Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-smtgx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-10-04T16:40:30.318Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 September 2025

Johan E. Gustafsson*
Affiliation:
UT Austin, Austin, TX, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails one of the Repugnant Conclusion and the Sadistic Conclusion, depending on the critical level. Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism is a version of Critical-Level Utilitarianism where it is indeterminate which well-being level is the critical level. Undistinguished Critical-Range Utilitarianism is a variant of Critical-Level Utilitarianism where additions of lives in a range of well-being between the good and the bad lives make the resulting outcome incomparable to the original outcome. These views avoid the Repugnant Conclusion, they avoid the Sadistic Conclusion, and they agree on all outcome comparisons not involving indeterminacy or incomparability. So it may seem unclear whether we have any reason to favour one of these theories over the other. But I argue that Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism still entails the disjunction of the Repugnant Conclusion and the Sadistic Conclusion, which is also repugnant. By contrast, Undistinguished Critical-Range Utilitarianism does not entail this conclusion.

Information

Type
Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press

A central challenge in population axiology is to find a plausible way to avoid the following, counter-intuitive, conclusions:

The Repugnant Conclusion: Each outcome where everyone has a very good life is worse than some outcome where everyone has a barely good life.Footnote 1

The Sadistic Conclusion: Each outcome where everyone has a bad life is better than some outcome where everyone has a good life.Footnote 2

While it’s easy to find axiologies that avoid one of these conclusions, it’s surprisingly hard to find a compelling axiology that avoids both.Footnote 3 Consider, for instance, Total Utilitarianism, the axiology that values an outcome by the sum total of the well-being of the individuals who exist in the outcome. While Total Utilitarianism avoids the Sadistic Conclusion, it entails the Repugnant Conclusion.Footnote 4

Critical-Level Utilitarianism is a generalization of Total Utilitarianism. Like the latter, Critical-Level Utilitarianism is an additive measure of the value of an outcome, summing up the well-being of each person to get the value of the outcome. The difference is that, according to Critical-Level Utilitarianism, a certain critical level is subtracted from each individual’s well-being level before these levels are summed up. (If this critical level is the neutral level of well-being, however, the resulting version of Critical-Level Utilitarianism is equivalent to Total Utilitarianism.) Let the critical total value of an outcome $ X$ given a certain critical level $ w$ be

$$ v(X,w)=\sum _{i\,{\rm{exists}}\,{\rm{in}}\,X} ({w}_{i,X}-w),$$

where $ {w}_{i,X}$ is the well-being of individual $ i$ in $ X$ . Then, according to

Critical-Level Utilitarianism: An outcome $ X$ is at least as good as an outcome $ Y$ if and only if $ v(X,w)$ is at least as great as $ v(Y,w)$ .Footnote 5

No matter which level is the critical level, either Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Repugnant Conclusion or it entails the Sadistic Conclusion. To see this, note first that, given a neutral or bad critical level, Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Repugnant Conclusion. Let $ A$ be any outcome where everyone has a very good life. Then there is an outcome $ Z$ such that everyone in $ Z$ has a barely good life and, due to its much larger population, $ Z$ has a greater critical total value than $ A$ :

To avoid the Repugnant Conclusion, we need a critical level that is higher than the neutral level by a sufficient margin so that it’s unrepugnant that an outcome with a very large population where everyone has a level of well-being barely above the critical level is better than an outcome with a smaller population where everyone has a very good life.

Yet, if the critical level is above the neutral level with some margin so that there is at least one good well-being level below the critical level, then Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Sadistic Conclusion. The Sadistic Conclusion follows from Critical-Level Utilitarianism if there is a good well-being level below the critical level. To see this, note that one could make an arbitrarily bad outcome by increasing the size of a population where everyone has a life at this good well-being level below the critical level. Let Bad $ A$ be any outcome where everyone has a bad life. Then, like before, there is an outcome $ Z$ such that everyone in $ Z$ has a barely good life and, due to its much larger population, $ Z$ has a lower critical total value than Bad $ A$ :

So, to avoid the Sadistic Conclusion, we need a bad or almost neutral critical level.

There is a negative analogue to the Repugnant Conclusion. In this variant, people’s lives are bad rather than good. According to

The Mirrored Repugnant Conclusion: Each outcome where everyone has a very bad life is better than some outcome where everyone has a barely bad life.Footnote 6

Unless the critical level is sufficiently lower than the neutral level, Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Mirrored Repugnant Conclusion.

The trouble is that the critical level needs to be sufficiently high above the neutral level to avoid the Repugnant Conclusion. So, once we specify the critical level, Critical-Level Utilitarianism cannot avoid either entailing the Repugnant Conclusion or entailing both of the Mirrored Repugnant Conclusion and the Sadistic Conclusion.

1 Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism

One way to amend Critical-Level Utilitarianism so that it avoids each of these counter-intuitive conclusions is to also claim that it is indeterminate which well-being level is the critical level:

Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism is Critical-Level Utilitarianism in conjunction with there being a range of indeterminacy, which is a range of well-being levels such that it is determinate that the critical level is in this range but, for each level in the range, it is indeterminate whether that level is the critical level.

This makes some assumptions about the logic of indeterminacy. We have a determinately true disjunction where no disjunct is determinately true – that is, the disjunction of the claims, for each well-being level in the critical range, that that level is the critical level.Footnote 7

John Broome’s account of Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism relies on supervaluationism.Footnote 8 According to supervaluationism, the evaluation of a statement involving vague or indeterminate terms depends on its sharpenings – that is, the admissible ways it can be made precise. On Broome’s version of supervaluationism, we may assert a statement ‘ $ S$ ’ if and only if ‘ $ S$ ’ is true under each one of its sharpenings.Footnote 9 To apply supervaluationism to Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism, we let the well-being levels in the range of indeterminacy be the extensions of the sharpenings of the term ‘critical level’, and we assume for simplicity that the indeterminacy of ‘critical level’ is the only source of indeterminacy. We can then assert the statement that ‘some well-being level in the range of indeterminacy is the critical level’, since this will be true given each sharpening of ‘critical level’. But, for every well-being level $ l$ in the range of indeterminacy, we may not assert the statement ‘ $ l$ is the critical level’, since this will be false given some sharpening of ‘critical level’ (assuming that there is more than one level in the range).

Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism could also be coupled with an epistemic view of indeterminacy, where indeterminacy is merely a kind of ignorance. On the epistemic view, there are sharp boundaries to the extensions of vague or indeterminate terms but we do not know and perhaps cannot know where those boundaries lie.Footnote 10 Applying the epistemic view to Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism, we let the well-being levels in the range of indeterminacy be a set of well-being levels such that we know that one of them is the extension of ‘critical level’ and, if there is more than one level in the range, we are ignorant, for each level in the range, as to whether that level is the extension of ‘critical level’. So we know that one of the well-being levels in the range of indeterminacy is the critical level. But, for every well-being level in the range of indeterminacy, we don’t know whether that level is the critical level (assuming again that there is more than one level in the range).

Let $ I$ be the set of well-being levels in the range of indeterminacy. Then, on either supervaluationism or the epistemic view of indeterminacy, Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails that

an outcome $ X$ is determinately at least as good as an outcome $ Y$ if and only if, for all $ w$ in $ I$ , it holds that $ v(X,w)$ is at least as great as $ v(Y,w)$ , and

an outcome $ X$ is determinately not at least as good as an outcome $ Y$ if and only if, for all $ w$ in $ I$ , it holds that $ v(X,w)$ is not at least as great as $ v(Y,w)$ .

Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism avoids each one of the Repugnant Conclusion, the Mirrored Repugnant Conclusion, and the Sadistic Conclusion. Given a range of indeterminacy with an upper bound sufficiently higher than the neutral level and a lower bound sufficiently lower than the neutral level, none of these conclusions is determinately true on Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism. Yet, while these conclusions are not determinately true on Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism, they are not determinately false either. Following Broome, however, we may feel that the indeterminacy of these conclusions is enough to mitigate their repugnance.Footnote 11

2 Undistinguished Critical-Range Utilitarianism

We have seen how we can avoid both the Repugnant Conclusion and the Sadistic Conclusion if we add indeterminacy to Critical-Level Utilitarianism. But, in much the same way, we can also avoid these conclusions if we add incomparability to the theory. There is a structurally analogous variation of Critical-Level Utilitarianism, where, instead of a range of indeterminacy, there is a range of undistinguishedness. This is a range of well-being levels such that adding a person whose well-being falls in this range renders (other things being equal) the resulting outcome incomparable to the original. Consider

Critical-Range Utilitarianism: Let $ U$ be the set of well-being levels in the range of undistinguishedness. Then an outcome $ X$ is at least as good as an outcome $ Y$ if and only if, for all $ w$ in $ U$ , it holds that $ v(X,w)$ is at least as great as $ v(Y,w)$ .Footnote 12

If $ U$ and $ I$ contain the same well-being levels, then Critical-Range Utilitarianism will entail that an outcome $ X$ is at least as good as an outcome $ Y$ if and only if Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails that $ X$ is determinately at least as good as $ Y$ . The theories still differ, however, in that, when Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails that $ X$ is indeterminately at least as good as $ Y$ , Critical-Range Utilitarianism entails that $ X$ is incomparable with $ Y$ .

Suppose we further accept that lives at the well-being levels in $ U$ are undistinguished – that is, that they are value bearers but they are not good, not bad, and not neutral.Footnote 13 Then we can accept

The Personal Critical-Range View: Let $ U$ be the set of well-being levels in the range of undistinguishedness. Then lives at well-being levels higher than all levels in $ U$ are good, lives at well-being levels lower than all levels in $ U$ are bad, and lives at well-being levels in $ U$ are undistinguished.Footnote 14

Note that, since undistinguished lives are still value bearers, this view is consistent with the claim that a first life is at least as good as a second life if and only if the first life is at a well-being level at least as high as the second life. That is, we can compare lives at well-being levels in the range of undistinguishedness.

Let Undistinguished Critical-Range Utilitarianism be the combination of Critical-Range Utilitarianism and the Personal Critical-Range View.Footnote 15 Given Undistinguished Critical-Range Utilitarianism, we avoid both the Repugnant Conclusion and the Sadistic Conclusion (and the Mirrored Repugnant Conclusion). So it seems that Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism and the combination of Critical-Range Utilitarianism and the Personal Critical-Range View both avoid repugnance and sadism.Footnote 16

There are, of course, other worries. For instance, Critical-Range Utilitarianism is open to the Greediness Objection – that is, if we improve the lives in an outcome and add some people with lives at a well-being level in the critical range (other things being equal), the resulting outcome may be incomparable to the original.

One motivation for having a critical range is to capture the Intuition of Neutrality – that is, to capture the intuition that, while we are in favour of making people happy, we are neutral about creating happy people.Footnote 17 But, if improving people’s lives is an improvement and adding a life is neutral, then the combination of improving and adding should result in an outcome that is better, rather than an outcome that is incomparable with the original.Footnote 18 Nevertheless, Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism faces much the same problem, because, if we improve the lives in an outcome and add some people with lives at a well-being level in the critical range (other things being equal), the resulting outcome may be indeterminate in comparison to the original according to Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism – rather than determinately better.Footnote 19

3 The Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion

So we have two approaches for amending Critical-Level Utilitarianism with essentially the same formal structure. And they both avoid entailing the various problematic conclusions we have considered. But they differ in whether this is done by introducing indeterminacy or incomparability. As Broome notes, indeterminacy and incomparability lead to much the same practical problems.Footnote 20 And the views agree about all comparisons of outcomes that do not involve indeterminacy or incomparability. That is, they will do so if the range of indeterminacy, $ I$ , includes the same well-being levels as the range of undistinguishedness, $ U$ . The two theories agree, for any two outcomes $ X$ and $ Y$ , about whether $ X$ is determinately at least as good as $ Y$ .Footnote 21 (And the outcomes are incomparable according to Critical-Range Utilitarianism if and only if their comparison is indeterminate on Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism.) So one may wonder if we have any reason to favour one of these approaches over the other.

I shall argue, however, that these approaches differ in their ability to avoid repugnance. Even if we merely wish to avoid entailing that something repugnant is determinately true, Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism still fails in this regard. While the two theories agree, for any two outcomes $ X$ and $ Y$ , whether $ X$ is determinately at least as good as $ Y$ , the theories can still disagree about general claims about comparisons of outcomes. To see this, we shall consider two conclusions which are disjunctions of the previous ones. According to

The Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion: [Either the Repugnant Conclusion or the Mirrored Repugnant Conclusion] is true.Footnote 22

And, similarly, according to

The Either-Repugnant-or-Sadistic Conclusion: [Either the Repugnant Conclusion or the Sadistic Conclusion] is true.

These two disjunctive conclusions seem on a par in repugnance with the Repugnant Conclusion.

Moreover, there is a straightforward argument that the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion should be repugnant. For each disjunct in these conclusions, any value ordering of outcomes that satisfies the disjunct is repugnant. So each of these disjuncts entails that the value ordering of outcomes is repugnant. By argument by cases, we then find that each of these disjunctions entails that the value ordering of outcomes is repugnant. So these disjunctive conclusions should be repugnant too. Formally, the argument can be put as follows. Let $ \mathrm{R}\mathrm{C}$ be the Repugnant Conclusion, let $ \mathrm{S}\mathrm{C}$ be the Sadistic Conclusion, and let $ \mathrm{R}$ be that the value ordering of outcomes is repugnant. Since any value ordering of outcomes satisfying at least one of $ \mathrm{R}\mathrm{C}$ and $ \mathrm{S}\mathrm{C}$ is repugnant, we have $ \mathrm{R}\mathrm{C}\supset \mathrm{R}$ and $ \mathrm{S}\mathrm{C}\supset \mathrm{R}$ . Then – from $ \mathrm{R}\mathrm{C}\supset \mathrm{R}$ , $ \mathrm{S}\mathrm{C}\supset \mathrm{R}$ , and $ \mathrm{R}\mathrm{C}\vee \mathrm{S}\mathrm{C}$ – we have $ \mathrm{R}$ by argument by cases.Footnote 23

There is a further argument that these disjunctive conclusions should be repugnant if ‘repugnant’ is used in an evaluative sense. This is how it is used by, for example, J. M. E. McTaggart, who was the first to call conclusions like the Repugnant Conclusion ‘repugnant’. He writes:

This conclusion would, I believe, be repugnant to certain moralists. But, in the first place, a conclusion may be rightly repugnant to us, and yet it may be true, since the universe is not completely good.Footnote 24

A standard view in the logic of value is the principle of disjunctive interpolation, that is, the principle that disjunctions fall between their disjuncts in terms of intrinsic value.Footnote 25 If, for example, $ p$ is intrinsically bad and $ q$ is intrinsically bad, then the disjunction $ p\vee q$ is also intrinsically bad. Analogously, the repugnance of a disjunction should fall between its disjuncts in terms of repugnance. So, if both the Repugnant Conclusion and the Mirrored Repugnant Conclusion are repugnant, the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion should be repugnant too. Likewise, if both the Repugnant Conclusion and the Sadistic Conclusion are repugnant, the Either-Repugnant-or-Sadistic Conclusion should be so too.

The problem is that, regardless of which well-being levels are in the range of indeterminacy, Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails both of these disjunctive conclusions. Or, at least, it does so given either of the two standard views of indeterminacy – namely, supervaluationism and the epistemic view.Footnote 26 Let a precise version of Critical-Level Utilitarianism be Critical-Level Utilitarianism with a certain well-being level as the precise critical level. So, for each well-being level, we have a unique precise version of Critical-Level Utilitarianism where that level is the critical level. Every precise version of Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion. This is because, whichever well-being level is the critical level, Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails at least one of the disjuncts in the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion. Moving on, the rest of the argument proceeds differently depending on whether we adopt supervaluationism or the epistemic view of indeterminacy.

On supervaluationism, we may assert the statement ‘Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion’ if it is true on each one of its sharpenings. Having assumed for simplicity that the only source of indeterminacy is the indeterminacy of ‘critical level’, each sharpening of the statement will state that a certain precise version of Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion. And, since each precise version of Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion, we have that each sharpening of the statement is true. Hence we may assert that Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion, even if the critical level is indeterminate.

On the epistemic view, we know that one well-being level in the range of indeterminacy is the critical level. So, if we know that Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism is true, we know that some precise version of Critical-Level Utilitarianism is true, even though we don’t know which version it is. But, since every precise version of Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion, we then know that the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion is true. Hence we know that Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion.

So, on both of these views, we find that Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion. And, changing what needs to be changed, we find that Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism entails the Either-Repugnant-or-Sadistic Conclusion. Accordingly, Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism does not avoid these repugnant disjunctive conclusions.

Undistinguished Critical-Range Utilitarianism, however, entails neither the Disjunctive Repugnant Conclusion nor the Either-Repugnant-or-Sadistic Conclusion. It entails that both of these conclusions are false, since it entails that each of their disjuncts is false. Hence we have an argument for favouring Undistinguished Critical-Range Utilitarianism over the formally very similar view, Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism.

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Gustaf Arrhenius, Barry Lee, Martin Peterson, Mozaffar Qizilbash, Wlodek Rabinowicz, Tom Stoneham, and the audience of the Final conference of the Franco-Swedish Program for Philosophy and Economics at Swedish Collegium for Advanced Study on June 8, 2015 for valuable comments.

Footnotes

1 Parfit’s (Reference Parfit1984, p. 388) canonical statement of the Repugnant Conclusion is more complicated. But those complications won’t matter for our discussion.

2 Arrhenius Reference Arrhenius2000, p. 256.

4 For example, while Average Utilitarianism avoids the Repugnant Conclusion, it entails the Sadistic Conclusion. See Arrhenius Reference Arrhenius2000, p. 251. See Parfit Reference Parfit1984, p. 422 for the similar objection that, on Average Utilitarianism, it can be better to add lives at a negative well-being level than not to do so (other things being equal).

5 Blackorby and Donaldson Reference Blackorby and Donaldson1984, p. 14. Broome (Reference Broome2004, p. 255) calls this the Integrated Standardized Total Principle.

6 Carlson Reference Carlson1998, p. 297.

7 While determinately true disjunctions where no disjunct is determinately true are allowed on supervaluationism and an epistemic view like Williamson’s (Reference Williamson1994), they are ruled out by truth-functional many-valued theories, such as Halldén’s (Reference Halldén1949, p. 48) logic of nonsense and Machina’s (Reference Machina1976) degree-theoretic approach, where a disjunction cannot be completely true if no disjunct is completely true.

8 Broome Reference Broome2004, pp. 255–6.

9 Broome (Reference Broome2004, pp. 177–8) adds the qualification that supervaluationism does not apply if ‘ $S$ ’ contains terms from the metalanguage, such as ‘vagueness’, ‘sharpening’, or ‘we may assert’.

11 Broome Reference Broome2004, pp. 213–14.

12 Blackorby et al. (Reference Blackorby, Bossert and Donaldson1996, p. 141) called this Incomplete Critical-Level Utilitarianism. Blackorby et al. (Reference Blackorby, Bossert and Donaldson2005, p. 252) later renamed it Critical-Band Utilitarianism. Rabinowicz (Reference Rabinowicz2009, p. 404), Qizilbash (Reference Qizilbash2007), and Gustafsson (Reference Gustafsson2020, p. 92) propose similar views.

13 Gustafsson Reference Gustafsson2020, p. 88; Reference Gustafsson2023, p. 610.

15 Gustafsson Reference Gustafsson2020, p. 92.

16 It may be objected that Undistinguished Critical-Range Utilitarianism entails both of the following conclusions (and their good/bad-inverted, mirrored variants):

The Weak Repugnant Conclusion (barely-not-bad version): Each outcome where everyone has a very good life is not at least as good as some outcome where everyone has a life that is just marginally better than some bad life. (Gustafsson Reference Gustafsson2020, p. 95.)

The Weak Sadistic Conclusion (not-bad version): Each outcome where everyone has a bad life is not worse than some outcome where everyone has a life that is not bad.

These conclusions, however, seem less repugnant once we grant the Personal Critical-Range View. An outcome with a very large number of lives at an undistinguished level will be (overall) very undistinguished and, hence, incomparable with many outcomes with only bad lives or only good lives. For a fuller response, see Gustafsson Reference Gustafsson2020, pp. 94–6.

17 Narveson Reference Narveson1973, p. 80 and Broome Reference Broome2004, pp. 143–6.

18 Broome Reference Broome2004, p. 169. For a response to the Greediness Objection, see Gustafsson Reference Gustafsson2020, pp. 107–10.

19 Rabinowicz Reference Rabinowicz2009, p. 400.

20 Broome Reference Broome2004, p. 85; Reference Broome2009, pp. 415–17.

21 For example, suppose the range of both indeterminacy and undistinguishedness is $\left[ { - 10,10} \right]$ . And suppose that we are considering adding a pair of people with lives at well-being levels $100\space \rm and\space 9$ . Then, on Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism, this is a determinately good addition — since, for every sharpened critical level $w$ in the range of indeterminacy, it holds that $\left( {100 - w} \right) + \left( {9 - w} \right) \gt 0$ . But, on Undistinguished Critical-Range Utilitarianism, this is also a good addition — since, for every level $w$ in the range of undistinguishedness, it holds that $\left( {100 - w} \right) + \left( {9 - w} \right) \gt 0$ . Note that the addition is overall good, even though the addition of the person at level $9$ is undistinguished, since, on every level $w$ in the range of undistinguishedness, the contribution of the person at level $100$ outweighs the (potentially) negative contribution of the person at level $9$ .

22 Here and in the Either-Repugnant-or-Sadistic Conclusion, the square brackets indicate that ‘is true’ applies to the disjunction rather than the disjuncts.

23 It may be objected that argument by cases is not a valid form of inference on supervaluationism; see Williamson Reference Williamson1994, p. 152. Keefe (Reference Keefe2000, pp. 175–6), however, points out that, in the absence of the ‘definitely’ operator, the consequence relation of supervaluationism coincides with the consequence relation of classical logic. And there is no ‘definitely’, ‘determinately’, or ‘we may assert’ operator in play in the present argument — there is, in fact, no talk of vagueness or indeterminacy at all. In the formal version of the argument, we also avoid the ‘is true’ locution of the disjunctive conclusions. Hence, in this case, we can apply classical inference rules, such as argument by cases, even on supervaluationism. Furthermore, argument by cases is valid on Williamson’s (Reference Williamson1994, p. 271) logic of clarity.

24 McTaggart Reference McTaggart1927, p. 453.

25 See, for example, Hansson Reference Hansson1968, p. 438, Castañeda Reference Castañeda1969, p. 264, and Chisholm Reference Chisholm1975, p. 297. The name is due to Hansson (Reference Hansson1997, p. 437). (For a preferential analogue, see Bolker Reference Bolker1967, p. 336 and Jeffrey Reference Jeffrey, Hooker, Leach and McClennen1978, p. 229; Reference Jeffrey1983, p. 146.) This axiological principle has been challenged by Oldfield (Reference Oldfield1977, pp. 245–6). For Oldfield’s counter-example, we assume hedonism and consider all conjunctions such that the first conjunct is the state of affairs Jones’s being happy to degree 1 and the second conjunct is either the state of affairs Bill’s not existing or a state of affairs of the form Bill’s being happy to degree $i$ , where positive values of $i$ represent degrees of happiness and negative values of $i$ represent degrees of unhappiness. Some of these conjunctions are intrinsically good; some are intrinsically bad; and some are intrinsically neutral. Let $G$ be the disjunction of the intrinsically good conjunctions; let $B$ be the disjunction of the intrinsically bad conjunctions; and let $N$ be the disjunction of the intrinsically neutral conjunctions. It seems plausible that $G$ is intrinsically good, $B$ is intrinsically bad, and $N$ is intrinsically neutral. Oldfield claims that the disjunction $G$ -or- $B$ is neither intrinsically good nor intrinsically bad, since it is ‘good at some worlds and bad at others’. Finally, on hedonism, the disjunction $N$ -or-( $G$ -or- $B$ ) must be intrinsically good, since it is necessarily equivalent with Jones’s being happy to degree 1. But then $N$ -or-( $G$ -or- $B$ ) is intrinsically better than each of its disjuncts, which contradicts the principle of disjunctive interpolation. A weak point in Oldfield’s counter-example is his argument that $G$ -or- $B$ is not intrinsically good. It turns on Oldfield’s idea that intrinsic value can be world relative, which, as Carlson (Reference Carlson1997, p. 99) points out, seems to ‘reflect a failure to grasp the concept of intrinsic value’. Carlson (Reference Carlson1997, p. 104), however, still finds it plausible that $G$ -or- $B$ isn’t intrinsically good and he endorses Oldfield’s counter-example. Yet I don’t see why $G$ -or- $B$ cannot be intrinsically good; it guarantees that Jones is happy to degree 1 and it does not guarantee that there is any unhappiness.

26 Also, it’s unclear whether Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism could fare better with some of the less standard views of indeterminacy. For example, as was mentioned in note 7, truth-functional many-valued theories do not fit with the assumptions about the logic of indeterminacy in Indeterminate Critical-Level Utilitarianism.

References

Arrhenius, Gustaf, ‘An Impossibility Theorem for Welfarist Axiologies’, Economics and Philosophy, 16 (2000), 247266.10.1017/S0266267100000249CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackorby, Charles, Bossert, Walter, and Donaldson, David, ‘Quasi-Orderings and Population Ethics’, Social Choice and Welfare, 13 (1996), 129150.10.1007/BF00183348CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackorby, Charles, Bossert, Walter, and Donaldson, David, Population Issues in Social Choice Theory, Welfare Economics, and Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).10.1017/CCOL0521825512CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackorby, Charles and Donaldson, David, ‘Social Criteria for Evaluating Population Change’, Journal of Public Economics, 25 (1984), 1333.10.1016/0047-2727(84)90042-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolker, Ethan D., ‘A Simultaneous Axiomatization of Utility and Subjective Probability’, Philosophy of Science, 34 (1967), 333340.10.1086/288171CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, John, Weighing Lives (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).10.1093/019924376X.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, John, ‘Reply to Rabinowicz’, Philosophical Issues, 19 (2009), 412417.10.1111/j.1533-6077.2009.00175.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carlson, Erik, ‘The Intrinsic Value of Non-Basic States of Affairs’, Philosophical Studies, 85 (1997), 95107.10.1023/A:1017902109118CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carlson, Erik, ‘Mere Addition and Two Trilemmas of Population Ethics’, Economics and Philosophy, 14 (1998), 283306.10.1017/S0266267100003862CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castañeda, Hector-Neri, ‘Ought, Value, and Utilitarianism’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 6 (1969), 257275.Google Scholar
Chisholm, Roderick M., ‘The Intrinsic Value in Disjunctive States of Affairs’, Noûs, 9 (1975), 295308.10.2307/2214633CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gustafsson, Johan E., ‘Population Axiology and the Possibility of a Fourth Category of Absolute Value’, Economics and Philosophy, 36 (2020), 81110.10.1017/S0266267119000087CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gustafsson, Johan E., ‘Our Intuitive Grasp of the Repugnant Conclusion’, in The Oxford Handbook of Population Ethics, ed. by Arrhenius, Gustaf, Bykvist, Krister, Campbell, Tim, and Finneron-Burns, Elizabeth (New York: Oxford University Press, 2022), pp. 371389.10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190907686.013.25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gustafsson, Johan E., ‘The Possibility of Undistinguishedness’, Philosophical Studies, 180 (2023), 609613.10.1007/s11098-022-01889-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halldén, Sören, The Logic of Nonsense (Uppsala: Uppsala Universitets Årsskrift, 1949).Google Scholar
Hansson, Bengt, ‘Fundamental Axioms for Preference Relations’, Synthese, 18 (1968), 423448.10.1007/BF00484978CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansson, Sven Ove, ‘Situationist Deontic Logic’, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 26 (1997), 423448.10.1023/A:1004233913104CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, Richard C., ‘Axiomatizing the Logic of Decision’, in Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory Volume I: Theoretical Foundations, ed. by Hooker, C. A., Leach, J. J., and McClennen, E. F. (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1978), pp. 227231.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, Richard C., The Logic of Decision, 2 nd edn (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983).Google Scholar
Keefe, Rosanna, Theories of Vagueness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).Google Scholar
Keefe, Rosanna and Smith, Peter, ‘Introduction: Theories of Vagueness’, in Vagueness: A Reader, ed. by Keefe, Rosanna and Smith, Peter (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997), pp. 157.10.7551/mitpress/7064.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machina, Kenton F., ‘Truth, Belief, and Vagueness’, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 5 (1976), 4778.10.1007/BF00263657CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McTaggart, John McTaggart Ellis, The Nature of Existence Volume II (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1927).Google Scholar
Narveson, Jan, ‘Moral Problems of Population’, Monist, 57 (1973), 6286.10.5840/monist197357134CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Oldfield, Edward, ‘An Approach to a Theory of Intrinsic Value’, Philosophical Studies, 32 (1977), 233249.10.1007/BF00354136CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, Derek, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984).Google Scholar
Qizilbash, Mozaffar, ‘The Mere Addition Paradox, Parity and Vagueness’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75 (2007), 129151.10.1111/j.1933-1592.2007.00063.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinowicz, Wlodek, ‘Broome and the Intuition of Neutrality’, Philosophical Issues, 19 (2009), 389411.10.1111/j.1533-6077.2009.00174.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinowicz, Wlodek, ‘Getting Personal: The Intuition of Neutrality Reinterpreted’, in The Oxford Handbook of Population Ethics, ed. by Arrhenius, Gustaf, Bykvist, Krister, Campbell, Tim, and Finneron-Burns, Elizabeth (New York: Oxford University Press, 2022), pp. 114141.10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190907686.013.17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Timothy, Vagueness (London: Routledge, 1994).Google Scholar
Zuber, Stéphane, Venkatesh, Nikhil, Tännsjö, Torbjörn, Tarsney, Christian, Stefánsson, H. Orri, Steele, Katie, Spears, Dean, Sebo, Jeff, Pivato, Marcus, Ord, Toby, Ng, Yew-Kwang, Masny, Michal, MacAskill, William, Lawson, Nicholas, Kuruc, Kevin, Hutchinson, Michelle, Gustafsson, Johan E., Greaves, Hilary, Forsberg, Lisa, Fleurbaey, Marc, Coffey, Diane, Cato, Susumu, Castro, Clinton, Campbell, Tim, Budolfson, Mark, Broome, John, Berger, Alexander, Beckstead, Nick, and Asheim, Geir B., ‘What Should We Agree on about the Repugnant Conclusion?’, Utilitas, 33 (2021), 379383.10.1017/S095382082100011XCrossRefGoogle Scholar