Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-2bdfx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-10-10T08:39:37.439Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

WHY SHOULD IDENTITY BE LOGICAL?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 September 2025

CHRIS MITSCH*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF COMPUTER SCIENCE BUCKNELL UNIVERSITY LEWISBURG PA 17837 USA

Abstract

Logical inferentialists have expected identity to be susceptible of harmonious introduction and elimination rules in natural deduction. While Read and Klev have proposed rules they argue are harmonious, Griffiths and Ahmed have criticized these rules as insufficient for harmony. These critics, moreover, suggest that no harmonious rules are forthcoming. We argue that these critics are correct: the logical inferentialist should abandon hope for harmonious rules for identity. The paper analyzes the three major uses of identity in presumed-logical languages: variable coordination, definitional substitution, and co-reference. We show that identity qua variable coordination is not logical by providing a harmonious natural-deduction system that captures this use through the quantifiers. We then argue that identity qua definitional substitution or co-reference faces a dilemma: either its rules are harmonious but they obscure its actual use in inference, or its rules are not harmonious but they make its actual use in inference plain. We conclude that the inferentialist may have harmonious rules for identity only by disrespecting its inferential use.

MSC classification

Information

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Article purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Boolos, G., Burgess, J., & Jeffrey, R. (2007). Computability and Logic (fifth edition). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fiengo, R., & May, R. (2009). De Lingua Belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Geach, P. T. (1973). Ontological relativity and relative identity. In Munitz, M. K., editors. Logic and Ontology. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Gratzl, N., & Orlandelli, E. (2016). Double-line harmony in sequent calculi. In Arazim, P., & Lavicka, T., editors. The Logical Yearbook 2016. Rickmansworth: College Publications, pp. 151171.Google Scholar
Griffiths, O. (2014). Harmonious rules for identity. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 7(3), 499510.Google Scholar
Griffiths, O. (2017). Inferentialism and quantification. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 58(1), 107113.Google Scholar
Griffiths, O., & Ahmed, A. (2021). Introducing identity. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 50, 14491469.Google Scholar
Hale, B., & Wright, C. (2001). The Reason’s Proper Study: Essays towards a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1956). Identity, variables, and impredicative definitions. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 21(3), 225245.Google Scholar
Indrzejczak, A. (2021). A novel approach to equality. Synthese, 199(1–2), 47494774.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1978). The plight of the platonist. Noûs, 12(2), 119136.Google Scholar
Klev, A. (2017). The Logical Form of Identity Criteria, The Logica Yearbook, 181196.Google Scholar
Klev, A. (2019). The harmony of identity. Journal of Philosophical Logic, Springer, 48(5), 867884.Google Scholar
Maddy, P. (2024). Wittgenstein on Mathematics. Philosophical Investigations, 47(4), 461483.Google Scholar
Murzi, J. (2020). Classical harmony and separability. Erkenntnis, 85, 391415.Google Scholar
Negri, S., & Von Plato, J. (2008). Structural Proof Theory. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Negri, S., & Von Plato, J. (2015). Meaning in use. In W. Heinrich editor, Dag Prawitz on Proofs and Meaning. New York: Springer, 239257.Google Scholar
Pardey, U., & Wehmeier, K. F. (2019). Frege’s Begriffsschrift theory of identity vindicated. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Language, 1, 122147.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1950). Identity, ostension, and hypostasis. The Journal of Philosophy, 47(22), 621633.Google Scholar
Van Orman, W., & Quine, O. (1960). Word and Object. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Read, S. (2004). Identity and harmony. Analysis, 64(2), 113119.Google Scholar
Read, S. (2010). General-elimination harmony and the meaning of the logical constants. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 39(5), 557576.Google Scholar
Read, S. (2016). Harmonic inferentialism and the logic of identity. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 9(2), 408420.Google Scholar
Read, S. (2016). Harmonic inferentialism and the logic of identity. This is an amended version of [23]. The emendations occur only in §4. https://www.st-andrews.ac.uk/~slr/Inferentialism-Identity-amended.pdf.Google Scholar
Rumfitt, I. (2003). Singular terms and arithmetical logicism. Philosophical Books, 44(3), 193219.Google Scholar
Steinberger, F. (2011). Harmony in a sequent setting: A reply to Tennant. Analysis, 71(2), 273280.Google Scholar
Steinberger, F. (2011). What harmony could and could not be. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89, 617639.Google Scholar
Tennant, N. (1978). Natural Logic. Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Tennant, N. (2004). A general theory of abstraction operators. The Philosophical Quarterly, 54(214), 105133.Google Scholar
Tennant, N. (2010). Harmony in a sequent setting. Analysis, 70(3), 462468.Google Scholar
Vlasáková, M. (2021). What is identical? Logica Universalis, 15, 153170.Google Scholar
Wehmeier, K. (2004). Wittgensteinian predicate logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 45, 111.Google Scholar
Wehmeier, K. (2008). Wittgensteinian tableaux, identity, and co-denotation. Erkenntnis, 69(3), 363376.Google Scholar
Wehmeier, K. (2012). How to live without identity–and why. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(4), 761777.Google Scholar
Wilson, M. (1983). Why contingent identity is necessary. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 43(3), 301327.Google Scholar
Wilson, M. (2006). Wandering Significance: An Essay on Conceptual Behavior. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (2005). In Luckhardt, C. G., and Aue, M. A. E., editors. The Big Typescript: TS 213. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar