘compatibilism’, which maintains that free will is compatible with the comprehensive causation of human behavior. We show that compatibilism neutralizes the threat that genetic explanation poses to human agency and rescues a generous conception of personal responsibility that aligns with our moral intuitions.

Information

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of International Society for Twin Studies

4. Nonshared Environmental Influences Do Not Measure Human Agency

In this section we will highlight several fundamental problems with Turkheimer’s theory that the nonshared environmental variance component can be used as a yardstick of human agency. We begin by discussing how Turkheimer’s proposal that we can use the nonshared environment to compare the level of agency we have over different traits has implications just as controversial and politically dangerous as the ‘hereditarian’ perspective it’s proposed as an antidote to.

4.1 A Controversial Implication of Turkheimer’s Nonshared Environment Equals Free Will Thesis

In the second paragraph of ‘Genetics and Human Agency’, Turkheimer poses the question ‘What is the right way to think about genetic influences on sexual orientation?’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 825). Two pages later he answers that question: ‘The nonshared environment captures what is at stake when we are concerned about whether people are able to control their own weight or choose their own sexual orientation or whether they should be held responsible for their criminal behavior’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 827 [emphasis added]). Note first the framing of sexual preference as a ‘choice’ in this sentence. Note also the juxtaposition of that ‘choice’ with criminal responsibility. Now let us revisit Turkheimer’s table of nonshared environmental influences, which he suggests are ‘ordered in terms of their controllability and moral relevance: weight more than height, personality more than intelligence, and depression more than schizophrenia’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 827 [emphasis added]).

In Table 1 (see Part I) we have reproduced Turkheimer’s table of traits in exactly the same order that he listed them. Specifically, note that the table does not order the traits from lowest to highest nonshared environmental variance, but instead arranges them into the pairs that Turkheimer contrasts in the sentence quoted above: weight versus height, personality versus intelligence, depression versus schizophrenia. We have added gridlines to emphasize these pairwise groupings. Only one of these trait comparisons in Table 1 is left conspicuously unstated: sexual preference versus criminality. The clear but unspoken conclusion that Turkheimer invites his readers to draw is that sexual orientation (1-rMZ = 0.5) displays more ‘controllability and moral relevance’ than criminality (1-rMZ = 0.4); that is, that people have more choice over their sexuality than whether or not they commit a crime. This is a remarkable thing to suggest.

Of course, this does not imply that Turkheimer takes personal issue with people’s sexual orientation one way or another — indeed his statement that ‘the term “genetics of sexual orientation” is to be preferred over the term “genetics of homosexuality’’’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 825) in order to avoid pathologizing homosexuality is clear evidence that he does not.

Nevertheless, it should be evident that Turkheimer’s interpretation of the nonshared environment as ‘the free-will coefficient’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021a, p. 12.5), his inferences about what this means for the ‘controllability and moral relevance’ of sexual preference, and his ill-considered juxtaposition of sexual preference with criminal behavior risk buttressing homophobic viewpoints that see homosexuality as a morally charged lifestyle choice.

The incendiary implication that we have more control over our sexual orientation than whether we commit a crime should not prevent us from dispassionately assessing whether Turkheimer’s theory that the nonshared environment is a measure of human agency is valid (though we will presently argue that this theory is not valid). It does, however, show that Turkheimer’s theory of human agency poses downstream political risks remarkably similar to those that are sometimes attributed to ‘hereditarian’ interpretations of behavioral genetic research; namely, of potentially providing ideological ammunition to hate groups or helping to sustain reactionary political ideologies. This example highlights the dangers of using indirect risks as a principle to determine which ideas are discussed and which findings are published. Indirect risks are not always immediately obvious, and the flight from facts or ideas that are perceived to be dangerous can sometimes drive us towards greater dangers.

4.2 Sexual Orientation Is Not a Choice

An important reason it troubles us to hear sexual orientation characterized as more controllable than criminal behavior is that it suggests we can change our sexual orientation at will. But it should be self-evident that this is not the case. Few of us could simply decide to be sexually attracted to a different sex (or sexes) from the one (or two) that we are currently attracted to, any more than we can decide which individuals we are or are not attracted to. We can choose not to act on our desires, and we can even choose to act against our desires, but we cannot normally choose what our desires and preferences are.

One of the things that made the heritability of sexual preference so appealing to gay rights campaigners was that it seemed to imply that same-sex-attracted individuals were ‘born this way’ (Bean, Reference Bean2010; Gaga, Reference Gaga2011). However, this turns out to be a mischaracterization. Yes, there is a genetic component to sexual preference that makes it more likely that monozygotic twins share the same sexual preferences than nonidentical twins, but it is nevertheless quite common for identical twins to have different sexual orientations to each other. Genetics and shared family background both play a smaller role in who we are sexually attracted to than the general public has been led to believe.

Nevertheless, the peculiar circumstances that lead us to be attracted to men versus women, blondes versus brunettes, or whatever other idiosyncratic sexual preferences we find ourselves having, are hardly under our control. When one member of an identical twin pair turns out to be gay and the other turns out to be straight, it is not because they made different choices about who they find attractive. Our sexual orientation, whatever it may be, is not a choice but a brute fact about who we are, shaped by our genetic history, our family history, and our unique personal history. Likewise, just because personality shows nonshared environmental influence of 60%, this does not mean we chose to be outgoing, people-pleasing, neurotic, or conformist, or that we can choose to have a different personality tomorrow to the one we have today.

As Plomin writes in Blueprint, ‘A … crucial discovery … is the unexpected way in which the environment makes us who we are … the environment makes siblings reared in the same family as different as siblings reared in separate families. What makes us different environmentally are random experiences, not systematic forces like families’ (Plomin, Reference Plomin2018, pp. xiii–ix). The nonshared environment often defines who we are as much as our genetic endowment does, substantially explaining our differences from other people. But these random experiences still cause our subsequent behavior as surely as our genetic influences or shared environmental influences do.

4.3 The Nonshared Environment Is Not Experienced as Free Will

This gets us to a fundamental misconception at the heart of Turkheimer’s theory that the nonshared environment measures human agency. Turkheimer writes that, ‘We have a special concern for the genetics of behavior because behavior genetics is experienced genetics’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 827), and for him, the nonshared environment represents the most important domain of human experience because ‘From the point of view of the individual, this represents the degree to which [e.g.,] intelligence is under that individual’s control, as opposed to the degree to which it is limited by either genes or upbringing’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 827). This assertion is the very core of Turkheimer’s argument, and it is false. The nonshared environment is not experienced as the domain of personal control and free will.

If one monozygotic twin suffers a lifelong cognitive impairment because he was struck by lightning, this is an environmental influence he is unlikely to share with his co-twin, but this event can hardly be said to be under his control. Likewise, if a monozygotic twin sustains a life-altering brain injury because a drunk driver collided with her bicycle, her reduced IQ score relative to her co-twin will hardly be a matter of choice. Perversely, Turkheimer’s theory of free will seems to hold the less fortunate twin in these examples responsible for the accident that reduced their cognitive abilities. Even more perversely, it holds the drunk driver only semi-responsible for his crime, because the nonshared environmental estimate for criminal behavior is 0.5.

It might be countered that these kinds of events constitute ‘exogenous within-family environmental differences’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 826) of the kind that Turkheimer lists as further discounts to our agency after accounting for heritable and shared environmental variation, but Turkheimer seems to insist that it is only measured environmental differences that should be discounted in this way. If being struck by lightning or being hit by a drunk driver is not on the checklist of variables that researchers tend to collect as potential predictors of twin differences in adult intelligence, it seems unjust that twins should be held responsible for these differences. Once we recognize that the nonshared environment largely consists of unmeasured environmental differences that twins cannot be held responsible for — illnesses, accidents, and countless other serendipitous advantages and disadvantages that are outside of people’s control — the nonshared environment is entirely invalidated as a meaningful index of human agency.Footnote 21

These examples also throw up another serious problem with Turkheimer’s theory that ‘the nonshared environment … is free will’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 826), namely, that this population variance component tells us nothing about the level of agency any particular individual has over a given trait. The fact that the nonshared environment accounts for ∼20% of the variation in adult intelligence in developed Western countries (see Table 1) reveals nothing about the extent to which genetic, shared environmental, or nonshared environmental influences explain why a particular individual scored well or badly on an IQ test relative to the rest of the population.Footnote 22 In the examples just given, a nonshared environmental insult explains virtually all of the IQ differences between the identical twins and also explains why one twin from each pair performs substantially worse on adult IQ tests than members of the general population. In summary, not only is the magnitude of the nonshared environmental variance uninformative about the extent to which people are responsible for their trait differences across a population, it is also uninformative about the extent to which any individual is responsible for a given behavior — and it is nearly always the extent to which individuals are responsible for their behavior that is the question that concerns us in discussions of personal responsibility.

4.4 ‘Sliding Doors’ as a Parable About Nonshared Environmental Luck

The fact that the attributes of one monozygotic twin cannot be perfectly predicted from the attributes of their co-twin does not necessarily mean the differences between them are under their control, or that the nonshared environmental variance component is a measure of human agency. We can vividly illustrate how the nonshared environment is not a domain of personal choice by enlisting the 1990s Gwyneth Paltrow movie Sliding Doors (Howitt, Reference Howitt1998) which Harden frequently enlists as a teaching device in her own writings and talks. The conceit of Sliding Doors is that the life of Paltrow’s character, Helen, is set on two different courses based on the accident of whether or not she manages to board a particular train. In the reality in which she catches her train, she arrives home in time to find her long-term boyfriend in bed with another woman. Conversely, in an alternate reality where she narrowly misses her train, she never discovers that her boyfriend is having an affair. This discovery or nondiscovery sets her two lives on very different trajectories, one happy, the other tragic.

In her opening remarks for an Intelligence Squared debate in 2019 (Open to Debate, 2019), Harden used Sliding Doors to illustrate that our lives might have turned out very differently if we had have been born into a different family in a different society, saying, ‘What if you had the same genes but you were raised … by a Hazda family in Tanzania?’Footnote 23 This anecdote enlists Sliding Doors as a parable about the luck of the shared environment, the between-family differences that have preoccupied psychologists and other behavioral scientists since Freud. But fundamentally Sliding Doors is a parable about the luck of the nonshared environment, the serendipitous events or unhappy accidents that set our lives on different courses.

Recall that, in twin studies, the nonshared environment is estimated as the fraction of the variation in a particular trait that is not shared by identical twins (1-rMZ). It is an omnibus measure of all the things that lead identical twins to differ from each other after accounting for their identical genes and the environmental experiences they hold in common. In this respect, the two Helens in Sliding Doors are effectively super-identical twins who not only share the same genes, and the same family environments, but even share the same nonshared environmental histories up until a moment in Helen’s mid-20s when her life forks along two different paths in two alternative realities. Moreover, the environmental difference that sets Helen’s life on two different paths is a nonshared environmental experience par excellence. In one reality a little girl blocks Helen’s path down the train station’s stairway. In the other reality the little girl’s mother pulls her out of Helen’s way (see Figure 3). Helen had no control or responsibility over the decisive environmental factor that sets her life on two different courses.

Figure 3. A trivial environmental difference sets Helen’s life on two separate paths in the film Sliding Doors (Howitt, 1998).

In a 1987 paper that first drew wide attention to the major role of the nonshared environment across human behavioral traits, Plomin and Daniels (Reference Plomin and Daniels1987) floated the possibility that the nonshared environment might largely consist of ‘unsystematic, idiosyncratic, or serendipitous events’ like these,Footnote 24 and give the example of a Sliding Doors moment that changed the course of Charles Darwin’s life and thereby altered the course of science and history. Darwin writes: ‘The voyage of the Beagle has been by far the most important event in my life, and has determined my whole career; yet it depended on so small a circumstance as my uncle offering to drive me thirty miles to Shrewsbury’ (Plomin & Daniels, Reference Plomin and Daniels1987, p. 8). However, Plomin and Daniels do not make the mistake of assuming that Darwin was somehow responsible for the ‘serendipitous events’ that secured him a place on the Beagle. They recognize them as matters of pure luck.

As with Darwin, the two Helens are no more responsible for the random incident that set their lives on two different paths than identical twins are for the stochastic developmental variation that makes them different from each other. Harden rightly recoils from the proposition that we might be held responsible for random developmental differences in our brain wiring, which is why she feels compelled to subtract that unknown quantity from the nonshared environmental variation that quantifies human agency (albeit only in a footnote). But she fails to grasp the nettle and take the important final step, which is to recognize that there is no variation in behavior that luck does not explain at some level. All human behavior is ultimately due to antecedent causes of behavior that are outside of the individual’s control. There is no gap in Harden’s (and Turkheimer’s) God-of-the-gaps theory of free will for human agency to get a foothold.Footnote 25 A solid foundation for human agency must instead be sought elsewhere.

4.5 The Nonshared Environment as the Archetypal Domain of Luck

The throughline of Harden’s book, like Turkheimer’s (Reference Turkheimer2011) article, is that ‘Your genotype, like the social class of your family, is an accident of birth over which you had no control’ and ‘a source of luck in your life’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021b, p. 204). On this basis, Harden argues that one’s genetic endowment and one’s family background are both fortuitous sources of lifelong (dis)advantage for which one can take no blame or credit. But the glaring omission in both Turkheimer and Harden’s account is the more obvious role that luck plays in the nonshared environment. Indeed, nonshared environmental luck epitomizes what we ordinarily think of as ‘luck’.

Luck, as traditionally defined, concerns the ordinary fortunes and misfortunes that befall us over the full course of our lives. It does not normally concern the circumstances of our birth. We ordinarily invoke luck when random events work unexpectedly in our favor (or work against us) as compared with how we expected events to unfold based on our efforts and abilities. This has been the traditional conception of ‘Lady Luck’ since ancient times, personified in the Roman goddess Fortuna and the Greek goddess Tyche, who represents the capricious role of Chance in our lives. She is the fickle goddess who can propel a mediocre athlete to victory by making stronger competitors stumble or who can turn a battle in a smaller army’s favor through a serendipitous weather event. These lucky and unlucky breaks don’t account for all of the nonshared environmental variance. For instance, one identical twin in each pair can be reliably faster than the other because they train harder or have more fast twitch muscle fibres. But unlike differences in abilities, which produce predictable and reliable differences in people’s performance, luck in this conventional sense, is unpredictable and unreliable by definition. Buying a winning lottery ticket is the textbook example of this kind of luck, where overnight a person’s financial prospects are improved beyond what a lifetime of ordinary strivings could accomplish.

The Genetic Lottery invites us to take this quintessential example of nonshared environmental luck and extend it to the genetic and the shared environmental domains — and, of course, there is a certain sense in which our genetic endowments and the type of family we were born into are also matters of what we might call ‘cosmic’ luck.Footnote 26 But Harden has neglected the role of luck in the nonshared environment, which is its archetypal domain. If we follow Harden’s exculpatory logic that we are not responsible for any behavior that can ultimately be traced to fortuitous antecedent causes, then we are forced to accept that it’s luck all the way down — to accept, as the philosopher Galen Strawson famously put it, that ‘luck swallows everything’ (Strawson, Reference Strawson2016).Footnote 27 This is precisely the conclusion reached by free will skeptics like the philosopher Greg Caruso who, in the passage below, describes three kinds of luck that we encounter in our lives:

First, there is the initial ‘lottery of life’ or ‘luck of the draw,’ over which we have no say. Whether we are born into poverty or affluence, war or peace, abusive or loving homes, is simply a matter of luck. It is also a matter of luck what natural gifts, talents, predispositions, and physical traits we are born with. Beyond this initial lottery of life, there is also the luck of what breaks one encounters during one’s period of self-formation, and what environmental influences are most salient to us. (Dennett & Caruso, Reference Dennett and Caruso2021, p. 23 [emphasis added])

These three categories of luck essentially describe shared environmental luck, genetic luck, and nonshared environmental luck respectively, and for Caruso these three categories are exhaustive. Under this view, there is no corner of human behavior that luck does not explain.

5. Situating Turkheimer and Harden Within the Academic Free Will Debate

Having provided several initial critiques of Turkheimer’s theory that the nonshared environment can be used as an index of human agency, we will now proceed to contextualize Turkheimer’s and Harden’s views on free will within the academic free will debate. This will help us to better understand both of their positions and highlight what we will argue is a core philosophical confusion at the heart of their respective free-will-by-subtraction theories.

5.1 The Three Major Positions on Free Will in Academic Philosophy

In academic philosophy, there are three main positions staked out in the free will debate: compatibilism, free will skepticism, and libertarianism:

Compatibilists (sometimes called ‘soft determinists’) maintain that human agency, personal responsibility, and moral desert (that is, praiseworthiness or blameworthiness for our actions) are fully compatible with a deterministic universe in which causation reigns and in which history was always going to unfold as it did. They argue that the key question for deciding whether an agent is responsible for his actions is not whether his behavior was determined and/or has antecedent causes, but rather whether he could have acted differently if he had wanted to do so badly enough (M. S. Moore, Reference Moore2016).Footnote 28 The philosopher Daniel Dennet is one of the best-known contemporary evangelists for this position (Dennett, Reference Dennett1984, Reference Dennett2004), but notable historical compatibilists include Thomas Hobbes and David Hume (Hobbes, Reference Hobbes1656; Hume, Reference Hume1739).

Free will skeptics (sometimes called ‘hard determinists’) maintain that we cannot be held responsible for any of our actions because the ultimate causes of those actions are outside of our control. Some of the best known free will skeptics in contemporary academic philosophy are Galen Strawson and Derk Pereboom (Pereboom, Reference Pereboom2001; Strawson, Reference Strawson2016). The neuroscientists Sam Harris and Robert Sapolsky are both prominent advocates for this position (Harris, Reference Harris2012; Sapolsky, Reference Sapolsky2023).

Libertarians maintain that human behavior is not entirely determined — either because indeterministic properties of the universe (e.g., at the quantum level) make human decisions inherently unpredictable, or because human beings are endowed with metaphysical powers that free them from the laws of causation that govern the rest of the natural world, allowing them to become uncaused causes of subsequent events. A dualistic, supernatural model of agent causation is the implicit position on free will maintained in many religious traditions, but ‘folk’ conceptions of free will often uncritically inherit the libertarian conception of human beings as self-causing agents even in secular communities (Sarkissian et al., Reference Sarkissian, Chatterjee, De Brigard, Knobe, Nichols and Sirker2010). Prominent agent-causation libertarians include Roderick Chisholm, Richard Taylor, and Timothy O’Connor (Chisholm, Reference Chisholm1964; Taylor, Reference Taylor1966; O’Connor, Reference O’Connor2000). The neurogeneticist Kevin Mitchell supports a kind of quantum libertarianism (Mitchell, Reference Mitchell2020a, Reference Mitchell2020b).

Libertarianism and free will skepticism are both classified as ‘incompatibilist’ positions because they hold that human agency and moral responsibility are incompatible with conditions under which our behavior is determined by antecedent causes. The main difference between these two positions is that free will skeptics hold that all of our behavior is ultimately dictated by antecedent causes, while libertarians claim that human behavior is incompletely determined by preceding events and that this affords us wiggle room to shape our own behavior to some extent.

It should be noted, however, that neither compatibilism nor free will skepticism hinge on determinism being strictly true. Proponents of both positions acknowledge that there are properties of the universe that appear to be indeterministic at the quantum scale and are prepared to accept the possibility that these indeterministic phenomena could have repercussions at the macroscopic scale in which humans operate. Neither position would be invalidated, then, if quantum indeterminacy somehow rendered human behavior inherently unpredictable to some extent and if more than one future were strictly possible at any given moment.

The key debate between compatibilists and free will skeptics is whether human beings can be held responsible when the ultimate causes of their actions are outside of their control. Both positions are indifferent to the question of whether those causes are deterministic or indeterministic. For this reason, some free will skeptics prefer to describe their position as ‘hard incompatibilism’ rather than ‘hard determinism’ (Pereboom, Reference Pereboom2001).Footnote 29 Alternatively, they sometimes refer to their position as ‘hard luck’ (Levy, Reference Levy2011), highlighting the notion that we cannot be held responsible for our behavior when the particular set of causes that drove our behavior are ultimately matters of chance.Footnote 30

5.2 Turkheimer Is a Libertarian, Not a Compatibilist

Confusingly, Turkheimer and Harden both present Turkheimer’s nonshared environmental theory of free will as a compatibilist theory when it is not. For example, in ‘Heritability and Biological Explanation’, Turkheimer writes: ‘Philosophers are less likely to agree than even social scientists, but a broad area of consensus has emerged about how these questions might be answered. In the free-will literature, this point of view is known as compatibilism’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer1998, p. 790). Turkheimer then represents his own position on free will as belonging to this philosophical consensus and repeatedly namedrops the compatibilist philosopher Daniel Dennett as though they were fellow travelers in the same philosophical tradition.

Harden follows suit, and uses the title of one of Dennett’s best known books to describe Turkheimer’s theory of free will, writing: ‘To borrow a phrase from the philosopher Daniel Dennett, [the nonshared environment] lets you know how much “elbow room” you have to choose who are you [sic] going to be’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021b, p. 202). But the compatibilist theory of free will outlined in Dennett’s (Reference Dennett1984) book Elbow Room and defended across his philosophical career diametrically opposes the position staked out by Turkheimer and Harden.Footnote 31 Neither does Turkheimer’s theory correspond to the position defended by any other notable compatibilist philosopher.

Far from being a compatibilist, Turkheimer is, in fact, a libertarian incompatibilist. He is an incompatibilist in the sense that he holds that antecedent genetic and environmental causes of behavior infringe upon human agency, and a libertarian in the sense that he treats antecedent causes of human behavior as nonexhaustive, leaving some uncaused fraction of behavioral variation that human agency explains.

The unusual sense in which Turkheimer describes himself as a ‘compatibilist’ is merely to signal that he is he is a secular materialist who supports the existence of free will in contrast to those who would invoke supernatural explanations for human agency. We see this, for example, when he writes, ‘The nonshared environment, in a phrase, is free will. Not the kind of metaphysical free will that no one believes in anymore, according to which human souls float free above the mechanistic constraints of the physical world, but an embodied free will, tethered to biology’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 826 [emphasis added]). However, despite his peremptory dismissal of metaphysical libertarianism in this passage, Turkheimer’s conception of free will bears several fundamental characteristics in common with it.

First, note that under many, if not most, libertarian conceptions of free will, human behavior remains partly subject to physical laws rather than being completely independent of them. Second, consider that under a metaphysical conception of free will in which human beings are partially self-causing agents, we would expect the miraculous, contra-causal workings of the unique soul of each identical twin to manifest precisely as nonshared environmental variance in behavior genetic analyses (i.e., as differences in behavior that could not be predicted from their shared genetic and environmental backgrounds). This would be a special subcategory of nonshared environmental variation that was different from the prosaic kind produced by the ‘exogenous within-family environmental differences’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 826) that behavioral scientists try to identify — just like the subcategory of nonshared environmental variance that Turkheimer says is a measure of free will. It would also be different from the nonshared environmental variance contributed by measurement error, or by stochastic developmental variation.

By suggesting that nonshared environmental variance is a measure of human agency, Turkheimer is effectively proposing that twin differences in behavior are self-caused rather than externally caused. He explicitly writes that the nonshared environment captures ‘the self-determinative ability of humans to chart a course for their own lives’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 826). Far from offering a sophisticated materialist conception of human agency that offers an alternative to supernatural conceptions of free will, Turkheimer’s theory simply rehearses the dualistic notion that there are special domains of human behavior which ‘float free above the mechanistic constraints of the physical world’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 826) without presenting a nonsupernatural explanation for how human beings can possibly accomplish that (see Figure 4).

Figure 4. Turkheimer suggests the nonshared environmental variation is an index of agent self-causation without explaining how non-miraculous self-causation can possibly occur. Cartoon by Sidney Harris (image reproduced with permission of ScienceCartoonsPlus.com©).

5.3 Indeterministic and Chaotic Causes of Behavior Cannot Support Free will

The fundamental challenge facing secularized libertarian perspectives on free will is that they beg the question of precisely how human beings are supposed to acquire the power of self-causation (i.e., of being an ‘uncaused cause’ or an ‘unmoved mover’). The possibility of quantum indeterminism at the human scale does not supply this positive account. It is unclear why people should be considered any more responsible for actions dictated by a cosmic coin toss than for actions dictated by the inexorable march of history.Footnote 32 These indeterministic causes would still present the same problem as deterministic causes, that is, of being antecedent sources of our behavior that are outside of our control.Footnote 33 As Sam Harris writes:

Some scientists and philosophers hope that chance or quantum uncertainty can make room for free will. … [However, if] my decision to have a second cup of coffee this morning was due to a random release of neurotransmitters, how could the indeterminacy of the initiating event count as the free exercise of my will? Chance occurrences are by definition ones for which I can claim no responsibility. And if certain of my behaviors are truly the result of chance, they should be surprising even to me. How would neurological ambushes of this kind make me free? … [Q]uantum indeterminacy does nothing to make the concept of free will scientifically intelligible. In the face of any real independence from prior events, every thought and action would seem to merit the statement ‘I don’t know what came over me.’ (Harris, Reference Harris2012, p. 24 [emphasis added])

Similar challenges confront attempts to base free will on ‘deterministic chaos’ (i.e., the unpredictability of complex systems which are highly sensitive to infinitesimal differences in starting conditions). Turkheimer repeatedly appeals to the ‘complexity’ and ‘interactivity’ of genetic and environmental causes as though these characteristics could somehow generate human agency, but a cause is a cause, irrespective of whether it is simple or complex. If human agency requires us to be the ultimate cause of our own actions, it is disqualified by antecedent causes of any kind, regardless of whether they are systematic or unsystematic, deterministic or indeterministic.Footnote 34

Harden notes that Turkheimer takes ‘Unpredictability [as] a sign of freedom’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021b, p. 202), but while complex or indeterministic causes pose serious challenges for the scientific prediction of human behavior, they provide no firmer basis for personal responsibility than simple or deterministic causes do. Under the logic of incompatibilism, the only kind of unpredictability that could potentially signal human agency would be the unpredictability arising from self-causing agents whose actions were thereby genuinely independent of antecedent events. However, human behavior can be unpredictable for many, far less exotic reasons, meaning unpredictability cannot be safely interpreted as an index of human agency. Besides, without a positive, secular account of how agent self-causation might be possible, there is no compelling reason to believe that it actually exists (Pereboom, Reference Pereboom1995). Belief in self-causing agents seems to demand the same leap of faith as the religious belief in an immaterial soul.

5.4 Harden’s Libertarian Incompatibilism: Less Libertarian and More Incompatibilist

In The Genetic Lottery, Harden provides a sympathetic summary of Turkheimer’s nonshared environmental theory of free will that is even longer than the article in which Turkheimer originally presented it (Harden, Reference Harden2021b). She also dedicates several pages of her review in the Annual Review of Psychology to his theory (Harden, Reference Harden2021a). But despite giving Turkheimer’s theory substantial real estate in two publications intended to convey her overarching philosophy of behavioral genetics, Harden never gives an unequivocal endorsement of Turkheimer’s position, leaving some uncertainty about whether his and her views are entirely the same.Footnote 35 We will show that both of their positions are philosophically very close, but with some important practical differences.

When we look at Harden’s explicit statements about the nature of free will, we find her initially reserving judgment about whether human behavior is fully determined by antecedent causes or whether we have a metaphysical capacity for self-causation. In The Genetic Lottery she writes: ‘Whether the universe is deterministic, whether such a thing as free will actually exists — these questions are beyond the scope of this book’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021b, p. 200).

Likewise, in her Annual Review article she writes:

Whether one can glean from twin studies any information about a person’s metaphysical freedom to do otherwise is, to put it mildly, controversial. But even if we put aside metaphysical discussions about whether people really have free will, identical twins provide a glimpse into how constrained one’s life path is by one’s starting point in life. (Harden, Reference Harden2021a, p. 12.6)

Note that while Harden reserves judgment about whether human behavior is completely determined here, she has already tacitly accepted the incompatibilist premise that we are not free to the extent that we can ultimately trace the causes of our behavior to events outside of our control. She also appears to have accepted the incompatibilist premise that ‘real’ free will consists of the metaphysical ability to act differently from how antecedent conditions lead us to behave. Harden then proceeds to give several indications that she does not believe the world is completely deterministic. A first indication is in her Annual Review article, where she writes:

You only have one life to live, but if you rewound the tape and started anew from the exact same genetic and environmental starting point, how differently could your life go? Overall, twin research suggests that, in your alternative life, you might not have gotten divorced, you might have made more money, you might be more extraverted or organized — but you are unlikely to be substantially different in your cognitive ability, education, or mental disease. (Harden, Reference Harden2021a, p. 12.7)

This passage implicitly rejects determinism. In a deterministic universe, if someone ‘rewound the tape’, your life (and everyone else’s) would unfold in exactly the same way as before. You would still have gotten divorced, made precisely the same amount of money, and been just as shy and disorganized. More generally, under determinism, every individual was always going to follow the path they did, because the history of the universe was always inevitably going to unfold the way it has from the moment of the big bang. It is only in an indeterministic universe that we could expect things to turn out any differently if we ‘rewound the tape’ and let it play out again — either because of random quantum-style indeterminacy or because human beings have special contra-causal powers of self-determination.

Another indication that Harden does not take the prospect of determinism seriously is the brevity with which she discusses hard determinism, dedicating just a short, two-sentence aside to this position. She writes, ‘If you think that the universe is deterministic, and the existence of free will is incompatible with a deterministic universe, and free will is an illusion, then genetics doesn’t have anything to add to the conversation. Genetics is just a tiny corner of the universe where we have worked out a little bit of the larger deterministic chain’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021b, p. 200).Footnote 36 However, if hard determinism gets short shrift, compatibilism is overlooked completely, with Harden providing no discussion about how or why personal responsibility might be compatible with antecedent causation of behavior. Instead, we are treated to an extended disquisition on how genetic and environmental causes of behavior diminish people’s responsibility for any crimes they commit and reduces the credit they can take for their achievements in life.Footnote 37

What we are left with is a de facto libertarian incompatibilism in which some unspecified sliver of human behavioral variation mysteriously survives the general annihilation of personal responsibility that antecedent causes otherwise produce. Harden’s libertarianism is manifest in the fact that she still clearly believes that some forms of responsibility exist. Despite dedicating an entire chapter of The Genetic Lottery to the topic of how genetic and environmental causes of our behavior diminish our responsibility, the book is filled with moral and political exhortations about what we ‘must’ or ‘should not’ do, and repeatedly discusses ‘our social responsibilities’ to reduce inequality.Footnote 38 In addition, Harden’s belief in responsibility is displayed in her scathing moral condemnation of scientists like Francis Galton, Karl Pearson, Ronald Fisher, and Henry Goddard, at whose feet she lays the ultimate blame for Nazi genocide and for forced sterilization programs carried out elsewhere.Footnote 39

Harden fails to provide a coherent positive account of how human agency can arise under conditions in which our behavior has antecedent causes, but like Turkheimer she sometimes appeals to deterministic chaos to explain the nonshared environmental variance. She references a scene from the film Jurassic Park in which Jeff Goldblum’s character, a mathematician specializing in chaos theory, illustrates the inherent unpredictability of complex systems by showing how two droplets of water fail to follow the same path down his interlocutor’s hand. ‘It changed. Why?’, he explains, ‘Because tiny variations — the orientation of the hair on your hands, the amount of blood distending your vessels, imperfections in the skin … — never repeat and vastly affect the outcome’ (Spielberg, Reference Spielberg1993). From this, Harden concludes: ‘[The nonshared environment] represents differences between people that are not due to differences … in their DNA or in the social circumstances into which they were born. [The nonshared environment] reflects the degree to which two identical drops of water, beginning in the same place, fall off in different directions’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021b, p. 201).

However, if infinitesimal differences in initial conditions are the ultimate wellspring of the twin differences captured by the nonshared environment, twins can hardly be held responsible for those differences in starting conditions. When two water droplets follow different paths down a surface, we do not say the droplets have agency. As discussed above, attempts to base human agency on deterministic chaos founder on the problem that these antecedent causes of human behavior are also outside of the individual’s control — just like people’s genetic endowment or the family they were born into.

Unlike Turkheimer, Harden does not suggest that people should be held responsible for actions caused by the kind of indeterministic chaos that makes identical twins different from each other, but this makes it unclear how personal responsibility is supposed to arise at all in Harden’s philosophical framework. Her remarks about the contribution of deterministic chaos to the nonshared environmental variation mirror her previously mentioned comments about the contribution of stochastic developmental variation. We are again left with the implication that the nonshared environment represents at best, ‘an upper bound of the extent to which people have agency’, after stochastic developmental variation and other sources of deterministic chaos have been removed (alongside measurement error, and ‘exogenous within-family environmental differences’). As with Turkheimer, we are left with the conception that some portion of human behavioral variation is effectively attributed to agent self-causation. However, once again no positive account is provided as to how this self-causation can possibly arise.

The main difference between Harden’s libertarian incompatibilism and Turkheimer’s is that Turkheimer reserves almost the entirety of the nonshared environmental variation as a refuge for free will, while Harden is prepared to concede that nearly all of it might be attributable to antecedent causes of our behavior that are outside of our control (whether we have identified the specific causes of that nonshared environmental variation or not). Harden is prepared to accommodate this anemic conception of human agency because it is easy to reconcile with the Rawlsian equity ethics that she champions in her book. Rawls likewise endorses a conception of free will and personal responsibility that is minimal at best, as we explore briefly in section 8 (see Part III). This makes Harden considerably more sanguine about genetic and shared environmental causation of human behavior than Turkheimer.

Turkheimer, by contrast, is keen to preserve a much larger role for human agency. However, as a libertarian incompatibilist, this goal obliges him to carve out a large fraction of human behavioral variation that is not explained by antecedent causes. In the next section, we will explore an alternative formulation of Turkheimer’s libertarian theory of free will that allows him to substantially expand the scope of human agency beyond the confines of the nonshared environmental variance to encompass parts of the heritable and shared environmental variation as well. Turkheimer adopts two questionable strategies to achieve this goal: first, he seeks to reduce all causes of human behavioral variation down to the causes that we know about; and second, he actively seeks to downplay our knowledge of those causes of variation.

6. Ignorance Is Not Freedom

Earlier, in section 4, we tried to show that nonshared environmental influences are just as deterministic of human behavior as genetic and shared environmental influences. We marshalled several examples of environmental exposures that would produce different outcomes for identical twins and are not under their deliberate control; for example, being struck by lightning, being hit by a drunk driver, or being obstructed on the way to catching a train (one could think of countless others). We did this to highlight that the nonshared environmental sources of individual differences are every bit as fortuitous as genetic and shared environmental sources, and also to highlight that there are innumerably more nonshared environmental influences that affect our life outcomes than the ones typically measured by behavioral scientists. Turkheimer’s position that the nonshared environment represents a nonsupernatural escape hatch through which we can slip the causal chains of the deterministic universe is mistaken, and the root of his confusion is that he uses our ignorance about some of the specific causes of human behavioral variation as evidence that those behavioral differences are uncaused and self-caused. He enlists that ignorance as evidence for our metaphysical freedom.Footnote 40

We see this when Turkheimer writes: ‘In any world we can plausibly imagine, there will be significant limits on our ability to predict who will become [e.g.] depressed because the hyper-complex contingencies of a freely led life will always intercede between our knowledge of the family environment and the genome on the one hand and complex human outcomes on the other’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 827 [emphasis added]).Footnote 41 It is also implicit in his general stance, described by Harden, that ‘Unpredictability [is] a sign of freedom’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021b, p. 202). Turkheimer promotes the idea that unpredictability is evidence for agent self-causation under the banner of what he calls ‘the gloomy prospect’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2000, Reference Turkheimer2019a; Turkheimer & Waldron, Reference Turkheimer and Waldron2000).

6.1 The Moral Inversion of the ‘Gloomy Prospect’

Turkheimer’s investment of the nonshared environment with the special property of being able to measure human agency has its roots in a longstanding scientific debate about the nature of that variance component. The main contours of that debate were initially outlined by Plomin and Daniels (Reference Plomin and Daniels1987) who wrote: ‘What is happening environmentally to make children in the same family so different from one another? One gloomy prospect is that the salient environment might be unsystematic, idiosyncratic, or serendipitous events such as accidents, illnesses, and other traumas, as biographies often attest.’ (p. 8 [emphasis added]).

While they were the first to raise this ‘gloomy prospect’, Plomin and Daniels suggested that we should first investigate whether specific nonshared environments could be identified that accounted for this large source of individual differences in human behavior before throwing in the towel, writing: ‘[U]ntil more systematic research on nonshared environmental variance sources is conducted it is too early to conclude that the large environmental component of variance … is brought about by idiosyncratic experiences’ (Plomin & Daniels, Reference Plomin and Daniels1987, p. 6). However, after embarking on a multi-decade search for specific nonshared environments that explain this large fraction of behavioral variation, Plomin has become convinced of the reality of the gloomy prospect, writing: ‘After thirty years of searching unsuccessfully for systematic non-shared environmental influences, it’s time to accept the gloomy prospect. Non-shared environmental influences are unsystematic, idiosyncratic, serendipitous events without lasting effects’ (Plomin, Reference Plomin2018, p. 80).

By contrast, Turkheimer and his co-author Mary Waldron had already declared science’s defeat at the hands of the gloomy prospect in the year 2000, barely a decade after the search had begun. After conducting a review of existing studies that found that less than 3% of the variance in behavioral traits could typically be explained by measured nonshared environmental influences, Turkheimer and Waldron (Reference Turkheimer and Waldron2000) declared that the search should be called off. ‘The gloomy prospect is true’, Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2000) separately proclaimed (p. 163).

Turkheimer and Waldron partly present this verdict as a lesson in scientific humility, for example, writing ‘The limitations of our existing social scientific methodologies ought not provoke us to wish that human behavior were simpler than we know it to be’ (Turkheimer & Waldron, Reference Turkheimer and Waldron2000, p. 93). But crucially, they also went much further than this, actively celebrating the fact science may have hit an epistemological barrier. They wrote: ‘a world in which human behavior could be understood all the way down in terms of correlations between difference scores … would present its own gloomy prospects in the ethical evaluation of human agency’ (Turkheimer & Waldron, Reference Turkheimer and Waldron2000, p. 93 [emphasis added]).

Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2000) hit the same celebratory note, writing, ‘Finally, it must be remembered that the gloomy prospect is gloomy only from the point of view of the working social scientist. … In the long run, the gloomy prospect always wins, and no one would want to live in a world where it did not. … The gloomy prospect isn’t [gloomy].’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2000, p. 164 [emphasis added]). Here we see a complete inversion of Plomin and Daniels’ gloomy prospect, in which scientific pessimism about the prospects of explaining human behavior becomes a source of moral and metaphysical optimism.

Note that the sentiment expressed here is no longer simply concern about scientific hubris and overreach. It is a particularly candid expression of what Daniel Dennett has called the fear of creeping exculpation: ‘Is science going to show us that nobody ever deserves punishment? Or praise, for that matter?’ (Dennett, Reference Dennett2004, p. 21). It is a libertarian incompatibilist concern that human beings will lack agency to the extent that their behavior is shown to have antecedent causes. Readers are invited to hope that some fraction of the nonshared environmental variation will never be explained by science, as full explanation would mean the extinction of human agency. It therefore becomes ‘methodologically vexing [but] humanistically pleasing’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2000, p. 161) when science fails to isolate the specific causes of differences in human behavior.

In Turkheimer and Waldron (Reference Turkheimer and Waldron2000), then, we already see the skeleton of the nonshared environmental theory of free will that Turkheimer would flesh out 11 years later in ‘Genetics and Human Agency’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011). Moreover, in his later writings, Turkheimer would make the relationship between his inverted gloomy prospect and his theory of free will even clearer, writing: ‘The gloomy prospect … is gloomy for working scientists, but for individual people it is freedom; it is human agency’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2019a, p. 125 [emphasis added]).

6.2 Turkheimer Extends the ‘Gloomy Prospect’ to Heritability

The foundations for Turkheimer’s nonshared environmental theory of free will may have been laid in Turkheimer and Waldron (Reference Turkheimer and Waldron2000), but in ‘The three laws of behavior genetics and what they mean’, Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2000) extended that theory in an important new direction. After reiterating Turkheimer and Waldron’s conclusion that the gloomy prospect prevails for the nonshared environment, and embellishing their fledgling idea that the gloomy prospect might represent a refuge for human agency, Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2000) generalized the gloomy prospect beyond the nonshared environment to other variance components, with a particular emphasis on the heritable variation. Turkheimer writes:

There is an interesting parallel between the search for individual genes that influence behavior and the failed attempt to specify the nonshared environment in terms of measured environmental variables. In each case, investigators began with statistically reliable but causally vague sources of variance, and set out to discover the actual causal processes that produced them. … The gloomy prospect looms larger for the genome project than is generally acknowledged. (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2000, p. 164)

While Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2011) would later argue that any variance in the nonshared environment left unexplained by specific environmental measures quantified human agency, the extension of the gloomy prospect in Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2000) had already laid the grounds for a more radical position: namely, that the variance unexplained by specific variables under any variance component quantifies human freedom.

Both positions are libertarian, free-will-by-subtraction theories of human agency in which the total causes of human behavioral variation are treated as being limited to and co-extensive with the known causes of behavioral variation. However, the generalized genetic-plus-environmental gloomy prospect in Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2000) accommodates an even larger potential role for agent self-causation, mainly because any heritable variation which is not explained by specific genetic variants is also deemed a potential refuge for human agency. While the genetic dimension of this extended gloomy prospect was neglected in Turkheimer’s theory of free will as it was presented in Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2011), championing the genetic gloomy prospect has been a persistent focus of Turkheimer’s public commentary as the molecular behavioral genetics revolution has gained momentum.

6.3 Turkheimer’s Epistemic Libertarianism: Defining Ignorance as Freedom

It is worth taking a moment to stress what an extraordinary position Turkheimer has staked out by making himself the flagbearer of the gloomy prospect. The gloomy prospect is not merely the claim that science has already hit (or will someday hit) a limit regarding how much behavioral variation it can explain. It is an active celebration of the prospect that science will hit that limit — and the sooner the better! It is nothing less than the hope that behavioral science will stop advancing. This is a remarkably antiscientific position for a practicing behavioral scientist to take.

Unfortunately, Turkheimer’s theory of human agency occasionally lurches in an even more antiscientific direction. Instead of implicitly defending metaphysical libertarianism as discussed above, he sometimes defends a position that we might call epistemic libertarianism, that is, rather than arguing that the nonexhaustive scientific explanation of human behavior leaves room for the possibility of self-causation, Turkheimer sometimes defends the eccentric position that it is ignorance of the causes of human behavior that generates human agency.Footnote 42

We see Turkheimer’s epistemic libertarianism in action when he argues that unexplained behavioral variation captures human agency (‘the gloomy prospect … is freedom’, Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2019a, p. 125) while simultaneously acknowledging that unexplained variation is attributable to unknown causes that might one day yield to scientific investigation. This implies that it is our knowledge of the causes of human behavior that infringes on our freedom rather than causation as such.

Turkheimer and Waldron (Reference Turkheimer and Waldron2000) acknowledge that the unexplained variation consists of unidentified causes when they write, ‘something about the environment must be causing differences among genetically related siblings reared together’ (Turkheimer & Waldron, Reference Turkheimer and Waldron2000, p. 90 [emphasis added]).Footnote 43 They likewise acknowledge that those unidentified causes of behavior might eventually yield to scientific explanation when they write:

New methodological paradigms will no doubt evolve … but some aspects of the development of complex human behavior may remain outside the domain of systematic scientific investigation for a very long time … a substantial portion of human development remains too complex, too interactive, and too resistant to controlled investigation and straightforward statistical methods to yield to systematic scientific analysis as we currently understand it. (Turkheimer & Waldron, Reference Turkheimer and Waldron2000, p. 93 [emphasis added])

Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2000) also acknowledges that the nonshared environment consists of antecedent causes of human behavior but proposes that these causes are currently too complex for scientists to understand. He writes, ‘Nonshared environmental variability predominates … because of the unsystematic effects of all environmental events, compounded by the equally unsystematic processes that expose us to environmental events in the first place’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2000, p. 163). He then proceeds to say that ‘Psychology is at least one good paradigm shift away from an empirical answer to the gloomy prospect’, conceding that much of the variation in human behavior that remains unexplained by specific genetic and environmental measures might someday yield to scientific investigation.

However, perhaps the starkest example of Turkheimer defending the idea that ignorance is itself freedom is in a Twitter thread he published in September 2022 where he wrote:

we are born with genetic constraints on our personality, but unless we have an identical twin we have no way of knowing what those constraints are! We never will. … This is how you can have a realistic behavior genetics with its sensible methodological consequences, without determinism. Genetic differences do affect our outcomes, but the nature of those effects are in principle beyond our knowledge. (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2022f [emphasis added])

Here Turkheimer openly acknowledges that actual genetic constraints on our behavior exist but then suggests that whether we have an identical twin or not affects how free (vs. determined) our behavior is simply by conferring knowledge about how much of our behavior is predictable from our co-twin’s behavior.

To consider what an extraordinary statement this is, consider the documentary film Three Identical Strangers about three monozygotic triplets reared apart who discover at age 19 that they have genetically identical siblings (Wardle, Reference Wardle2018). The lives of these three men were not suddenly more determined after they discovered they were triplets. The discovery simply revealed how determined they already were by their genetic influences. This error in Turkheimer’s logic was pointed out almost immediately by a respondent on Twitter who replied: ‘Comprehension isn’t a prerequisite for determinism. A deterministic system is still deterministic even in the absence of observers with knowledge of its workings’ (KuremaSan, 2022). Turkheimer never replied to this astute remark.Footnote 44

As the philosopher and legal scholar Michael Moore has noted, epistemic libertarianism ‘is a non-starter on its face’, because ‘[t]he degree of our knowledge of the causes of someone else’s choice can obviously have no bearing on the degree of their responsibility’ (M. S. Moore, Reference Moore2016, p. 59). It entails the ‘crude mistake’ of ‘slip[ping] from one’s own partial ignorance of causation to … partial absence of causation’ (p. 59 [emphasis added]).Footnote 45 Moore concludes that ‘to [clearly] state this view is pretty much to refute it’ (p. 59).Footnote 46

How is it, then, that Turkheimer sometimes finds himself advancing such an indefensible position? We submit that he is backed into this awkward intellectual corner because he is caught between his libertarian conception of free will and his professed secular materialism. As a secular materialist he cannot concede the existence of miraculously uncaused human behavior, yet his libertarian conception of human agency simultaneously demands it. Epistemic libertarianism offers a convenient way to hold these two contradictory ideas at the same time. But ignorance provides no escape hatch from the iron logic of incompatibilism. If one accepts the notion that human agency is incompatible with antecedent causation and also accepts that all human behavior has antecedent causes, one is obliged to accept hard incompatibilism and the nonexistence of free will (see Figure 5). Appeals to the irreducible complexity or scientific intractability of those causes cannot avert this conclusion.

Figure 5. The free will trilemma. The three main positions adopted in the academic free will debate represent three possible solutions to a trilemma in which only two of the three circled propositions can be logically subscribed to simultaneously: Libertarianism (A+B), Compatibilism (A+C), or Free will skepticism (B+C). Turkheimer champions a libertarian theory of free will which emphasizes the existence of personal responsibility (A), and the incompatibility of antecedent genetic and environmental causes of behavioral variation with personal responsibility (B); however, Turkheimer’s secular materialism compels him to simultaneously support the proposition that all human behavior has antecedent causes (C). But proposition C cannot be logically supported without rejecting proposition A or B. Turkheimer appeals to the scientific intractability of complex causes of behavior as a refuge for personal responsibility, but it is left unclear why personal responsibility would only be infringed by the causes known to science. Note that Turkheimer sometimes claims to be a compatibilist on the basis that he nominally supports propositions A and C, but this is untenable without rejecting proposition B.

Turkheimer attempts to paper over this problem by labelling himself a ‘compatibilist’, but compatibilism is not the proposition that human agency resides in the causes of human behavioral variation that remain unexplained. It is the position that free will and personal responsibility are compatible with the comprehensive causation of human behavior (encompassing known and unknown causes of human behavioral differences). By insisting we can ‘quantif[y] human agency … as the variability that remains after genetic and environmental … constraints have been taken into account’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2000, p. 827), Turkheimer has forfeited the argument that human agency is compatible with causation. There is no coherent basis for arguing that people are more responsible when the causes of their behavior are unknown rather than known. This is selective incompatibilism, not compatibilism. Mislabeling epistemic libertarianism as a ‘compatibilist’ position only serves to cloak a philosophically indefensible position in the authority of a respectable and widely held position in academic philosophy.

An unfortunate upshot of the eccentric position that knowledge itself infringes on human agency is that it implicitly creates a moral imperative to stymie and even reverse the advances of behavioral science in order to protect and expand the scope of human agency. Thankfully, Turkheimer has never followed this strand of his thinking through to its logical conclusion and embarked on an explicitly antiscientific campaign. He only enlists epistemic libertarianism to buttress his de facto metaphysical libertarianism, which it achieves by sustaining an ambiguity over whether unexplained human behavioral variation has antecedent causes or is self-caused.

As noted earlier, however, this de facto metaphysical libertarianism is sufficient in itself to motivate profound moral resistance to advances in the behavioral sciences, without tipping into the outright antiscientific stance that epistemic libertarianism would imply if that position were embraced wholeheartedly. We opened Part I of this series with a quote from Daniel Dennett that nicely captures the anxieties metaphysical libertarianism can produce:

There is no more potent source of anxiety about free will than the image of the physical sciences engulfing our every deed, good and bad, in the acid broth of causal explanation, nibbling away at the soul until there is nothing left to praise or blame, to honor, respect, or love. (Dennett, Reference Dennett2004, p. 289)

When ‘causal explanation’ is seen to ‘nibble away at the soul’ and narrow the scope of human agency, we can expect both genetic and environmental explanations for human behavioral differences to be met with considerable prejudice. Pessimism about scientific progress in the behavioral sciences becomes metaphysical optimism (‘the gloomy prospect isn’t [gloomy]’, Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2000, p. 164) and each failure of science to advance becomes something to be celebrated as a triumph for human agency and the human spirit (‘the gloomy prospect … is freedom’, Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2019a, p. 125).

7. Selective Determinism as a Source of Scientific Bias

In the last section we discussed how a libertarian conception of free will, which holds that antecedent causes of behavior infringe on our agency, can lead its proponents to experience dismay when behavioral science advances and rejoice when it faces significant setbacks. In this section we explore how Turkheimer’s theory of free-will-by-subtraction has led him to make unduly pessimistic predictions about what behavioral geneticists will discover in future and to downplay the importance of advances that have already been made. This suggests that selectively determinist, free-will-by-subtraction theories can unduly prejudice the reception of behavioral genetic research and the evaluation of its scientific prospects.

7.1 Moving Goalposts on Genetic Associations and Genetic Prediction

Two of Turkheimer’s signature scientific predictions were that the intractably complex causes of human behavior would mean the associations between genetic variants and particular behaviors ‘would fail to replicate and accumulate’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2000, p. 163) and that the likelihood of finding behavioral domains where they do would be ‘inversely related to the complexity of the behavior under study’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2000, p. 164). Both predictions have since been disproven by subsequent genomewide association studies (GWAS).

Turkheimer has himself subsequently acknowledged that genetic associations with behavior replicate, arguing in a public exchange with another GWAS critic, ‘Isn’t the success of a polygenic score in a new sample an indication that the effect sizes of SNPs are “replicating” in a general way? Otherwise, the scores wouldn’t predict anything’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2019b). In a follow-up exchange with Turkheimer a few months later, the statistical geneticist Michel Nivard listed several notable examples of statistically significant genetic associations (‘hits’) replicating out of sample, writing: ‘Howard [et] al replicate 97 out of 102 depression hits out of sample, Lee et al replicate a substantial number of 160 EA2 hits in the new data with no overlap. Okbay does the same for the 3 EA1 hits. Saying we don’t replicate out of sample is misleading’ (Nivard, Reference Nivard2019).Footnote 47

As of the latest, GWAS of educational attainment (EA4), Okbay et al. (Reference Okbay, Wu, Wang, Jayashankar, Bennett, Nehzati, Sidorenko, Kweon, Goldman, Gjorgjieva, Jiang, Hicks, Tian, Hinds, Ahlskog, Magnusson, Oskarsson, Hayward, Campbell and Young2022) were able to predict 13−17% of the variance in EA in independent samples. This shows that, against Turkheimer’s prediction, genetic associations identified in the GWAS do, in fact, accumulate into powerful genetic predictors of individual differences. Moreover, contrary to Turkheimer’s prediction that success in finding genetic associations that replicate and accumulate would be ‘inversely related to the complexity of the behavior under study’, some of the greatest successes so far have been for educational attainment, a highly complex and socially contingent behavioral trait. This is primarily because it has been easier to obtain data on educational qualifications for large numbers of genotyped subjects. The EA4 GWAS involved more than 3 million genotyped individuals.

The latest EA4 polygenic scores predict educational attainment about as accurately as parental education levels, one of the best phenotypic predictors we have for this outcome (see e.g., Figure 4b of Lee et al., Reference Lee, Wedow, Okbay, Kong, Maghzian, Zacher, Nguyen-Viet, Bowers, Sidorenko, Linnér, Fontana, Kundu, Lee, Li, Li, Royer, Timshel, Walters, Willoughby and Cesarini2018). That we can now guess someone’s educational attainment more accurately from their DNA than from their parents’ income strikes many laypeople as something from the realms of science fiction, and as recently as 2014 this prospect appeared to strike Turkheimer the same way. Reacting to an early GWAS of children’s intelligence (Benyamin et al., Reference Benyamin, St Pourcain, Davis, Davies, Hansell, Brion, Kirkpatrick, Cents, Franić, Miller, Haworth, Meaburn, Price, Evans, Timpson, Kemp, Ring, McArdle, Medland and Visscher2014), Turkheimer wrote:

When the researchers create [polygenic scores for intelligence], they can account for a weighted mean of 1.7% of the variance. … That, to me, is the bottom line: if we were [to] start a program tomorrow to take SNPs from newborns and predict their intelligence, we would do so at a level much worse than predicting from the parent’s income. … And this part of the story is not one that we expect to improve as samples get bigger. (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2013 [emphasis added])

Note that, in the blogpost cited above, the ‘bottom line’ was about genetic prediction of behavior. Indeed, Turkheimer concluded that blogpost by writing ‘The real question is whether, short of growing everyone an identical twin, … we can build useful … prediction models’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2013 [emphasis added]).Footnote 48 Nevertheless, eight years later, Turkheimer unironically greeted the results of EA4 with the dismal question: ‘Has GWAS of complex human behavior turned out to be a disappointment?’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2022a). Moreover, despite the above remarks about genetic prediction being a matter of public record, Turkheimer has insisted that his predictions ‘have been consistently right’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2022d) and that ‘it is GWAS-world that has moved the goalpost, not the critics’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2022c).

7.2 The Conspicuous Alignment of Turkheimer’s Views About Genetic Influence on Behavior

What we seek to highlight here is that the prior assumptions Turkheimer brings to his interpretation of many scientific results in behavioral genetics (and his pessimistic predictions about future scientific developments) are not based simply on empirical priors informed by the weight of previous evidence, but on philosophical priors based on the existential threat to free will that substantial genetic causation of human behavior is feared to imply. Without recognizing this it would be difficult to explain the improbable alignment of Turkheimer’s positions across a broad range of scientific issues.

If substantial genetic causation of individual differences in behavior is felt to represent an intolerable infringement on human agency, a particular constellation of scientific beliefs can predictably be expected to follow:

Turkheimer has publicly subscribed to all of the positions just described.

We stress that some of these positions are legitimate scientific hypotheses that may ultimately be borne out. What is conspicuous is how they are all aligned in a common direction that uniformly resists the prospect of substantial genetic causation of individual differences in human behavior. Such a uniformly one-sided skepticism is not scientifically impartial or disinterested. After all, there is no scientific reason why the default hypothesis should be that the genetic contribution to differences in human behavior should be statistically minute, and there are many empirical findings that suggest exactly the opposite.

While it is true that extraordinary claims demand extraordinary evidence, scientific claims should only be considered extraordinary to the extent that they contradict previous empirical findings, not on the basis that we dislike their potential moral or political implications. Otherwise, scientific skepticism risks becoming an instrument of wish-fulfilment. A classic dictum in philosophy called Hume’s guillotine is that one cannot derive an ‘ought’ from an ‘is’, that is, that one cannot derive a moral injunction from a set of facts. In behavioral genetics, we are at risk of making a more egregious philosophical error: the moralistic fallacy of deriving an ‘is’ from an ‘ought’ — of deciding that some things cannot be true because they must not be true.Footnote 49

Persistent skepticism about genetic influences on human behavior has had the welcome side-effect of driving rigor and technical innovation in behavioral genetics (Lee & McGue, Reference Lee and McGue2016), but selective and insatiable demands for scientific rigor from motivated skeptics risks placing behavior genetic research on a scientific treadmill that indefinitely postpones a public reckoning with potentially inconvenient truths (Alexander, Reference Alexander2014). Some of Turkheimer’s pessimistic predictions for behavioral genetics may well turn out to be correct but, of course, a blanket scientific pessimism will always turn out to be justified in some instances. The danger is that Turkheimer’s (explicitly) motivated scientific pessimism risks becoming a self-fulfilling prophecy if it is allowed to derail productive lines of scientific enquiry.

Competing interests

The author declares no competing interests.

Data availability

All data discussed in this piece is from publicly available studies.

Financial support

This work was generously funded by the Social, Genetic and Developmental Psychiatry Centre at King’s College London.

Ethical statement

The research presented in this article is a theoretical discussion of existing behavioral genetic studies, with no new data collection or human subjects involved. The author has ensured proper attribution of all cited studies and complied with ethical guidelines for scholarly research. Ethical approval was not necessary for this work, as it does not involve primary research.

Footnotes

21 This parallels Harden’s acknowledgment that the nonshared environment ‘might be thought of as an upper bound of the extent to which people have agency’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021b, p. 288) after taking the contribution of stochastic developmental variation into account. However, we will shortly challenge the idea that some residual fraction of the nonshared environment captures human agency.

22 In other contexts, Turkheimer specifically draws his readers’ attention to the difference between individual predictors of outcomes and variance components, especially when discussing the difference between genetic prediction and heritability. For example, in ‘Genetic Prediction’, Turkheimer draws attention to the fact that a Down’s syndrome diagnosis is associated with 30-point drop in IQ, while noting that this genetic condition accounts for a negligible proportion of the population variance in this highly heritable trait (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2015).

23 Note incidentally, how Harden’s example shifts the reference population away from the implicit population implied by the debate topic ‘Parenting Is Overrated’. Instead of addressing the question of how much differences in parenting practices account for the differences in their children’s behavior within the society that the American studio audience belonged to (a context in which twin studies show that the environmental differences between families have very limited effects on most behavioral outcomes), Harden shifted the reference population to the global context where different rearing environments account for far more of the behavioral differences we observe. Note that this shift in the reference population for evaluating the importance of shared environmental influences parallels the shift in the reference population which often occurs when discussing the heritability of species-universal traits (see section 2.2 in Part I).

24 Plomin and Daniels (Reference Plomin and Daniels1987) float this possibility against the alternative prospect that the causes of nonshared environmental variation will be systematic and measurable.

25 Charles Coulson coined the phrase ‘God of the gaps’ in his 1955 book Science and Christian Belief (Coulson, Reference Coulson1955). The phrase refers to a tendency to enlist supernatural causes to explain phenomena which cannot currently be explained by contemporary science and highlights how these supernatural stopgap explanations are imperiled as science ineluctably advances. Coulson wrote, ‘There is no ‘God of the gaps’ to take over at those strategic places where science fails; and the reason is that gaps of this sort have the unpreventable habit of shrinking’.

26 The Greeks and Romans had a separate concept to cover this more expansive concept of luck governing every aspect of our lives, namely Ananke (Fate) or Necessitas (Necessity), but these ancient concepts are more closely related to the contemporary concept of determinism rather than the concept of good or bad luck, which generally refers to an unpredictable departure from our reasonable expectations of what will take place.

27 In sections 8 and 9 in Part III, we will argue that luck does not, in fact, swallow everything because control and personal responsibility are compatible with human behavior having antecedent causes that are outside of our control. Specifically, in section 8.4 we enlist passages from Dennett (Reference Dennett1984) to argue that the kind of luck which renders us non-responsible is not the exhaustive, ‘cosmic’ definition of luck that Harden and Caruso use here.

28 There are multiple formulations of compatibilism. This particular formulation is a variant on a formulation by G. E. Moore (Reference Moore1912) and Donald Davidson (Reference Davidson1980) developed by Michael S. Moore (Reference Moore2016).

29 That is, because they hold that free will is incompatible with a universe which is either deterministic or indeterministic.

30 Some other, even finer terminological distinctions are sometimes drawn between compatibilists and ‘semi-compatibilists’, who hold that personal responsibility is compatible with antecedent causes of behavior but remain agnostic on the question of whether we have metaphysical free will or consider the question to be a pseudo-problem. Hayek, for instance, adopts a semi-compatibilist position in the unabridged version of the quote we used to open Part I of this series, writing ‘the assertion that the will is free has as little meaning as it’s denial’ (Hayek, Reference Hayek2011, p. 135). In many cases, the differences between compatibilists and semi-compatibilists — and even between compatibilists and free will skeptics — are ultimately semantic rather than substantive and mainly concern whether certain terms should be avoided because they contain too much metaphysical baggage or whether they should be retained because they serve an indispensable function in everyday speech. Semi-compatibilists and free will skeptics still recognize the distinction between signing a contract ‘of one’s own free will’ rather than under duress, even though they dislike the terminology. Likewise, most free will skeptics recognize the need to incentivize prosocial behavior and deter antisocial behavior, even if they reject the concepts of ‘reward’ and ‘punishment’ and reject the associated concepts of ‘responsibility’, ‘desert’, ‘praiseworthiness’ and ‘blameworthiness’. Our defense of compatibilism in section 8 (see Part III) will mainly seek to show that these contested terms can be interpreted in a way that is consistent with the view that all human behavior has antecedent causes, and that we risk falling into various philosophical traps when we try to dispense with them.

31 Indeed, in his book Freedom Evolves, Dennett lampoons the logic underlying Turkheimer and Harden‘s free-will-by-subtraction position, writing ‘When Nature and Nurture have done their work, will there be anything left over to be me?’ adding, ‘Does it matter what the trade-off is if, one way or another, our genes and our environment (including chance) divide up the spoils and “fix” our characters?’ (Dennett, Reference Dennett2004, p. 159). We defend a compatibilist position in sections 8 and 9 (see Part III) drawing heavily on Dennett’s writings and discuss the differences between Dennett‘s compatibilism and Turkheimer and Harden‘s libertarian incompatibilism in further detail in section 9.2.

32 In sections 8 and 9 (see Part III), we will argue the compatibilist position that personal responsibility is consistent with determinism and, in fact, requires a deterministic universe that is governed by predictable laws of cause and effect.

33 This is why neither compatibilists nor free will skeptics see quantum indeterminism as being relevant to the free will debate, as discussed at the beginning of this section.

34 Compatibilism holds that we do not need to be the ultimate cause of our actions as we will explore in section 8 in Part III.

35 In an exchange on social media in which the nonshared environmental theory of free will was referred to as ‘Harden’s free will argument’, Harden responded, ‘for the record, that’s not my argument; it’s [Turkheimer’s] argument’ (Harden, Reference Harden2022). However, from the context, it was unclear whether Harden was disavowing the idea or simply clarifying that she couldn’t take credit for coming up with it. Our analysis below suggests she meant the latter.

36 This throwaway sentence, and the footnote which accompanies it, contains one of the most important insights in Harden’s book. Under both compatibilist and hard incompatibilist stances on the free will question, evidence of substantial genetic causation of human behavior is not particularly threatening because both positions accept that all human behavior is explained by antecedent causes. Either human agency can be fully reconciled with comprehensive causation (compatibilism), or human agency cannot exist (hard incompatibilism).

Once it is accepted that all human behavior has antecedent, secular causes, the prospect that some of those causes are genetic is neither here nor there. There are hardly any nonreligious academic philosophers who do not subscribe to one of these two perspectives on free will (Bourget & Chalmers, Reference Bourget and Chalmers2020), suggesting that ‘genetic determinism’ is a nonproblem in secular academic philosophy.

37 This discussion mainly takes place in Chapter 10 of her book, which is specifically entitled ‘Personal Responsibility’.

38 To give a few examples: ‘Considering genetics as an absolution for social responsibility is a false pretext that must be dismantled’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021b, p. 24); ‘the existence of genetic influence … does not … operate as a ‘get out of jail free’ card for our social responsibilities’ (p. 93); ‘no matter how people differ genetically … we are still not absolved of the responsibility to arrange society to the benefit of all people’ (p. 93); ‘… the existence of genetic differences does not obviate our social responsibility’ (p. 94). Emphasis added in each quote.

39 These accusations are sometimes profoundly unjust, personally blaming these scientists for mass atrocities they would have almost certainly condemned, as when she describes ‘the enormity of the violence and harm [that Karl Pearson] brought to innocent people’ (p. 29). Moreover, these accusations frequently spill over into outright conspiracy theories, e.g., when Harden writes that, ‘Since Francis Galton, eugenic thinkers have steadily and successfully engaged in a misinformation campaign’ or writes that ‘Goddard worked deliberately to establish … an abhorrent idea—that intelligence test scores are a measure of someone’s worth’ (p. 260).

40 Harden briefly acknowledges the metaphysical libertarianism implied by Turkheimer’s nonshared environmental theory of free will when she notes that, ‘Whether one can glean from twin studies any information about a person’s metaphysical freedom to do otherwise is, to put it mildly, controversial’ (Harden, Reference Harden2021a, p. 126).

41 It is unclear exactly how ‘hypercomplex contingencies’ can produce a freely led life if these contingencies are themselves antecedent causes that are beyond our control (again, this is the problem with inferring freedom from quantum indeterminism or deterministic chaos discussed in the last section).

42 In philosophical terminology, ‘metaphysics’ concerns the fundamental nature of reality while ‘epistemology’ concerns the nature and limits of our knowledge. Metaphysical libertarianism holds that human beings have contra-causal freedom which make it impossible to fully predict human behavior. Epistemic libertarianism, by contrast, holds that we somehow gain freedom simply by not knowing the causes of human behavior.

43 The philosophical importance of this this concession is partly obscured by Turkheimer and Waldron (Reference Turkheimer and Waldron2000) attributing these environmental differences to the ‘effective’ rather than the ‘objective’ environment. They write: ‘Objective environments refer to environmental events as they might be observed by a researcher, as opposed to how they affect family members’ (p. 79), while ‘Effective environments are defined by the outcomes they produce’ (p. 79). Unfortunately, referring to researcher-measured features of the nonshared environment as ‘objective’ here, risks obscuring the fact that, from a secular materialist perspective, ‘effective’ differences between monozygotic twins must also ultimately be based on objective differences between them irrespective of whether those differences are detected (or detectable) by scientific observers. Those differences might consist of stochastic developmental differences, or they might consist of the idiosyncratic experiences that inevitably follow from twins occupying separate bodies and attending to different features of their environment. The fact that those differences might be intractable to scientific discovery because they are ‘hypercomplex’ (Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer2011, p. 827) or infinitesimally subtle does not alter the fact that they are extrinsic causes of twin differences over which the twins themselves have no control. For a secular materialist, then, the behavioral differences between twins cannot serve as a measure of human agency, any more than the differences between genetically different siblings, or unrelated individuals can.

44 If we followed Turkheimer’s logic in this thread to its conclusion, it would imply that adoptees with no way to gain knowledge about the attributes of their biological parents or siblings are thereby less genetically determined and have more agency than the rest of us. That would implausibly suggest that the triplets in Three Identical Strangers transitioned at age 19 from being the least genetically determined that anyone can be to the most genetically determined that anyone can be. In addition, Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2022f) is mistaken to say that, for nontwins, the effects of genetic differences on our behavior are ‘beyond our knowledge in principle’ (emphasis added). This confuses knowledge in practice with knowledge in principle — the unknown with the unknowable.

If Turkheimer’s predictions about the intractability of the genetic gloomy prospect prove wrong and a substantial fraction of the twin heritability for various behavioral traits comes to be explained by the direct effect of polygenic scores, then the rest of us will be able to gain access to at least some of the knowledge that is currently only available to identical twins. In this scenario, it clearly will not affect how determined or free our lives are whether we look up our polygenic scores or not, and neither does human agency hinge on whether such knowledge becomes accessible to science in general. Note that the question of how determined our actions are is quite distinct from the question of whether knowledge of how people with similar attributes to us have behaved risks becoming a self-fulfilling prophecy. However, even here, research on misclassified twins suggests that it is not merely the expectation of monozygotic twin similarity which drives their increased resemblance because, for most traits, misclassified MZ twins are not less similar than their true zygosity predicts, nor are misclassified DZ twins more similar than those who were correctly classified (Conley et al., Reference Conley, Rauscher, Dawes, Magnusson and Siegal2013; Gunderson et al., Reference Gunderson, Tsai, Selby, Caan, Mayer-Davis and Risch2006).

45 A more detailed critique of epistemic libertarianism is provided in section 9.5 in Part III where we discuss what Stephen Morse calls ‘the fundamental psycho-legal error’.

46 While we had independently developed the concept of ‘epistemological libertarianism’ to describe aspects of Turkheimer’s theory of free will, it was gratifying to discover late in the drafting of this series that a prominent philosopher had already catalogued ‘epistemic libertarianism’ as a common error in people’s thinking about free will (see M. S. Moore Reference Moore2016). We have subsequently defaulted to Moore’s more grammatically correct (‘epistemic’) phraseology throughout.

47 The papers referenced here are Howard et al.’s (Reference Howard, Adams, Clarke, Hafferty, Gibson, Shirali, Coleman, Hagenaars, Ward, Wigmore, Alloza, Shen, Barbu, Xu, Whalley, Marioni, Porteous, Davies, Deary and McIntosh2019) GWAS of depression, Lee et al.’s (Reference Lee, Wedow, Okbay, Kong, Maghzian, Zacher, Nguyen-Viet, Bowers, Sidorenko, Linnér, Fontana, Kundu, Lee, Li, Li, Royer, Timshel, Walters, Willoughby and Cesarini2018) GWAS of educational attainment (‘EA3’), Okbay et al.’s (Reference Okbay, Beauchamp, Fontana, Lee, Pers, Rietveld, Turley, Chen, Emilsson, Meddens, Oskarsson, Pickrell, Thom, Timshel, de Vlaming, Abdellaoui, Ahluwalia, Bacelis, Baumbach and Benjamin2016) previous GWAS of educational attainment (‘EA2’), and Rietveld et al.’s (Reference Rietveld, Medland, Derringer, Yang, Esko, Martin, Westra, Shakhbazov, Abdellaoui, Agrawal, Albrecht, Alizadeh, Amin, Barnard, Baumeister, Benke, Bielak, Boatman, Boyle and Koellinger2013) still earlier GWAS of educational attainment (‘EA1’). Focusing on educational attainment, in Supplementary Note 1.10 of Lee et al. (Reference Lee, Wedow, Okbay, Kong, Maghzian, Zacher, Nguyen-Viet, Bowers, Sidorenko, Linnér, Fontana, Kundu, Lee, Li, Li, Royer, Timshel, Walters, Willoughby and Cesarini2018), the authors write: ‘Here we conduct a replication analysis of the 162 lead SNPs identified at genome-wide significance in Okbay et al.’s pooled (discovery and replication) meta-analysis (N = 405,073). … Of the 162 SNPs, 158 of them pass quality-control filters in our updated meta-analysis, so we focus on those. … Of the 158 SNPs, we find that 154 have matching signs in the new data (for the remaining four SNPs, the estimated effect is never statistically significant at p < 0.10). Of the 154 SNPs with matching signs, 143 are significant at p < .01, 119 are significant at p < 10–5, and 97 are significant at p < 5×10–8’ (p. 14). A further statistical analysis described in the same section showed that this high, but imperfect, level of replication was closely in line with theoretical expectations.

48 The reference to ‘growing an identical twin’ also confirms that this comment is about raw genetic prediction using population-based polygenic scores, not about quantifying direct, genetically causal effects free from environmental confounding. One of Turkheimer’s recurring arguments is that the resemblance of identical twins reared apart (or the resemblance of identical twins reared together over and above the resemblance of fraternal twins reared together) does not tell us anything about the degree to which variation in a trait is genetically caused (see e.g., Turkheimer, Reference Turkheimer1998).

49 Dire warnings that it would be morally and/or existentially catastrophic if human behavioral differences turned out to be substantially caused by genetic differences are littered across Turkheimer’s writings. To provide just a few examples, in Turkheimer and Greer (Reference Turkheimer and Greer2024) he cautions that the research on the genetics of substance abuse performed by the Spit for Science group ‘brings with it dangers that cannot be ameliorated by their good intentions’ (p. 413). He asserts that the idea that polygenic scores might be used to assess whether someone has a genetic predisposition to substance abuse ‘leads to … treacherous philosophical and bioethical waters’ (p. 413) and warns that ‘the goal of improving human behavior via genetics has reliably led to moral disaster’ (p. 415). (For a critical response to this paper see Lee and Morris, Reference Lee and Morris2024). As we have already noted, in Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer2000) he writes that ‘no one would want to live in a world’ where the gloomy prospect was not true and measured genetic and environmental causes explained a large part of the variation in human behavior (p. 164). Moreover, in Turkheimer (Reference Turkheimer1998), he makes clear that he places himself in the camp ‘who consider biogenetic theories exaggerated, dehumanizing, and dangerous’ (p. 782) when they interpret heritability as an estimate of the degree to which genetic differences cause phenotypic variation in human behavior.

References

Alexander, S. (2014, August 14). Beware isolated demands for rigor. Slate Star Codex. https://slatestarcodex.com/2014/08/14/beware-isolated-demands-for-rigor https://archive.is/xTbTOGoogle Scholar
Bean, C. (2010). I was born this way: A gay preacher’s journey through gospel music, disco stardom, and a ministry in Christ. Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Benyamin, B., St Pourcain, B., Davis, O. S., Davies, G., Hansell, N. K., Brion, M.-J., Kirkpatrick, R. M., Cents, R. a. M., Franić, S., Miller, M. B., Haworth, C. M. A., Meaburn, E., Price, T. S., Evans, D. M., Timpson, N., Kemp, J., Ring, S., McArdle, W., Medland, S. E., … Visscher, P. M. (2014). Childhood intelligence is heritable, highly polygenic and associated with FNBP1L. Molecular Psychiatry, 19, Article 2. https://doi.org/10.1038/mp.2012.184 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourget, D., & Chalmers, D. J. (2020). Philosophers on philosophy: The 2020 Philpapers survey. Philosophers’ Imprint. Google Scholar
Chisholm, R. M. (1964). Human Freedom and the Self: The Lindley Lecture. University of Kansas. Google Scholar
Conley, D., Rauscher, E., Dawes, C., Magnusson, P. K. E., & Siegal, M. L. (2013). Heritability and the equal environments assumption: Evidence from multiple samples of misclassified twins. Behavior Genetics, 43, 415426. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10519-013-9602-1 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coulson, C. A. (1955). Science and Christian belief. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1984). Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (2004). Freedom evolves. Penguin Publishing Group.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C., & Caruso, G. D. (2021). Just deserts: Debating free will. John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Gaga, Lady. (2011). Born this way sheet music. Hal Leonard.Google Scholar
Gunderson, E. P., Tsai, A.-L., Selby, J. V., Caan, B., Mayer-Davis, E. J., & Risch, N. (2006). Twins of mistaken zygosity (TOMZ): Evidence for genetic contributions to dietary patterns and physiologic traits. Twin Research and Human Genetics, 9, 540549. https://doi.org/10.1375/twin.9.4.540 Google ScholarPubMed
Harden, K. P. (2021a). ‘Reports of my death were greatly exaggerated’: Behavior genetics in the postgenomic era. Annual Review of Psychology, 72, 3760. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-052220-103822 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harden, K. P. (2021b). The genetic lottery: Why DNA matters for social equality. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Harden, K. P. (2022, April 4). Kathryn Paige Harden on Twitter: ‘for the record, that’s not my argument; it’s @ent3c’s argument.’ [Online post]. https://web.archive.org/web/20220404155540/https://twitter.com/kph3k/status/1511009414525894657 Google Scholar
Harris, S. (2012). Free will. Simon and Schuster.Google ScholarPubMed
Hayek, F. A. (2011). The constitution of liberty: The definitive edition. University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226320519.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobbes, T. (1656). The questions concerning liberty, necessity, and chance: Clearly stated and debated between Dr. Bramhall Bishop of Derry, and Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury. Andrew Crook.Google Scholar
Howard, D. M., Adams, M. J., Clarke, T.-K., Hafferty, J. D., Gibson, J., Shirali, M., Coleman, J. R. I., Hagenaars, S. P., Ward, J., Wigmore, E. M., Alloza, C., Shen, X., Barbu, M. C., Xu, E. Y., Whalley, H. C., Marioni, R. E., Porteous, D. J., Davies, G., Deary, I. J., … McIntosh, A. M. (2019). Genome-wide meta-analysis of depression identifies 102 independent variants and highlights the importance of the prefrontal brain regions. Nature Neuroscience, 22, Article 3. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41593-018-0326-7 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howitt, P. (Director). (1998, May 1). Sliding Doors . Intermedia Films, Mirage Enterprises, Miramax.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1739). A treatise of human nature: Being an attempt to introduce the experimental method of reasoning into moral subjects. John Noon.Google Scholar
Inwagen, P. V. (1983). An essay on free will. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kane, R. (1998). The significance of free will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
KuremaSan. (2022, November 27). KuremaSan on Twitter: ‘@ent3c Comprehension isn’t a prerequisite for determinism.’ [Online post]. https://archive.ph/fFp4R Google Scholar
Lee, J. J., & McGue, M. (2016). Why behavioral genetics matters: Comment on Plomin et al. (2016). Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11, 2930. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691615611932 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, J. J., & Morris, D. (2024). The peculiarly favored condition of genetics. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 31(4), 441445.10.1353/ppp.2024.a948900CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, J. J., Wedow, R., Okbay, A., Kong, E., Maghzian, O., Zacher, M., Nguyen-Viet, T. A., Bowers, P., Sidorenko, J., Linnér, R. K., Fontana, M. A., Kundu, T., Lee, C., Li, H., Li, R., Royer, R., Timshel, P. N., Walters, R. K., Willoughby, E. A., … Cesarini, D. (2018). Gene discovery and polygenic prediction from a genome-wide association study of educational attainment in 1.1 million individuals. Nature Genetics, 50, 1112. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41588-018-0147-3 Google ScholarPubMed
Levy, N. (2011). Hard luck: How luck undermines free will and moral responsibility. OUP Oxford.Google Scholar
Mitchell, K. (2020a, July 31). Escaping flatland — When determinism falls, it takes reductionism with it. Wiring the Brain. http://www.wiringthebrain.com/2020/07/escaping-flatland-when-determinism.html https://archive.is/BBkyB Google Scholar
Mitchell, K. (2020b, December 12). Does freedom bubble up from the quantum realm? Wiring The Brain. http://www.wiringthebrain.com/2020/12/does-freedom-bubble-up-from-quantum.html https://archive.is/sSmxg Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1912). Ethics. Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Moore, M. S. (2016). Stephen Morse on the fundamental psycho-legal error. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 10, 4589. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9299-0 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nivard, M. G. (2019, May 26). Michel Nivard on Twitter: ‘Saying we don’t replicate out of sample is misleading’. [Online post]. https://twitter.com/michelnivard/status/1132685460587929601 Google Scholar
O’Connor, T. (2000). Persons and causes: The metaphysics of free will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Okbay, A., Beauchamp, J. P., Fontana, M. A., Lee, J. J., Pers, T. H., Rietveld, C. A., Turley, P., Chen, G.-B., Emilsson, V., Meddens, S. F. W., Oskarsson, S., Pickrell, J. K., Thom, K., Timshel, P., de Vlaming, R., Abdellaoui, A., Ahluwalia, T. S., Bacelis, J., Baumbach, C., … Benjamin, D. J. (2016). Genome-wide association study identifies 74 loci associated with educational attainment. Nature, 533, 539542. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature17671 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Okbay, A., Wu, Y., Wang, N., Jayashankar, H., Bennett, M., Nehzati, S. M., Sidorenko, J., Kweon, H., Goldman, G., Gjorgjieva, T., Jiang, Y., Hicks, B., Tian, C., Hinds, D. A., Ahlskog, R., Magnusson, P. K. E., Oskarsson, S., Hayward, C., Campbell, A., … Young, A. I. (2022). Polygenic prediction of educational attainment within and between families from genome-wide association analyses in 3 million individuals. Nature Genetics, 54(4), Article 4. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41588-022-01016-z Google Scholar
Open to Debate. (2019, October 29). LIVE DEBATE – Parenting Is Overrated [Video recording]. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=0hqjkBAd20M Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (1995). Determinism al dente. Noûs, 29, 2145. https://doi.org/10.2307/2215725 Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511498824CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plomin, R. (2018). Blueprint: How DNA makes us who we are. Penguin.Google Scholar
Plomin, R., & Daniels, D. (1987). Why are children in the same family so different from one another? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 116. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00055941 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rietveld, C. A., Medland, S. E., Derringer, J., Yang, J., Esko, T., Martin, N. W., Westra, H.-J., Shakhbazov, K., Abdellaoui, A., Agrawal, A., Albrecht, E., Alizadeh, B. Z., Amin, N., Barnard, J., Baumeister, S. E., Benke, K. S., Bielak, L. F., Boatman, J. A., Boyle, P. A., … Koellinger, P. D. (2013). GWAS of 126,559 individuals identifies genetic variants associated with educational attainment. Science, 340, 14671471. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1235488 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sapolsky, R. M. (2023). Determined: Life without free will. Random House.Google Scholar
Sarkissian, H., Chatterjee, A., De Brigard, F., Knobe, J., Nichols, S., & Sirker, S. (2010). Is belief in free will a cultural universal? Mind & Language, 25, 346358. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01393.x Google Scholar
Spielberg, S. (Director). (1993). Jurassic Park. Universal Pictures, Amblin Entertainment.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (2016). Free will. In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1st ed.). Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780415249126-V014-1 Google Scholar
Taylor, R. (1966). Action and purpose. Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (1998). Heritability and biological explanation. Psychological Review, 105, 782791. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.105.4.782-791 Google ScholarPubMed
Turkheimer, E. (2000). Three laws of behavior genetics and what they mean. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 9, 160164. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8721.00084 Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2011). Genetics and human agency: Comment on Dar-Nimrod and Heine (2011). Psychological Bulletin, 137, 825828. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0024306 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Turkheimer, E. (2013, February 13). GWAS of educational attainment. Eric Turkheimer. https://archive.ph/hPlpP Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2015). Genetic prediction. Hastings Center Report, 45, S32S38. https://doi.org/10.1002/hast.496 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Turkheimer, E. (2018, August 28). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘Trisomy 21 is a major CAUSE of IQ differences, but accounts for little… variance…’ [Online post]. https://archive.is/MaQ3Q Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2019a). Genetics and human agency: The philosophy of behavior genetics introduction to the special issue. Behavior Genetics, 49, 123127. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10519-019-09952-z CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Turkheimer, E. (2019b, February 1). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘Isn’t the success of a [PGS] in a new sample an indication that the effect sizes …are ‘replicating’…’ [Online post]. https://twitter.com/ent3c/status/1091426427696754690 Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2021a, October 16). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘The RDR h2 of EA…is. 17’ [Online post]. https://archive.ph/3clwQ Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2021b, October 18). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘the …genomic revolution…has had the net effect of reducing estimates of the heritability of behavioral differences’ [Online post]. https://archive.ph/CAu1V Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2021c, November 2). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘3.4% isn’t anything to write home about…’ [Online post]. https://web.archive.org/web/20211102234317/https:/twitter.com/ent3c/status/1455681907539255297 Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2021d, November 2). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘In which the direct effect of EA PGS in UK Biobank is estimated at 1.4%… [Online post]. https://web.archive.org/web/20211102155814/https:/twitter.com/ent3c/status/1455558690803683328 Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2022a, March 31). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘Has GWAS of complex human behavior turned out to be a disappointment?’ [Online post]. https://web.archive.org/web/20220331185921/https://twitter.com/ent3c/status/1509576563515445254 Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2022b, April 9). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘One reason C is so small…Is the MZ correlations are…inflated…by epistasis’ [Online post]. https://web.archive.org/web/20220409184607/https://twitter.com/ent3c/status/1512864178792546326/ Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2022c, May 17). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘…It is GWAS-world that has moved the goalpost, not the critics’ [Online post]. https://web.archive.org/web/20220517133421/https:/twitter.com/ent3c/status/1526556322711359493 Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2022d, June 1). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘We now know that the actionable h2, based on 3 million people, is maybe .05… [Online post]. https://archive.ph/coTSc Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2022e, June 2). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘My vote goes to epistasis…’ [Online post]. https://web.archive.org/web/20220602182650/https:/twitter.com/ent3c/status/1532360420119523331 Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2022f, November 27). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘we are born with genetic constraints on our personality, but unless we have an identical twin we have no way of knowing what those constraints are!’ [Online post]. https://archive.ph/hMvzl Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E. (2023, April 5). Eric Turkheimer on Twitter: ‘once confounds are properly accounted for, genetics makes no difference… [Online post]. https://archive.ph/sjMDR Google Scholar
Turkheimer, E., & Greer, S. R. (2024). Spit for science and the limits of applied psychiatric genetics. Philosophy Psychiatry and Psychology, 31, 397424 https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.0.a923702 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turkheimer, E., Haley, A., Waldron, M., D’Onofrio, B., & Gottesman, I. I. (2003). Socioeconomic status modifies heritability of IQ in young children. Psychological Science, 14, 623628. https://doi.org/10.1046/j.0956-7976.2003.psci_1475.x CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Turkheimer, E., & Waldron, M. (2000). Nonshared environment: A theoretical, methodological, and quantitative review. Psychological Bulletin, 126, 78108. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.126.1.78 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wardle, T. (Director). (2018). Three Identical Strangers. RAW.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 3. A trivial environmental difference sets Helen’s life on two separate paths in the film Sliding Doors (Howitt, 1998).

Figure 1

Figure 4. Turkheimer suggests the nonshared environmental variation is an index of agent self-causation without explaining how non-miraculous self-causation can possibly occur. Cartoon by Sidney Harris (image reproduced with permission of ScienceCartoonsPlus.com©).

Figure 2

Figure 5. The free will trilemma. The three main positions adopted in the academic free will debate represent three possible solutions to a trilemma in which only two of the three circled propositions can be logically subscribed to simultaneously: Libertarianism (A+B), Compatibilism (A+C), or Free will skepticism (B+C). Turkheimer champions a libertarian theory of free will which emphasizes the existence of personal responsibility (A), and the incompatibility of antecedent genetic and environmental causes of behavioral variation with personal responsibility (B); however, Turkheimer’s secular materialism compels him to simultaneously support the proposition that all human behavior has antecedent causes (C). But proposition C cannot be logically supported without rejecting proposition A or B. Turkheimer appeals to the scientific intractability of complex causes of behavior as a refuge for personal responsibility, but it is left unclear why personal responsibility would only be infringed by the causes known to science. Note that Turkheimer sometimes claims to be a compatibilist on the basis that he nominally supports propositions A and C, but this is untenable without rejecting proposition B.