Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cb9f654ff-lqqdg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-08-30T13:46:19.312Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - A Theory of WTO Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 December 2023

Chios Carmody
Affiliation:
University of Western Ontario

Summary

Criticism is often made that the WTO Agreement has the potential to undermine human rights and accentuates the disruptive effects of globalization. Nevertheless, justice in sovereign terms is different from justice in human terms. This difference is perhaps best illustrated by means of a theory. This book puts forward such a theory. The theory posits that law does justice in order to sustain the good of the community. Justice in relation to the good can be thought about either according to the good’s distribution ex ante or its correction ex post after injury. The metric of distributive justice is equality, whereas the metric of corrective justice is fairness, or what is appropriate. This dualism is exhibited in thinking about WTO arrangements and is replicated in WTO law. In one mode WTO law is about the attainment of equality by means of obligations. In a second mode WTO law is about the attainment of fairness by means of rights. The two modes of law interact over time. Ultimately, they depend upon each other to generate a third, overarching structure in the form of interdependent obligations and rights manifested in a sui generis legal system.

Information

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023

1 A Theory of WTO Law

theory, as of a system of knowledge.Footnote 1

1.1 Why a Theory?

This book puts forward a theory of the law of the World Trade Organization (WTO). A “theory” is a “system of ideas,” with the emphasis being on the “system,” or set of relationships, regularly exhibited between those ideas.Footnote 2

In this book I make the principal point that WTO law is about interdependence as reflected in varying conceptions of the good. The theory emphasizes how WTO law reflects regular relationships between classic forms of justice that work to sustain the good.

Before going into detail on this point, however, I think it is important to address some potential objections to a theory, both as a way of providing some background to the subject and underlining the importance of what is advanced here.

One potential objection is the fact that WTO disputes are difficult to assimilate with justice, at least if justice is thought about in corrective terms. Most WTO disputes are initiated by a single complainant country and defended by a single respondent country. If the complaint is made out, the proceedings normally end in a cryptic direction to the wrongdoing country to bring its laws and regulations “into conformity” with the organization’s basic treaty, WTO Agreement. No compensation is automatically payable.

Another potential objection is the lack of any direct reference to “justice” in WTO texts. When the WTO Agreement was concluded in 1994 member governments spoke chiefly of the new treaty as contributing to the rule of law, not justice, and since that time criticism of the treaty by human rights advocates, environmental activists and others has left the impression of it in many quarters as unjust.Footnote 3

A further potential objection is encapsulated in the question, why is such a theory necessary? After all, until recently WTO dispute settlement has functioned reasonably well without a theory, and so it might be queried whether one is required or useful.

Over time, however, eminent commentators have implied that a theory is useful, either by alluding to one or trying to define its contents in some preliminary way. For instance, as long ago as 1983 Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann observed with respect to the WTO Agreement’s forerunner, the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT 1947), that “a comprehensive economic theory of [the international economic system] is not to be found in the (neo) classical treatises on political economy.” Petersmann went on to note that:

an order should be characterized by a coherent system of starting points, objectives, principles, and institutional and instrumental means that can achieve the formulated objectives in an orderly fashion.Footnote 4

More recently in 2005, Thomas Cottier, Matthias Oesch and Thomas Fisher observed that “the absence of a long-standing legal theory or tradition of international trade regulation explains why even basic questions of international trade law are still in the open.”Footnote 5

The statements of Petersmann, Cottier and others infer that whatever the current state of thinking about WTO law, a theory is desirable because it conforms with the general intuition that a theory is rational.

There will be limits to this rationality of course. That is because any theory is a distillation. Anne Peters has pointed out how all theories involve simplification. The benefit of simplification is explanatory. “The simpler the theory, the better you understand [it].”Footnote 6

At the same time, the simplicity of a theory can generate uncertainty about its explanatory power and elicit criticism.Footnote 7 No theory will explain everything and as I intend to show, that is certainly true of the theory put forward in this book.

Instead, what is highlighted by the theory is tendencies as opposed to certainties. As such, some phenomena of WTO law will be explained relatively well by the theory whereas others will not. The theory aims to strike a balance between simplification and explanation. Its shortcomings will spur the quest for other, more accurate theories.

A theory like this one is likely to be useful in a number of ways. First, it will provide an overview, or “map,” of the WTO legal system. With it we will no longer be left to “wander around among the differences”Footnote 8 of WTO provisions and cases. Rather, there will be something more schematic to guide legal thinking.

Second, reasoning about WTO law often takes place from within the law – its existing texts and jurisprudence – whereas the theory outlined here analyzes the body of law by means of concepts beyond it, notably community and justice. This approach is particularly promising because there continues to be much debate about the future of the WTO as a community and about the ultimate justice of WTO law, issues which, as of the time of this writing, have provoked a variety of reactions, including an impasse over the role of the WTO dispute settlement system’s court of appeal, the Appellate Body, which in late 2019 suspended operation. To that extent, the theory may offer a diagnosis for what currently ails the WTO.

Third, a theory is useful because it is predictive. It will provide some indication of how WTO law is likely to evolve in future.

In response then to the question posed at the outset of this chapter, why a theory?, there are several answers. A theory is useful because it is rational as well as analytic, diagnostic and predictive.

There is something else too. This is the possibility of using the theory to outline a theory of law in general. At a time of some pessimism about the likelihood of ever successfully identifying a general theory of law, I will suggest that what is observed in WTO law is in some degree an illustration of how law does justice in any community.Footnote 9 Such an assertion might appear grandiose – even foolish – but in my view it is nothing more than recognition of the fact that what has happened in the course of WTO law’s short history is the emergence of regular relationships expressive of the need for justice in a community.

1.2 The Outline of a Theory

The word “theory” is often associated with abstraction and complexity. It is therefore worthwhile providing a synopsis of what is put forward here in order to summarize the theory’s contents and help direct subsequent discussion.

The theory outlined in this book is a three-fold theory. It is, first and foremost, a theory of community, a theory about how individual actors come together and depend upon each other to produce certain things they hold together and value that I will refer to as “goods.”

Second, the theory is a theory of justice, or in other words, a theory about how members of a community regularly conceive of what is right or correct in relation to goods.

Third, the theory is a theory of law, a theory about how legal elements relate to each other in an effort to do justice as it relates to goods.

A preliminary outline of the theory’s structure can be summarized as shown in Figure 1.1.

Figure 1.1 A communitarian theory outline

In sum, the theory posits that the law does justice in order to sustain the good of the community.Footnote 10 Again, it is helpful for the purposes of subsequent discussion to briefly outline these ideas a little further.

1.2.1 A Theory of Community

The foundation of a theory of law lies in interdependence, a phenomenon rooted in biology. Humans are members of a uniquely interdependent species.Footnote 11 We create and rely upon many goods that could not be produced by one individual in a single human lifetime. These include vaccines, jet travel and the internet.

In the latest phase of interdependence from 1990 on the “blend of Western industrial know-how and Asian manufacturing muscle” has fueled a “hyper-globalisation of supply chains” that has left an impression of the world as “flat.”Footnote 12 Although there are some indications that this hyper-globalizing trend has moderated, interdependence in the form of global supply and value chains remains enormously important.Footnote 13

Some idea of its importance was given in US – Aircraft, a WTO dispute concerning subsidies granted to the US aircraft industry. There, a WTO dispute settlement panel detailed the multinational list of suppliers involved in assembling the Boeing 787:

Completion of sub-assemblies and integration of systems takes place in Everett, Washington, with many components being pre-installed before delivery to Everett. The 787 composite wings are being manufactured by Mitsubishi Heavy Industries. The horizontal stabilizers are being manufactured by Alenia Aeronautica in Italy, and various parts of the fuselage sections are being built by Alenia in Italy, Vought in Charleston, South Carolina, Kawasaki Heavy Industries and Fuji Heavy Industries in Japan, Alenia in Italy and Spirit Aerosystems in Wichita, Kansas. The main landing gear and nose landing gear are being supplied by the French company Messier-Dowty, while passenger doors are being made by Latécoère in France, and the cargo, access and crew escape doors by Saab in Sweden.Footnote 14

The panel noted that as a result of globalized manufacturing, Boeing has “shifted responsibility for detailed component design to suppliers, and focuses on systems integration, managing overall requirements, as well as the assembly process. The 787 is essentially assembled from large substructures designed and produced by suppliers.”Footnote 15

The panel’s description of the Boeing 787’s assembly process is emblematic of the way that what has arisen through interdependence is an elaborate network of relationships. Much modern production and consumption is characterized by them. They value coordination and integration so that delivery of the final product becomes a unity.

Unity places demands on supply and value chain participants. They need to consider matters differently than they would if acting independently. Regular reliance means that actors have to pay at least as much attention to what they are required to do as to what they want to do.

The experience of Boeing and other actors demonstrates the way that interdependence modifies thinking. Similarly in this book, I maintain that the modification generated by WTO law is primarily mind-driven. The “security and predictability”Footnote 16 that are repeatedly identified as constituting the core of WTO disciplines are closely linked to interdependence in that they afford officials, producers and consumers in member countries an extended horizon on which to plan. The ultimate purpose of this coordination is to produce goods.Footnote 17

In light of these ideas, it is possible to begin outlining a theory of community as shown in Figure 1.2.

Figure 1.2 A theory of community

In economics goods are characterized by different degrees of exclusivity and rivalry.Footnote 18 Exclusivity refers to the way in which a good’s use may be limited or restricted to some individual or group. Rivalry refers to the way a good’s use may diminish its benefits for others.

The combination of exclusivity and rivalry results in four different categories of goods. First, there are exclusive, rivalrous private goods such as real estate. Second, there are exclusive, nonrivalrous “club” goods such as toll roads or the internet. Third, there are nonexclusive, rivalrous common goods such as natural resources. Fourth, there are nonexclusive, nonrival “public” goods such as public health.Footnote 19

As I will explain, the arrangements establishing the WTO Agreement create a “club” good. This is in the sense that the concessions and commitments made by member countries under it are reserved to the WTO membership, and that at least in theory, one member’s access does not diminish the treaty’s benefits for others.

At the time of the WTO Agreement’s inauguration in 1995, there was broad consensus about the advantages of this good. Over time, however, the sense of benefit and mutual advantage from it has decreased due to misgivings about unconditional interdependence. As a result, the club good of the WTO Agreement now appears to be splintering into a series of bilateral relationships more appropriately likened to private goods. This evolution is emblematic of the way in which the conception of the good can change and how it reflects the changing nature of the community.

1.2.2 A Theory of Justice

Notwithstanding these ideas, actors are unlikely to come together to produce goods without some assurance that they are better off by doing so. This gives rise to a preoccupation in a community with justice.

In this book I take the view that the idea of justice can be distilled into the essence proposed by Herbert Hart in 1958 when he observed that justice consists:

of two parts: a uniform or constant feature, summarized by the precept “Treat like cases alike” and a shifting or varying criterion used in determining when, for any given purpose, cases are alike or different.Footnote 20

A respected body of opinion championed by a number of scholars including Neil MacCormick later refined these ideas to assert that justice is fundamentally composed of values of equality plus fairness.Footnote 21 The basic relationship can be represented as follows:

Justice = Equality + Fairness

As I will show, the experience of WTO law suggests that the basic relationship above is accompanied by two provisos:

Proviso #1: Equality ≠ Fairness

Proviso #2: Equality > Fairness

Proviso #1 (i.e. Equality ≠ Fairness) emphasizes how the distinction ordinarily made between “equality” and “fairness” implies that the two terms do not mean the same thing.

The ascription of distinct meanings to equality and fairness dovetails with recent research in anthropology and evolutionary psychology, which indicates that fairness, in particular, is a uniquely human trait, something not observed in our closest genetic relatives.Footnote 22 As David Schmidtz has noted, what makes a result “fair [is] not that our slices are equal – they may not be – but that neither of us has grounds for complaint.”Footnote 23 From this set of insights, some evolutionary psychologists hypothesize that it is a sense of fairness – a sense that all participants will be treated “appropriately,” if not equally – that is key to explaining individuals’ extraordinary ability to cooperate.

Still, this set of observations leaves open an important question: if fairness is so important and if it has played such a central role in human evolution, why are human communities not entirely fairness-based? Many commentators have observed that fairness cannot serve as the basis for all human relations otherwise the law risks becoming purely subjective.Footnote 24

The natural limits to fairness infer that in an impersonal community another value becomes important.Footnote 25 This is equality.

For a long time equality has been the preeminent ideal of a political community, at least in Western thinking.Footnote 26 In contemporary life it assumes added importance because increased specialization forces actors to engage in many transactions to meet their daily needs. These transactions do not guarantee that actors will be relatively better off than their peers, only that they will have no “grounds for complaint.”

This paradox leads to Proviso #2 (i.e. Equality > Fairness). The proviso introduces a priority in the relationship between equality and fairness. It holds that equality is the primary ideal whereas fairness is the secondary ideal. One way of understanding the priority is to recognize that actors and institutions do fairness in order to attain equality. They participate in all kinds of inequalities for the purpose of realizing whatever equality is deemed to be.

A theory of justice can then be outlined and linked to the theory of community put forward earlier as shown in Figure 1.3.

Figure 1.3 A theory of community and justice

This combination suggests that actors come together and cooperate in communities to produce goods according to ideals of equality and fairness. These ideals are communally determined and unequal although not for that reason alone unjust. What matters, as mentioned, is that actors have no “grounds for complaint.”

The theory of justice put forward in this book is therefore communitarian. In that respect it differs from other theories and accounts of justice based on liberalism, or the school of thought that has traditionally emphasized the importance of the individual and the gradual reform of institutions.Footnote 27

Communitarian thinking took shape in the 1970s largely in response to the work of John Rawls. In A Theory of Justice (1969), Rawls put forward the now-famous liberal view that individuals coming together in a prototypical community would agree to two key principles of justice:

  1. 1. that each person should have an equal right to basic liberties (the “liberty principle”)

  2. 2. that social and economic inequalities would be arranged to be of the greatest benefit to the least-advantaged members of the community (the “difference principle”).Footnote 28

Communitarian thinkers took issue with these principles in several respects. Their most persistent criticism of Rawls’s work has been that it is inaccurate to maintain, as Rawls initially appeared to do, that a Rawlsian theory of justice is universally true.Footnote 29

Despite the persistence of a communitarian critique of Rawlsian ideas, however, leading communitarian critics of Rawls have never offered “a grand communitarian theory as a systematic alternative to liberalism.”Footnote 30 Communitarian emphasis on the particularity of communities and the uniqueness of justice in each community make it difficult to say much that is definitive about communitarian thinking. To this day there remains no standard account of what a communitarian vision of justice would look like.Footnote 31

In this book I undertake the task of outlining a communitarian theory of justice with the help of illustrative examples drawn in the first instance from WTO law. I agree with the basic communitarian thesis that justice is a product of community. At the same time, I posit that although the justice done in a community is community-specific, it will display some combination of the two ideals of justice mentioned above: equality and fairness. A community’s particular expression or “identity”Footnote 32 of these will therefore be distinct.

This position may appear superficially similar to that of Rawls but in the first instance draws more heavily on the work of Aristotle.

Aristotle was interested in many things including the nature of community, or as he put it, what “holds people together.”Footnote 33 He concluded that what holds people together is justice. This conclusion suggests that the ideas of equality and fairness highlighted above need to be operationalized in standard forms of justice.

In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle posited that a community will exhibit justice in two forms: corrective and distributive. Corrective justice applies to private goods and plays a rectificatory role in transactions. It is the justice most familiar in daily life. Thus, when people are wrongfully deprived of their property, they are entitled to have it returned or to be compensated.

Distributive justice, by contrast, applies to public goods such as “honours or wealth or anything else that can be divided among members of a community who have a share in the political system.”Footnote 34 When a breach of the public good occurs, the wrongdoer is usually deprived of community. An example is the case of a convicted criminal whose wrong – a crime – is a wrong done to the entire community and whose traditional penalty is imprisonment, in effect a deprivation of community.Footnote 35

In this book I likewise posit that law in a community will express some combination of corrective and distributive justice. However, while accepting Aristotle’s two-fold arrangement of justice, I do some with some modifications.

Aristotle’s original formulation inferred that the metric of corrective justice is equality – you get back what you’ve lost – whereas the metric of distributive justice is fairness – you get back what you’re entitled to. His position on these points has caused centuries of confusion among commentators who have plainly noted that the outcome of many corrective operations is not equal.Footnote 36

My solution to this problem is to modify Aristotelian ideas by positing the reverse.Footnote 37 In corrective operations you get what you’re entitled to get whereas in distributive ones you get what everyone merits as a member of the community.

What justifies such a rearrangement? First, the metric of corrective justice is fairness or what is appropriate because there are competing communal demands in any corrective operation. Simply put, a community does not have unlimited resources with which to correct injury, and indeed, in many instances has a vested interest in minimizing the communal cost of correction. Rules on settlement and court costs in many legal systems prove this point.Footnote 38

Second, the metric of distributive justice is more appropriately regarded as equality or what is necessary to affirm the equality of actors in the community.Footnote 39

This rearrangement of Aristotle’s ideas can be depicted as shown in Figure 1.4.

Figure 1.4 The structure of justice

The rearrangement infers that the basic relationship postulated in Proviso #2 above between equality and fairness (i.e. Equality > Fairness) is reproduced between distributive and corrective justice (i.e. Distributive Justice > Corrective Justice). Distributive justice is primary, whereas corrective justice is secondary.

On further reflection, however, it also becomes evident that the traditional Aristotelian categories of justice are conservative. They do not envisage any transformation of the good over time. Contemporary thinking recognizes this deficiency. It appreciates that a just legal system, as the hallmark of a sustainable community, must adapt to evolving ideas about the good.

This realization leads to the conclusion that over time there must be a point at which equality and distributive justice merge with fairness and corrective justice. Here the overarching aim of justice is transformative. What does transformative justice transform? Fundamentally it transforms legal relations with respect to the good.

The doing of transformative justice will result in what is deemed to be just – not ideal or “perfect” justice, but simply justice eo instante, the best that can be done in the instant moment. That justice inevitably will be perceived by some as unjust, a factor that provides a continuing impetus for reform.

The doing of equality via distributive justice and of fairness via corrective justice then encourages “accommodative relationships between groups with competing interests.”Footnote 40 The accommodation is reached in order to sustain the community. It serves as the basis for an interactive and interdependent view of the relationship between distributive and corrective justice, which I go on to develop in Chapter 3.

How exactly does this theory of justice manifest in WTO law? As will be seen, WTO law is structured chiefly as an egalitarian and distributive legal system. Its principal aim is to ensure the “security and predictability”Footnote 41 of trade concessions and commitments made by member countries that every other member country is deemed to have an equal expectation of. When injury occurs, the obligation on a wrongdoing country in WTO dispute settlement is to settle the dispute or withdraw the offending measure, action which is understood to restore the equality of competitive conditions.

A second aspect of WTO law is more evidently equitable and corrective. Correction is apparent in certain instances of permissible counteraction and authorizations of countermeasures under the WTO Agreement. As will be discussed, such action, though nominally “equivalent” to the injury sustained, is rarely in fact so and is more likely to be a matter of what is appropriate or “fair.”

Finally, the interaction of distributive and corrective justice in WTO law generates transformative justice. Transformation is particularly evident in a number of settlements achieved under WTO dispute settlement. This typology of justice explains how even though WTO arrangements do not allow for equal counteraction in every instance, they might nevertheless still be considered just.

1.2.3 A Theory of Law

The theories of community and justice outlined above serve as background for a theory of WTO law. In sum, their ideas of the “good” and what is just condition the nature of the WTO legal system. To appreciate this point, some further explanation is necessary.

A convenient starting point for identifying a theory of WTO law is to ask what is legal about the WTO Agreement. In other words, what gives the treaty its lawful, binding character? In Maritime Delimitation and Territorial Questions (Qatar v. Bahrain)Footnote 42 the International Court of Justice (ICJ) held that the essence of a legal agreement in international law is whether or not a particular agreement – in that case the minutes of a meeting – discloses an intention to be bound:

the Minutes … do not merely give an account of discussions and summarize points of agreement and disagreement. They enumerate the commitments to which the Parties have consented. They thus create rights and obligations under international law for the Parties.Footnote 43

The Court’s reference to “rights and obligations” is behind my insistence, pursued more fully in subsequent chapters, at focusing on rights and obligations as the basis of a theory of law. Their arrangement, the contrapuntal stress they create, and the way they simultaneously work to “constrain and enable”Footnote 44 actors’ behavior offer insight into why WTO law is as it is.

In law the traditional relationship of rights and obligations is correlative. Each right is considered to be matched by a single offsetting obligation (i.e. Right = Obligation).Footnote 45 In WTO law, however, the jural matrix is more complex. GATT’s Most Favored Nation (MFN) obligation causes obligations owed by one member country to be owed simultaneously to the entire WTO membership. Due to this and other nondiscrimination provisions in the treaty, the general orientation of the WTO legal system is toward obligations. Hence, obligations are primary whereas rights are secondary (i.e. Obligation > Right).

That same orientation is also discernible in the WTO Agreement structurally. Many commentators have taken to describing WTO legal arrangements as either a “contract” or a “constitution.” The most authoritative reference to contractualism is the WTO Appellate Body’s statement in Japan – Alcoholic Beverages that:

The WTO Agreement is a treaty – the international equivalent of a contract. It is self-evident that in an exercise of their sovereignty, and in pursuit of their own respective national interests, the Members of the WTO have made a bargain. In exchange for the benefits they expect to receive as Members of the WTO, they have agreed to exercise their sovereignty according to the commitments they have made in the WTO Agreement.Footnote 46

The Appellate Body’s statement in Japan – Alcoholic Beverages emphasizes the limited nature of the treaty and its legal system. The WTO Agreement is a “contract,” and national sovereignty is constrained only to the extent that countries have made commitments under it. Thus, WTO law would appear to be composed of rights that countries have limited for the purpose of enjoying the benefits extended under the treaty.Footnote 47

A second view of the WTO Agreement is constitutive. This is in the sense that the treaty establishes the WTO as an international organization.Footnote 48 In addition, John Jackson and others have referred to the WTO Agreement as a “constitution” and Gail Evans has made the observation that “WTO law may be explained as a trade constitution having the capacity to universalize norms of substantive law.”Footnote 49 Accordingly, WTO law would appear to be composed of obligations that are more constraining and limitative.Footnote 50

The record of WTO law infers a certain priority or orientation between “contract” and “constitution.” That is because WTO member countries are limited in the degree to which they can “contract out” of their WTO obligations.Footnote 51 From this requirement it is possible to conclude that the WTO legal system is more constitutive than contractual (i.e. Constitution > Contract).

The same orientation is also visible in the temporal perspective of WTO law. WTO law applies over time in a succession of moments progressing from the past to the future. This continuum demonstrates the same general orientation as the other conceptual pairs introduced above in the sense that WTO law is always open to renegotiation and change (i.e. Future > Past).Footnote 52

Finally, the same orientation is visible in WTO law’s reasoning, which is either deductive or inductive. Deduction is the logic of what “will be” based on assumptions.Footnote 53 By contrast, induction is the logic of what “is” or “was” based on proof.Footnote 54

WTO law depends heavily on deductive reasoning and presumption. There is, for example, the well-known presumption in WTO law which provides that “[i]n cases where there is an infringement of the obligations assumed under a covered agreement, the action is considered prima facie to constitute a case of nullification or impairment.” Case law has generally upheld the principle that while the presumption is formally rebuttable, in practice, it had “operated as an irrefutable presumption.”Footnote 55 This conclusion follows from a number of GATT-era cases wherein nullification or impairment was found even for measures that had no demonstrable trade effect.Footnote 56

The presumption mentioned above lies at the heart of the WTO legal system inasmuch as it conditions when state responsibility will be triggered. Much less often does WTO law depend on induction and proof. Proof can be particularly hard to supply in a system without a mechanism for discovery such as WTO dispute settlement, hence the priority of deduction versus induction (i.e. Deduction > Induction).

The regular orientation of elements suggests that the theory of law set out above can be joined to the theories of community and justice outlined earlier. In addition, the alignments observed between conceptual pairs in the theoretic framework above are not only “horizontal” (i.e. between elements of the same pair) but also “vertical” (i.e. between elements of different pairs). In other words, there is a link between ideas of obligation, constitution, an ex ante perspective and deduction. This link is evident inasmuch as an order of obligations is often referred to as a constitution, which is a document “for the future”Footnote 57 within which much is presumed. Likewise, a link is observed between rights, contract, an ex post perspective and induction since a contract is frequently described as expressing the will – or rights – of parties and breach is determined by proof of injury after-the-fact.Footnote 58

These ideas can now be assembled and arranged together as shown in Figure 1.5.

Figure 1.5 A communitarian theory of law (preliminary)

From the foregoing arrangement, it then becomes possible to identify two distinct “idea-complexes”Footnote 59 at work in WTO law. In one idea-complex the law is about the attainment of equality as a matter of distributive justice. In the other it is about the attainment of fairness as a matter of corrective justice. The two complexes describe the law in a single moment.Footnote 60

The theory’s division of the law into separate idea-complexes is attractive. It streamlines the law, highlighting its contrasting tendencies.

Nevertheless, the division also involves considerable simplification and, taken literally, might be dismissed as a kind of reductio ad absurdem. That is because, as mentioned, the conception of the good is not static and justice is not purely a matter of equality or fairness but rather aims at transformation.

This preoccupation with transformation emerges from integration. Integration is evident in the way that the two elements of each conceptual pair outlined above over time tend to merge to create a tertium quid or “third thing,” defined as “something novel, yet also dependent on what went on before.”Footnote 61

The impulse to transformation modifies thinking about legal relationships, notably the conception of obligations and rights in relation to goods. As a result, obligations and rights become interdependent.Footnote 62 Working together they generate a sui generis legal system, which conditions the behavior of actors in distinctive ways within the system that are not observed – at least not to the same degree – outside the system.

Similarly, in the case of a legal structure, the interaction of constitutive and contractual frameworks generates what I term a “contractual constitution,” a structure whose content is fluid but whose boundaries are essentially fixed.

In the case of temporal perspectives, the interaction of ex ante perspectives with ex post perspectives generates a contemporary perspective with an emphasis on law doing justice eo instante (i.e. in the present).

Finally, in the case of reasoning the interaction of deductive logic in the form of presumptions and inductive logic in the form of requirements for proof generates abductive logic, often called “an intelligent guess”Footnote 63 or “inference to the best explanation.”Footnote 64

The foregoing ideas can then be depicted altogether as shown in Figure 1.6.

Figure 1.6 A communitarian theory of law

The task of identifying a theory of law then becomes one of furnishing proof of these conceptual pairs and their associated relationships by means of examples drawn from WTO law.

1.3 Of Relationships and a System

In the previous section, I discussed how conceptual pairings in both justice and law exhibit the same relationships of correlation, subordination and integration. However, the core of a theory of law is somewhat more complex than this and needs to be more fully explained.

To review, the theoretic background suggests that the first relationship between elements is one of correlation. In short, where there is equality and distributive justice there will be a need for fairness and corrective justice. Here, the existence of obligations implies corresponding rights (i.e. Obligation/Right).

The second relationship is one of subordination. Equality and distributive justice tend to be primary, whereas fairness and corrective justice tend to be secondary. Here, obligations are primary whereas rights are secondary (i.e. Obligation > Right).

The third – and new – relationship is one of transition. Transition infers that at their outer limits, equality and distributive justice will convert or transition into their conceptual opposites of fairness and corrective justice, and vice versa (i.e. Equality/Distributive Justice = Fairness/Corrective Justice). Transition is observed in the way that equality tends to splinter into fairness positions and, likewise, that multiple instances of fairness generate contradiction and demands for egalitarian unity.Footnote 65

Transition is similarly exhibited in the relationship between obligations and rights in WTO law. This is in the sense that WTO members are only bound to the extent of their obligations, beyond which they are generally free to exercise their rights (i.e. Obligation = Right). The same tendency is also exhibited between constitution and contract (i.e. Constitution = Contract), future and past (i.e. Future = Past), and deduction and induction (i.e. Deduction = Induction).Footnote 66 Transition is a reflection of the way in which each conceptual pair in the theory forms what Jack Balkin has termed a “nested opposition.”Footnote 67

Finally, the fourth relationship is one of integration. I have already mentioned how the interaction of equality and fairness generates justice – not “ideal justice,” but justice in the present that is transformative (Distributive Justice + Corrective Justice = Transformative Justice).

Similarly, obligations and rights generate a sui generis legal system (i.e. Obligation + Right = Sui Generis Legal System), constitution and contract generate a “contractual constitution” (i.e. Constitution + Contract = Contractual Constitution), ex ante perspectives and ex post perspectives generate an eo instante perspective (i.e. Future + Past = Present), and deduction and induction generate abduction (i.e. Deduction + Induction = Abduction).

These four recurrent relationships at the level of both justice and law emphasize how the theory put forward in this book works in a coherent way as a “system.” Consequently, the idea of system needs to be examined and explained.

Systems theory suggests that a system exhibits at least five characteristics.Footnote 68 First, a system displays coherence and unity. The components of a system relate to each other more closely and regularly than those outside the system. Second, a system is exclusive. It is “closed” to external influence in some degree, and as a result, manifests its own distinctive rationality. Third, a system is ordinarily considered to be self-regulating. That regulation may take the form of correspondence as in a symmetry, or conditionality as in a sequence, or it may assume certain classic forms through its link to a common regulating factor such as a constitution. Fourth, a system displays transformed properties that are different from its constituent elements. These may take the form of independent attributes or identity. Fifth, a system aims to achieve a certain purpose. In legal systems, for instance, the principal purpose of the system is often said to be to do justice.Footnote 69

The systematic character of WTO law is well-known. In Brazil – Dessicated Coconut, for instance, the Appellate Body observed that:

The WTO Agreement is fundamentally different from the GATT system which preceded it. The previous system was made up of several agreements, understandings and legal instruments, the most significant of which were the GATT 1947 and the nine Tokyo Round Agreements, including the Tokyo Round SCM Code. Each of these major agreements was a treaty with different membership, an independent governing body and a separate dispute settlement mechanism … Unlike the previous GATT system, the WTO Agreement is a single treaty instrument which is accepted by the WTO Members as a “single undertaking.”Footnote 70

The Appellate Body went on to detail how the WTO system alters behavior through the concurrent operation of obligations and rights, in that case involving disciplines on countervailing action by member countries to address trade-distorting subsidies:

The [GATT and WTO] SCM Agreements do not merely impose additional substantive and procedural obligations on a potential user of countervailing measures. Rather, the SCM Agreements and Article VI together define, clarify and in some cases modify the whole package of rights and obligations of a potential user of countervailing measures.Footnote 71

What is apparent from these excerpts is the idea that WTO obligations and rights function “concurrently and cumulatively”Footnote 72 as a system to shape states’ behavior in a single moment. No one element is individually responsible for doing so. Instead, all elements work together systematically to transform the relationships in question. In Brazil – Dessicated Coconut the Appellate Body confirmed this understanding by referring to the WTO Agreement as “an integrated system.”Footnote 73

1.4 A Theory as Theory

The communitarian theory outlined above naturally raises the question, what kind of a theory is this? Where does it fit within the constellation of generally accepted theories of law?

Theories of law traditionally take as their starting point the “semantic” theories of natural law and positivism.Footnote 74 Natural law considers the law to be dictated by higher authority or reason and to be essentially coextensive with justice. Positivism, by contrast, considers the law to be “posited” by those with the authority to do so and hence to be something that may depart from justice.Footnote 75

The two semantic theories are often thought to be separate and distinct. However, the communitarian theory put forward in this book appears to combine both. That is because in highlighting interdependence the theory emphasizes how natural law impulses in the form of obligations and positivist impulses in the form of rights are present and reconciled within a single legal system. To that extent, the theory can be thought of as a synthesis.

The foregoing observations apply primarily to the theory’s character as a theory of law. However, as mentioned, the theory outlined here is a combined theory of community, justice and law. It is therefore worthwhile saying something about the theory as a theory of community and justice before returning to the matter of its characterization as a theory of law.

Earlier I said that leading communitarians have never offered a comprehensive theory as a systematic alternative to liberalism. As a result, there continues to be no standard account of what a communitarian theory of law would look like nor any definitive list of what its central tenets might be.

In this book I take the view that the essence of community arises out of what actors share, or in other words, what they have in common and value. It stands to reason that what they share and value they will seek to protect, adjust and transform.

This simple assertion might not be enough for the purposes of identifying a defensible theory of community, however. Instead, a conceptual framework appears necessary. Such a framework may be sourced in thinking about the international community.

In 1998 Bruno Simma and Andreas Paulus observed that “[t]here seems to be general agreement that the factual element of a community, namely, a sufficient degree of interdependence, is present in the international system.”Footnote 76 Simma and Paulus went on to identify the international community’s values and institutions.

They referred to three traditions of thought about the international community, each of which “is connected to a certain reception of values incorporated in the international system”Footnote 77 First, there is a Hobbesian or “realist” tradition in which “states are seen as being in a permanent situation of cold or hot war,” where “[i]nternational law merely duplicates the power structure.”Footnote 78 Second, there is a Kantian or universalist tradition that “sees at work in international politics a potential community of mankind” whose systemic value is justice. This tradition may justify “community intervention for the protection of individuals against their own state.”Footnote 79 Third, there is a Grotian or internationalist tradition in which “international society is composed of states … [and] cooperation between states is considered possible … in order to realize common values and interests.”Footnote 80

Simma and Paulus went on to divide the Grotian tradition into two strands. One is “Vattelian” and international only in a narrow sense. “It emphasizes the international interest of states.” Here, “[c]ooperation is the exception, not the rule.” The main value “is not cooperation, but order.”Footnote 81 The other strand is “truly Grotian” or “neo-Grotian” “because of its modern emphasis on institutions.”Footnote 82 It “sees the international system on its way to becoming an ‘organized state community’ with an emphasis on common interests, the development of common values and the creation of common institutions.”Footnote 83 Its paramount value is “solidarity between peoples.”Footnote 84

An examination of WTO arrangements and certain terminology emanating from WTO dispute settlement suggests that the concept of community prevailing under the WTO Agreement is primarily “neo-Grotian.” As I will show, WTO dispute settlement has managed to identify a club good arising from concessions and commitments made by member countries that involves their common interest. This good emerges from interdependence.

Nevertheless, the theory also suggests that the idea of the good is not completely stable. Its character and identity can change.

As mentioned, at the time of the WTO Agreement’s conclusion in 1994 there was a strong consensus about the advantages of unconditional interdependence. The Cold War had just ended and there was a desire to restructure the international economic system. In that era it was relatively easy to associate the new treaty with distributive justice and an ex ante perspective on its arrangements summed up in the phrase “the equality of competitive conditions.”

Accompanying this consensus was a new streamlined system of dispute settlement in the WTO composed of panels and an Appellate Body, which raised hopes that countries would submit their differences to “fair, prompt and effective” resolution of trade disputes.Footnote 85 Where no settlement could be achieved or compensation negotiated, trade sanctions could follow. On this view WTO law would promote “self-enforcing trade”.Footnote 86

The idea of “self-enforcing trade” was a popular one and promoted a second, competing conception of community under the WTO Agreement as “Kantian or possibly “Vattelian”. According to that conception, member countries would complain against each other for violations of the treaty, and where necessary, invoke countermeasures to promote compliance. The chief concern of the community would be achieving “justice” or instilling “order.”

The difficulty with that conception is that it is at odds with the treaty’s community, which remains more evidently Grotian. As I will explain, WTO law does not offer compensation for trade injury in the past and is instead primarily distributive and forward-looking. A Kantian or Vattelian conception also seems to ignore or downplay several practical issues that arise in countries’ invocation of countermeasures and the point made earlier that corrective justice imposes costs on a community. Consequently, it has been little realized in practice.

Three decades on, however, both the unconditional interdependence provided for in WTO arrangements and WTO dispute settlement are viewed much more cautiously. While there remains support for the idea of comparative advantage on which WTO arrangements are based, the combined effects of trade liberalization and technical change have caused governments to rethink, and in some cases reduce, their commitment to it. This development, together with growing inequality in many countries and unease at vulnerabilities stemming from interdependence, lies at the core of current concern with the WTO Agreement.

This development is suggestive of the way that the good emanating from the WTO Agreement as a community has come to be regarded as less good, and in certain quarters, as “bad.” Movement away from a view of the treaty as a relatively unified club good now appears to be taking place. Along with it, there appears to be a parallel movement away from WTO law as a matter of equal opportunity ex ante toward one involving debate about the fairness or unfairness of specific outcomes ex post.

One solution to current difficulties may lie in remaking the WTO dispute settlement system into something more evidently Kantian and corrective, but this option would appear to undercut the primarily distributive nature of the treaty and the fact that countermeasures between pairs of countries in the image of action for breach have not proven popular.

The net result suggests that justice under WTO law is far more complex than simply protecting the equality of competitive conditions or promoting correction. Ultimately, the theory put forward in this book suggests that justice is concerned with “solidarity between peoples” and transformation.

Transformation is visible in many settlements reached in WTO dispute settlement. It is also visible in current efforts to reform and repurpose the WTO as an organization.

All of the above hints at a more modest role for the WTO in terms of justice, not as a Kantian “trade enforcer” but as a setting within which common positions can be worked out, with some attention paid to law. Perhaps the best that can be hoped for at present is a “forum organization”Footnote 87 in line with Simma and Paulus’s idea of a neo-Grotian community.

Earlier I said that a communitarian theory achieves a synthesis of natural law and positivism. It bears considering what this synthesis involves.

Most wholesale theories of law are preoccupied with identifying the ultimate source of legal obligation, or in other words, where legal obligations come from.

Efforts to answer this question in domestic law – at least in the Anglosphere – focus on “a few key figures and their central claims.”Footnote 88 These include the command theory of John Austin,Footnote 89 Herbert Hart’s theory of law as the union of primary and secondary rules,Footnote 90 Hans Kelsen’s theory of a legal system as resting upon a fundamental norm (grundnorm),Footnote 91 Joseph Raz’s service conception of authority and sources thesis,Footnote 92 and Ronald Dworkin’s theory of interpretation.Footnote 93 These authorities have been supplemented by an array of other theories and approaches in recent decades, generally of more limited scope, attempting to theorize the law in one field, or with respect to one particular doctrine or cause of action.Footnote 94

Theories of international law have likewise been preoccupied with identifying the ultimate source of legal obligation but have traditionally approached the job of theory from the perspective of consent.Footnote 95 Generally speaking, they appear to forward a mix of natural law and positivist explanations.Footnote 96 More recently, some theorists have also attempted to discern whether international law exhibits a “deep structure” based on alternating utopian (i.e. idealist) and apologist (i.e. realist) accounts, but have had difficulty linking these to any larger framework or explanation such as “non-will-related justice.”Footnote 97

What is apparent from these efforts is that theories of domestic and international law come at the question of the ultimate source of legal obligations by means of their own frames and rationalities. Notwithstanding the difference, what commentators in both spheres seem to conclude is that the source of obligations is found in no single category or source of law but rather in their combination.Footnote 98 The idea of obligation then may be said to arise from the totality of a legal system.

If this is true, then a communitarian theory of law can offer a more coherent and detailed understanding of the ultimate source of legal obligations because of its foundation in “system.”

Still, this bare identification of “system” as the ultimate source of legal obligations may appear a little broad-brush and will not be enough for those who expect theories of law to be more precise. That is why I refer to the four relationships of correlation, subordination, transition and integration identified earlier. They impart a certain direction, or dynamic, in the system. At the same time, commentators will demand to know what the practical consequences of such an identification are.

One immediate consequence is interpretative. For instance, where the question of an obligation arises, a communitarian theory of law suggests that the legal element is likely to be interpreted in a broad and plenary way – to be constitutive, prospective and presumptive, and to involve equal application of the law. Likewise, where the question of a right arises, a communitarian theory suggests that the legal element is likely to be interpreted in a narrow and exceptional way – to be contractual, retrospective and proof-oriented, and to involve fair application of the law.

As I will show, examples of these interpretative practices are frequent in the WTO legal system. Do the same practices hold in every instance? I will suggest that they are likely to, but not invariably. This qualification is tied to a point made earlier, namely, that the theory put forward in this book emphasizes tendencies as opposed to certainties.Footnote 99 Particular fact patterns may exhibit in a contrary way (i.e. Equality < Fairness, Obligation < Right). The foregoing interpretative conventions are discernible in WTO law, but in Chapter 7 I will show how they also exhibit to a degree in international investment law. This projection supplies an example of the theory’s “illuminating power.”Footnote 100

Another consequence of the relationships outlined above is to identify a gradual oscillation, or movement, between the idea-complexes that are part of a theory. In the normal course the conception of the law should move back and forth among polarities, though not necessarily in a monolithic fashion. It seems fairly clear, for instance, that current WTO arrangements are moving away from an obligation-based constitutive regime toward something more rights-based and contractual. In line with this trajectory, some commentators also forecast a further move back toward obligation-based constitutionalism at some point in the future.Footnote 101

One theorist whose work this theory may recall is Hans Kelsen. Kelsen’s “pure” theory of law posited that law should be logically self-supporting and should not depend on extralegal values such as justice. Instead, Kelsen believed that law should be traceable to some basic norm or assumption (the Grundnorm) accepted by a substantial proportion of the community.

Kelsen’s ideas differ from the ones I put forward here in their eschewal of justice. For Kelsen justice was “an irrational ideal … not subject to cognition.”Footnote 102 That rejection deprives his theory of the directing impulse that justice as equality instills. Instead, the relationships he foresaw were organized hierarchically, with subordinate norms being linked to higher-level ones and ultimately to the basic norm. Again, this conception differs from the view taken here wherein law is composed organically as the product of an interactive system. I submit that this systematic conception provides a more accurate description of the workings of a legal system than Kelsen’s does and is more in line with contemporary understanding of power in a community as being exercised both vertically and horizontally.Footnote 103

Where Kelsen and my theories parallel each other, however, is in their monism. Both he and I make little or no distinction between international and domestic law and regard their structures as essentially the same.Footnote 104 Some commentators continue to assert the centrality and vitality of such differences.Footnote 105 In this book I have suggested that the idea of basic structural sameness in law is reinforced by similar structures of justice.Footnote 106 The fact that these structures might express differently in different systems is more a matter of “identity,” that is, how the particular legal system is situated between polarities of equality/distributive justice and fairness/corrective justice, than any presence or absence of elements that might undermine the theory’s architecture.

The theory of law based on justice in this book will also draw comparison with the work of John Rawls. A communitarian theory parallels but also differs from Rawls’s work in a number of ways.

Rawls’s theory of justice was contractarian. By comparison, the theory I put forward in this book is communitarian. Rawls regarded the basic settlement about justice among actors within a community as occurring in a single moment, with only modest attention paid to the need for updating. The theory here exhibits greater awareness of the requirement for ongoing reform. This pivotal distinction generates a series of further differences in our respective positions.

As mentioned, Rawlsian thinking is premised on the founding of a prototypical community, a view that naturally lends itself to a focus on distributive justice.Footnote 107 For this reason Rawls addressed only minimally the problem of dealing with issues of justice correctively ex post such as the WTO membership now confronts.

In addition, Rawls’s work left open the all-important question of how distributive and corrective justice are related. Many commentators today adhere to either a “dependent” view of the relationshipFootnote 108 or, alternatively, one of distributive and corrective justice as independent and autonomous of each other.Footnote 109

The view I take here is that neither of the foregoing views is entirely convincing. Consequently, in Chapter 3 I put forward what I term an “interdependent” view of the relationship.Footnote 110 This view regards the relationship as a variable one that exhibits the four relations of correlation, subordination, transition and integration introduced earlier.

At the same time, there is considerable complexity to such a view. That is because an interdependent view regards a distributive priority as the law’s dominant tendency while also acknowledging corrective justice as the law’s subordinate tendency, generating feedback over time for adjustment of the relevant distribution. Such a hybrid view not only reflects state practice but also better accords with the common understanding of distributive justice as “dynamic” and corrective justice as “static.”Footnote 111

More fundamentally, perhaps, Rawls’s and my views on the nature of community differ. A community may emerge from a Rawlsian “overlapping consensus,” but the communitarian theory outlined in this book suggests that the justice which sustains the community is never entirely ideal and encompasses a wide penumbra of dissent, forcing ideas of injustice and change. Moreover, any historic community retains within it a memory of prior inequalities – for instance, about slavery and racial discrimination in the United States or China’s humiliation at the hands of the Western powers in the nineteenth century – that conditions thinking about the contemporary meaning of equality and fairness.

Another difference between contractarian and communitarian theories of justice lies in their respective approaches to fairness. Rawls’s theory of justice was founded on the notion of equality as modified by “justice as fairness” promoting arrangements for the advantage of the least well-off. As part of the communitarian theory put forward in this book, I recognize fairness to be a much more regular and pervasive phenomenon in a community than Rawls’s projected. It is not simply undertaken for the benefit of the less well-off.Footnote 112

A further difference between contractarian ideas and a communitarian theory is attention to the specific legal elements involved in realizing justice. As mentioned, Rawls was principally concerned with distributive justice and famously articulated entitlements to his liberty and difference principles in terms of “rights.” By contrast, I emphasize the way that a historic community involves both distributive and corrective justice as well as obligations and rights and therefore mandates some degree of priority between them. As a matter of theory, Rawls was not completely clear about the structure of legal relationships arising in a community.

Finally, Rawls disagreed with the application of his theory of justice as fairness to international law. Instead, he projected a separate “Law of Peoples” in international relations, a particular political conception of right and justice that promotes certain key principles and norms of international law.Footnote 113 These would include an ethic of toleration for decently organized peoples. The communitarian theory put forward in this book makes no such distinction. To the extent that a domestic or international community constitutes a community wherein actors hold things in common, I posit that the same conceptual pairings should be visible in that community’s operation as well.

These then are some of the ways in which our respective theories differ, differences which I will elaborate upon in subsequent chapters. At this point I simply suggest that a communitarian theory supplies a more comprehensive and accurate description of what happens under the rubric of “justice” than a purely distributive or contractarian one does, although this should not be taken as a criticism. It might be concluded instead that a communitarian theory “builds out” Rawlsian ideas, supplementing and extending them.Footnote 114 That conclusion would be consistent with the view taken here that many Rawlsian positions remain valid.

A distinctive aspect of this theory of law is its treatment of time. Time is a substantive component of the theory, a resource used to generate interdependence and transformation. Time is therefore more central and active a component in this theory than in other theories and accounts of law, which often regard time passively as a sort of background against which other more dynamic factors play out or which proceeds haltingly from one epoch to the next.Footnote 115

Time is inherent in the keystone concept of community, a concept that highlights what actors share and value across time. The community’s vision of the good and its value are transformed over time. This is because time transforms perception. Actors within a community are constantly confronted by ideas and views different from their own. They must adapt their ideas and views to those of others. In this way the individual’s views are reconciled with those of the community.Footnote 116

This working out of the relationship between the individual and the communal happens, however, only over time, the conception of which may differ depending on the particular community.Footnote 117 WTO law encompasses two distinct conceptions of time, one which is progressive and dynamic (chronos), the other momentary and static (kairos). Their combination takes a form that is transcendent, hence the need to regard both justice and law under the WTO Agreement as diachronic.Footnote 118

The communitarian theory introduced above is founded on a number of conceptual pairs: equality/fairness, obligation/right and so forth. John Finnis has argued that one cannot do first-order legal theory without taking a stand on what the important features are that an adequate theory of law must explain.Footnote 119 Why then employ these particular pairings to outline a theory?

I focus on these pairs because they appear to describe the most basic conceptual couplets involved in discussions of justice and law and because the individual elements within them are naturally thought of as correlatives and opposites.Footnote 120

This is particularly true of obligations and rights, which are frequently referenced together in constitutive instruments of international and domestic law in ways that suggest their preeminence.Footnote 121 In international law it is noteworthy, for instance, that among the initial tasks undertaken by then new United Nations International Law Commission (ILC) in the late 1940s was the development of a Draft Declaration on Rights and Duties of States, as if “rights” and “duties” (i.e. obligations) are somehow foundational in the formulation of international law.Footnote 122 In domestic legal systems their importance as basic legal elements is beyond question.Footnote 123

Inherent in all the referenced pairs, however, is tension, a tension which is also discerned in biology. What do I mean?

Biology is the study of life and living organisms. It emphasizes the life force (zώη) and interaction exhibited during the life cycle of an organism. Each organism establishes a unique set of relationships between itself and its environment. Internally, living organisms are also unique inasmuch as they possess distinct attributes such as metabolism and the capacity to grow and respond to stimuli that are not displayed by their constituents alone. In sum, they are distinct from their constituent elements and surrounding environments but also dependent upon them.

The trade-off between distinctiveness and dependence is not maintained without effort, however. An organism exerts constant effort to sustain and differentiate itself from the rest of its environment.

A community composed of obligations and rights manifests a similar effort. Out of the resulting push-and-pull, what becomes apparent is that in any single moment the legal system of the community approximates a “middle way,” via media, that can be likened to the struggle of an organism to maintain itself between polarities of unity and diversity. The system does so by means of a dialectic.

The dialectic is a process of reasoning dependent upon opposing concepts of thesis, antithesis and synthesis. It has been a regular feature of law and moral philosophy since at least the time of the ancient Greeks. It was famously revived by Hegel, who maintained that mental patterns will manifest themselves over time in pairs of contradictions that ultimately generate a reconciliation.Footnote 124

Such a reconciliation takes place out of the interaction and interdependence among the conceptual pairs I have chosen which, working together, result in transformation. The continual dialectic allows for “integrative thinking,” which Roger Martin has described as:

the ability to face constructively the tension of opposing ideas and, instead of choosing one at the expense of the other, generat[ing] a creative resolution of the tension in the form of a new idea that contains elements of the opposing ideas but is superior to each.Footnote 125

Integrative thinking has four main characteristics. First, it “takes a broader view of what is salient. … More salient features make for a messier problem.”Footnote 126

Second, integrative thinking is open to considering multidirectional and nonlinear causal relationships. That is because “[s]imple, unidirectional relationships are easier to hold in the mind, but they don’t generate more satisfactory resolutions.”Footnote 127

Third, integrative thinking does not “break a problem into independent pieces [to be worked on] separately.”Footnote 128 Instead, the entire problem or system is kept in mind as work proceeds on individual parts. Retention assists in achieving “breakthrough solutions.”Footnote 129

Fourth, integrative thinking searches “for creative resolution of tensions, rather than accept unpleasant trade-offs.”Footnote 130

The communitarian theory presented in this book is a product of integrative thinking. It attempts to analyze the conceptual oppositions at work in WTO law from the vantage point of the system as a whole. To that extent, it highlights how ideas of obligations and rights are generated and conditioned within a community.

The theory is also open to considering multidirectional influences in WTO law, particularly from anthropology, evolutionary psychology and biology, mentioned above. Because the theory’s implicit frame of reference is system-wide, it does not divide the problem of explaining the nature and shape of WTO law into discrete pieces or cases. Instead, in line with the foundational idea of interdependence, it regards all components of the system as working together.

Finally, the theory’s profiling of complexity reveals how the law in operation arrives at a medial point, searching for “creative resolution of tensions, rather than accept[ing] unpleasant trade-offs.” This is evident in its identification of “third things” emanating from the operation of a legal system.

As mentioned, a communitarian theory draws heavily upon biology. Law is “bio-mimetic” in that it imitates biology “or is a mimesis of the processes that take place in biological systems.”Footnote 131

The particular contribution of biology to the theory is its emphasis on interdependence and evolutionary adaptation. To sustain interdependence in the form of community certain factors need to be adhered to over time, justice and law being among them. Still, conditions and conceptions of the good change, and so consequently there is a need for justice and law to change.

It is common to speak of justice and law as “evolving.” However, what I am especially interested in identifying a communitarian theory is the overall direction and content of that change.Footnote 132 How exactly do justice and law change over time in the face of interdependence?

Interdependence means that actors may become responsible for acts or effects upon those with whom they do not immediately depend or reciprocate. Most evidently, these relationships emphasize obligation. That transformation is visible at the level of justice in the evolution of what is considered right or correct, as in the case of certain transformative outcomes in WTO dispute settlement. It is also visible in the emergence of state responsibility for action that is not, strictly speaking, contrary to any treaty obligation, as indicated for example in the “non-violation” cause of action in GATT/WTO law.Footnote 133

Insight from biology thus promotes a transformative view of the law. The tendency is to see the law either as impermeable, fixed and static, or, alternately, as porous, fluid and dynamic. By contrast, biology tends to emphasize the way law is ultimately adaptive, evolutionary and diachronic. It changes according to the evolving sense of the good. The advantage of this conception is that the law is understood more organically. This is the ultimate product of integrative thinking.

1.5 The Structure of This Book

A few words should be said about the structure of this book. I have intended this opening chapter as an overview of the book’s principal themes and ideas. This chapter has provided a summary of the theory and a justification for its three-fold structure.

Chapter 2 examines the WTO Agreement as a community. It sets out a theory of community before furnishing an overview of GATT/WTO arrangements as a community and some idea of the historical background from which they emerged. The chapter makes the point that the WTO Agreement can be understood as a club good belonging to the membership as a whole. A look is taken at the way in which the treaty’s cognitive framework is shaped by textual and contextual considerations that lead to a substantial degree of cohesion and unity.

From this set of observations it might be concluded that WTO obligations are integral – that is, they are owed unconditionally – as indeed the text of the WTO Agreement provides. However, a number of additional features suggest that WTO member countries consider their obligations under the treaty to be interdependent. There is an astute appraisal by countries of reciprocal behavior. Countries will commit, but only to the extent that others do so.

A look is then taken at how contemporary perceptions of fairness are causing the club good emanating from the community of the treaty to become uncoupled and evolve into something looser and perhaps less well-defined. Here, the common good of the membership appears at some points to be splintering into bilateral relationships more akin to private goods.

Chapter 3 focuses on the idea of justice and what theories have been put forward to explain it. The chapter introduces a modified Aristotelian theory of justice that explains much of what is observed in WTO dispute settlement. The chapter also illustrates how Aristotelian categories of distributive and corrective justice, classically conceived of as separate and distinct, are in fact interrelated and work together interactively and interdependently to promote transformation. The chapter concludes with a survey of how transformative justice falls short of “ideal justice,” thereby instilling a continuing impulse for reform in WTO law.

Chapters 4 to 6 constitute the core of this book. Successive chapters are devoted to explaining WTO law as a law of obligations (Chapter 4), a law of rights (Chapter 5) and as a sui generis legal system (Chapter 6). Each chapter opens with some general observations about the law’s operation in that mode, followed by more detailed remarks about its workings in four respects. These are: juridically in terms of obligations and rights, structurally in terms of constitution and contract, temporally in terms of future and past, and rationally in terms of deduction and induction.

The foregoing framework is reasonably coherent and does a good job of accounting for the nature and structure of WTO law. This raises an intriguing question: to what extent can a communitarian theory be understood as a theory of law in general? The question points to a need to apply and test the theory’s operation in other legal systems.

Chapter 7 therefore applies the communitarian theory to international investment law, a body of law chiefly concerned with the protection of investor rights in host countries. Due to this, a communitarian theory would forecast investment law to be preoccupied with corrective justice and to be heavily contractual, retrospective and inductive. The chapter demonstrates how all of these features are confirmed in the shape of contemporary international investment law, and how in light of considerable dissatisfaction with the current regime an impulse is detected toward something more egalitarian, and therefore more obligatory, constitutive, prospective and presumptive.

Finally, Chapter 8 summarizes the ideas put forward in this book. It details how justice under the WTO Agreement is transformative as opposed to corrective but not for that reason entirely unjust. That is because its chief value is solidarity. The chapter also examines the possibility of a communitarian theory serving as a general theory of law. A theory based on these ideas explains a considerable amount in a way that is naturally coherent and fruitful and offers several predictions and prescriptions about the possible future of WTO law.

At the same time, the chapter acknowledges that a communitarian theory is itself incomplete. This is due to abduction, which stresses the tentative, open-ended nature of current knowledge. Presentism suggests there is a danger in thinking about obligations and rights of countries narrowly in the current moment and not in the broader sense of obligations owed to future generations.

1.6 Conclusion

To conclude this opening chapter, it is helpful to say a few words about the wider context in which a communitarian theory will appear.

A theory of WTO law based on ideas about community and justice is likely to provoke reactions from commentators familiar with existing work on the WTO Agreement. There will be the demand to justify the theory outlined above in terms of prior work and to indicate in greater detail what the benefits of identifying such a theory are. Indeed, an acceptable answer to the question posed at the beginning of this chapter – why a theory? – appears to rest implicitly on perceived shortcomings of existing accounts and to promise something better.

To date, the WTO Agreement and its legal system have generated an enormous literature that analyzes the law according to a number of different approaches. I will mention three here.

First, the dominant textual approach to WTO law tracks or reacts to interpretation of the WTO Agreement principally by means of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (VCLT). That interpretation focuses on the text, context, object and purpose of the treaty.Footnote 134 Although textualism has generated significant commentary about the WTO Agreement, it has been unable to offer a coherent theory of WTO law and says little about developments beyond the treaty language itself.

Second, WTO law, as an acknowledged branch of international economic law, might be expected to draw on economics for theoretic insight. However, despite generating substantial commentary about the WTO Agreement, economics also has failed to identify a generally accepted theory of WTO law.Footnote 135 In this respect Petros Mavroidis has pointed out:

The end result is that economic theory has not, as of yet, come up with a comprehensive explanation for the GATT, as we know it … What we still lack is an internally consistent theory that we can use as guidance to understand and interpret all of the GATT instruments.Footnote 136

This is in addition to the fact that WTO dispute settlement panels and the Appellate Body have been hesitant to engage with economic analysis, treating it for the most part as an “afterthought.”Footnote 137

Third, there are power-based approaches to WTO law anchored in ideas about legitimacy. The usual issue in these accounts is why WTO law is lacking in legitimacy or how the law might buttress its legitimacy.Footnote 138 That analytical frame normally involves careful analyses of panel and Appellate Body decisions with models of legitimating state authority in mind, an exercise which is inherently problematic given that the WTO is not a state and its organs of dispute settlement are meant to settle disputes, not act as courts. As such, power-based accounts fail to track much of the language employed by the organs of dispute settlement in any systematic way or to explain its content in convincing detail.

Consequently, existing approaches to WTO law offer only fragmentary and limited insight into why the law is as it is. They do not offer a wholesale theory in the sense of an integrated “system of ideas.”

Still, the attempt to set out a communitarian theory of WTO law in this book is likely to encounter the objection that the concept of community is too vague a basis for a theory and that WTO law, like the rest of international law, is not traditionally understood as a form of justice.Footnote 139 Furthermore, the principal features which I focus on in order to outline a theory have been traditionally understood as countermeasures promoting compliance, not remedies promoting justice.

Nevertheless, I take the view that whatever objections may be raised to my approach, a wholesale theory is merited if previous attempts at theorization fail to say very much in a systematic manner about the arrangement of WTO law. Such a theory is all the more important and pressing if a persistent criticism of WTO arrangements is that they are unjust.

In short, what I have introduced above and will detail in subsequent chapters is the way that a theory of WTO law is justified because it possesses superior explanatory power. Simply put, the theory offers a richer, more complete explanation for the shape of WTO law than other accounts do.

At the same time, the theory put forward in this book will not be easy to assimilate or appreciate. There is, in addition, much in it that on conventional understandings will appear counterintuitive and even nonsensical.

One universal tenet of thinking about justice is corrective, namely that a successful plaintiff is entitled to full recovery for harm. The theory’s two-fold response to this principle, namely that corrective justice in most instances is constrained by distributive considerations and is about what is “fair,” and beyond that, that justice aims in an overarching sense at transformation, will seem odd and perhaps a little alien.

There are other ways that the theory put forward here will be unsettling as well. In the main, what I set out does not engage with cosmopolitan views of global justice or arguments about the priority of human rights.Footnote 140 To be sure, core human rights are jus cogens, fundamental norms from which no derogation is possible. However, human rights do not operate on the same plane as the rights and obligations in WTO law. As Gabrielle Marceau has pointed out, “there is no perfect coherence between the human rights and WTO systems of law and jurisdiction.”Footnote 141Instead, I posit that the justice of WTO law is a distinctive form of justice between member states and an example of what Steven Ratner has termed the “thin justice” of international law.Footnote 142 The justice I describe here applies among equals – that is, among countries that have made the necessary trade concessions and commitments to be part of a community. Individuals do not do this. Thus, while some readers may be apt to champion the need for WTO arrangements to forward global justice and to call my description of WTO law as justice a masquerade for continuing injustice, the explanation I prefer for this inconsistency is simply that individuals and countries are different. That difference is a reflection of the fact that justice in sovereign terms is not always the same as justice in human terms.Footnote 143

A further objection to the theory will be thus: why focus on “rights and obligations” as the basis for a theory of law? Isn’t the landscape of a legal system much richer and more complex than this? What about general principles of law, declarations, soft law and so forth? Don’t these merit inclusion and discussion in a theory that aims to be general and comprehensive?

In response I suggest that it is appropriate to focus in the first instance on “rights and obligations” as the foundation for a theory because they reflect a basic understanding of what the law involves. They are backgrounded by consideration of the good and justice and become the nucleus around which other concepts build. Focusing on them to begin with is part of the theory’s simplification.Footnote 144

Several years ago Ronald Dworkin observed:

our intellectuals distrust theory perhaps more than any earlier age has. We hear, wherever we turn, the injunctions and disclaimers of the post-modernists, the pre-structuralists, the deconstructionists, the critical legal students, the critical race scholars, and a thousand other battalions of the anti-theory army. Some say that theory is phony, and others that it is oppression, and many that it is both.Footnote 145

Dworkin’s remarks convey the current mood of suspicion and mistrust of theory. A theory can be illuminating and liberating, but it can also be perceived as constraining and “hegemonic.”Footnote 146

A theory like the one put forward here is likely to attract particular criticism. One view may be to regard it as presumptuous – in effect, an attempt to do too much. The conventional approach to legal analysis in WTO law and elsewhere is to search for answers provision-by-provision or case-by-case, offering only slim generalizations. A theory of law that identifies broad idea-complexes and their associated relationships at work in WTO law and projects them as a theory of law in general is likely to upset incrementalist orthodoxies and provoke resistance.

In addition, one effect of the increasing interdependence referred to above is a marked bias in many fields of research toward “participation,” “inclusiveness” and collaborative development.Footnote 147 In light of this preference, nothing – let alone anything as fundamental as a theory of law – is thought to be the product of a single all-encompassing explanation. To the extent that the theory is so, it will be attacked as exclusive and simplistic. Some readers may be tempted to dismiss what is put forward in this book as “Grand Theory.”

Another view is likely to criticize the theory as insufficient, in effect doing too little. The apparent novelty of the theory means that it risks being greeted by all sorts of inflated expectations about the insights it will furnish, as the following forecast of a theory of international law implies:

the theory of international law must take account of law’s functions in regime design and maintenance: establishing rules as focal points that provide an equilibrium in situations requiring coordination, where thereafter no participant has an incentive to defect from the rule, providing transparency and monitoring and some sanctioning in ways that make possible the capture of gains from cooperation without excessive cost; embedding international agreements in national law that can have more direct purchase on relevant actors; drawing systemic linkages among otherwise unrelated issues so as to raise the cost of violation; aiding powerful states to make commitments that others have confidence will be adhered to, by enmeshing them in deeper structure of legal obligation.Footnote 148

The foregoing description may appear overwrought – a sort of “kitchen sink” description of a theory – but it is symptomatic of the unstated demand in contemporary legal scholarship that a theory of law should explain everything.

Here, I think it is important to keep in mind Thomas Kuhn’s observation in 1962 that a theory is useful if it solves “a few problems” recognized as “acute.”Footnote 149 Among these acute problems is the need to supply an explanation for the kind of justice available under the WTO Agreement and for the peculiar shape of its legal system. Evidently, the theory put forward in this book will not resolve every problem or question of WTO law. To that extent, however, it leaves room for the development of other theories.

Footnotes

1 S.v. “Basis,” in Webster’s New World Dictionary, 1564 (Simon & Schuster, New York; 1976), quoted in EC – Sardines, WT/DS231/R, para. 7.110 (29 May 2002).

2 S.v. “Theory,” Shorter Oxford English Dictionary (5th ed.) 3236 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2002).

3 For criticisms of the WTO, see OXFAM International, Rigged Rules and Double Standards (2002), observing:

The problem is not that international trade is inherently opposed to the needs and interests of the poor, but that the rules that govern it are rigged in favour of the rich … Many of the rules of the World Trade Organization … on intellectual property, investment, and services protect the interests of … countries and powerful TNCs, while imposing huge costs on developing countries. This bias raises fundamental questions about the legitimacy of the WTO.

See also Sarah Joseph, Blame It on the WTO (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2011) (offering a critique of the organization and its legal system from a human rights perspective).

4 Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann, “International Economic Theory and International Economic Law: On the Tasks of a Legal Theory of International Economic Order” in R. St. J. Macdonald & D. M. Johnston (eds), The Structure and Process of International Law 234–235 (Martinus Nijhoff, Boston; 1983).

5 Thomas Cottier et al., International Trade Regulation 47 (Cameron May, London; 2005).

6 Anne Peters, “Realizing Utopia as a Scholarly Endeavour” 24:2 Eur. J. Int’l L. 533 at 536 (2013), quoting Gregory Chaitin, “The Limits of Reason” 294:3 Scientific American 74 (2006).

7 “[T]here must come a point where gaps between the explanadum and the explanans cast doubt on the value of the explanation.” Peter Cane, “The Anatomy of Private Law Theory” 25:2 Ox. J. L. S. 203 at 207 (2003).

8 H. Patrick Glenn, Legal Traditions of the World (5th ed.) at 153 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2014).

9 Joseph Raz, Between Authority and Interpretation 17 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2009). In chapter 2, Raz asks the question “can there be a theory of law?” but concludes that he is less than completely confident a workable theory can be identified.

10 The theory’s three-fold structure prioritizing community is dictated by the fact that “[w]e treat community as prior to justice and fairness in the sense that questions of justice and fairness are regarded as questions of what would be fair or just within a particular community.” Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire 208 (Belknap Press, Cambridge, MA; 1986).

11 Paul Seabright has written:

Homo sapiens sapiens is the only animal that engages in elaborate task-sharing – the division of labour as it is sometimes known – between genetically unrelated members of the same species. It is a phenomenon as remarkable and uniquely human as language itself. Most human beings now obtain a large share of the provision of their daily lives from others to whom they are not related by blood or marriage.

(Paul Seabright, The Company of Strangers 1 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ; 2004)).

12 “Flatness” is Thomas Friedman’s metaphor for viewing the world today as a level-playing field in terms of commerce wherein all competitors have an equal opportunity. Thomas L. Friedman, The World Is Flat (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, New York; 2005). See also Vijay Vaitheeswaran, “A Slow Unravelling” 432:9151 The Economist 3 (13 July 2019).

13 David Brooks, “Globalization Is Over. The Global Culture Wars Have Begun” The New York Times (8 Apr. 2022) Brooks notes how in the immediate aftermath of the Cold War:

[i]t seemed as if there would be a global convergence around a set of universal values – freedom, equality, personal dignity, pluralism, human rights. … The world is not converging anymore; it’s diverging. The process of globalization has slowed and, in some cases, even kicked into reverse … Sure, globalization as flows of trade will continue. But globalization as the driving logic of world affairs – that seems to be over.

For a more equivocal account, see Jeanna Smialek & Ana Swanson, “The Era of Cheap and Plenty May Be Ending” The New York Times (3 May 2022) (noting how if supply chain turmoil and geopolitical conflicts result in a reversal or reconfiguration of global production a decades-long decline in the prices of many goods could come to an end).

14 United States – Civil Aircraft (Second Complaint), WT/DS353/R, appendix VII.F.1, para. 25 (31 Mar. 2011). For similar observations of the Boeing 787 as emblematic of interdependence, see Michele Ruta & Mika Saito, “Chained Value” Finance & Development 52 (Mar. 2014).

15 United States – Civil Aircraft (Second Complaint), WT/DS353/R, appendix VII.F.1, para. 24 (31 Mar. 2011). WTO Director-General Pascal Lamy has described a similar phenomenon in the global textiles value chain. See “What Cannot Be Counted Does Not Count” (speech by WTO Director-General Pascal Lamy to the Economic Development Foundation (IKV) and the Economic Policy Research Foundation of Turkey (TEPAV), Istanbul, 14 Mar. 2013).

16 In EC – Computer Equipment, WT/DS62/AB/R, para. 82 (5 June 1998) the Appellate Body observed that “the security and predictability of ‘the reciprocal and mutually advantageous arrangements directed to the substantial reduction of tariffs and other barriers to trade’ is an object and purpose of the WTO Agreement, generally, as well as of the GATT 1994.” This reference has been cited in numerous other decisions: see EC – Chicken Cuts, WT/DS269/AB/R, para. 243 (12 Sept. 2005); EC – Bananas III, WT/DS27AB/RW2/ECU, para. 433 (26 Nov. 2008). In China – Automobile Parts the panel referred to it as the “main purpose” of the WTO Agreement: see China – Automobile Parts, WT/DS339, 340, 342/R para. 7.460 (18 July 2008) [emphasis added].

17 Aristotle posited that all human actions can be traced to some good. “Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things aim.” Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics (2nd ed.) 1094a1 (Terence Irwin, trans., 1999).

18 Moya Chin, “What Are Global Public Goods?” 58:4 Finance & Development 62 (Dec. 2021).

20 Herbert L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (2nd ed.) 160 (Oxford University Press, London; 2006).

21 Sanne Taekema observes that the combination of equality and fairness at the core of the concept of justice is also forwarded by Neil MacCormick, Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory 73 (Clarendon Press, Oxford; 1978). Fairness as the core of justice is proposed by David Miller, Principles of Social Justice (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA; 1976). Justice as equal treatment can also be found in Gustav Radbruch, Legal Philosophy 278 (Quelle & Meyer, Leipzig; 1932), Herbert L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law 159 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 1994), James Harris, Property and Justice 171 (Clarendon Press, Oxford; 1996), and Aristotle in the Nicomachean Ethics. See Sanne Taekema, The Concept of Ideals in Legal Theory 192 n. 31 (Kluwer Law International, The Hague; 2003).

22 “Patience, Fairness and the Human Condition” 385:8549 The Economist 67 (6 Oct. 2007); Keith Jensen et al., “Chimpanzees Are Rational Maximizers in an Ultimatum Game” 318 Science 107 (2007).

23 David Schmidtz, Elements of Justice 186 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; 2006).

24 Thus, Ronald Dworkin has observed:

Some philosophers deny the possibility of any fundamental conflict between justice and fairness because they believe that one of these virtues in the end derives from the other. Some say that justice has no meaning apart from fairness, that in politics, as in roulette, whatever happens through fair procedures is just. That is the extreme of the idea called justice as fairness. Others think that the only test of fairness in politics is the test of result, that no procedure is fair unless it is likely to produce political decisions that meet some independent test of justice. That is the opposite extreme, of fairness as justice. Most political philosophers – and I think most people – take the intermediate view that fairness and justice are to some degree independent of each other, so that fair institutions sometimes produce unjust decisions and unfair institutions just ones.

(Dworkin, Law’s Empire (177)

Herbert Hart observed:

The distinctive features of justice and their special connection with law begin to emerge if it is observed that most of the criticisms made in terms of just and unjust could almost equally well be conveyed by the words “fair” and “unfair.” Fairness is plainly not coextensive with morality in general; references to it are mainly relevant in two situations in social life. One is when we are concerned not with a single individual’s conduct but with the way in which classes of individuals are treated, when some burden or benefit falls to be distributed among them. Hence what is typically fair or unfair is a “share.” The second situation is when some injury has been done and compensation or redress is claimed.

(Herbert Hart, The Concept of Law 158 (1994))

25 Anthropologists suggest cognitive limits to the number of individuals that it is possible to maintain stable social relationships with. One of these measures, “Dunbar’s Number,” proposes that the number lies in the vicinity of 150. Numbers larger than this generally require more restrictive rules, laws, and enforced norms to maintain a stable, cohesive group. See David Schiefer & Jolanda van der Noll, “The Essentials of Social Cohesion: A Literature Review” 132 Soc. Indic. Res. 579 (2017) (positing that “(in)equality, quality of life, and shared values represent antecedents and consequences of social cohesion, instead of constitutive elements” and that “a cohesive society is characterized by close social relations, pronounced emotional connectedness to the social entity, and a strong orientation toward the common good.” In particular, orientation toward the common good is defined as “feelings of responsibility for the common good … [and] acceptance of and compliance to the social order and social rules versus anomy.”).

26 Amartya Sen has observed that “every normative theory of social arrangement that has [at all] stood the test of time seems to demand equality of something – something that is regarded as particularly important in that theory.” Amartya Sen, Inequality Reexamined 13 (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA; 1995).

27 “By definition,” Maurice Cranston says, “a liberal is a man who believes in liberty.” Maurice Cranston, “Liberalism” in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Paul Edwards (ed.), 458–461 (1967). See also Shane Courtland & David Schmidtz, s.v. “Liberalism” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (22 Feb. 2022).

28 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (rev’d. ed.) 53 (Belknap Press, Cambridge, MA; 1999).

29 Instead, communitarians argue that justice in the real world is far from consistent with either principle but rather depends on a range of factors. “Standards of justice must be found in forms of life and traditions of particular societies and hence can vary from context to context.” “Communitarianism” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (first published Thursday 4 Oct. 2001; substantive revision Friday 15 May 2020).

32 I thank Fiona Smith for suggesting use of this term in relation to the expression of justice within a particular community.

33 “In reality, this measure is need, which holds everything together; for if people needed nothing, or needed things to different extents, there would be either no exchange or not the same exchange.” Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 1133a28–30; also “Now clearly need holds [a community] together as a single unit, since people with no need of each other, both of them and either one, do not exchange, as they exchange whenever another requires what one has oneself, such as wine, when they allow the export of corn. This, then, must be equalized.” Footnote Ibid.1133b7–11.

34 Footnote Ibid. at 1131a25–29.

35 Outlawry and renegade behavior as emblematic of distinctive communities have populated the folklore of many traditions, Famous depictions of prison “communities” include Arthur Koestler’s Darkness at Noon (The MacMillan Company, New York; 1941) and Alexander Solzhenitsyn’s One Day in the Life of Ivan Denisovitch (Dramatic Publishing Company, Chicago; 1963).

36 For instance, in the Anglo-American common law, recovery for breach of contract is linked to protection of an “expectation interest,” which is said to give the injured party the “benefit of the bargain.” Restatement (Second) of the Law – Contracts, s. 344. This is not, however, the only interest protected:

The promisee may have changed his position in reliance on the contract by, for example, incurring expenses in preparing to perform, in performing, or in foregoing opportunities to make other contracts. In that case, the court may recognize a claim based on his reliance rather than on his expectation … The interest protected in this way is called “reliance interest.” Although it may be equal to the expectation interest, it is ordinarily smaller because it does not include the injured party’s lost profit.

(Footnote Ibid. [emphasis added])

The Restatement goes on to note that:

In some situations a court will recognize yet a third interest and grant relief to prevent unjust enrichment. This may be done if a party has not only changed his own position in reliance on the contract but has also conferred a benefit on the other party by, for example, making a part payment or furnishing services under the contract. The court may then require the other party to disgorge the benefit that he has received.

This third interest is referred to as the “restitution interest.” The Restatement observes that “[a]lthough it may be equal to the expectation or reliance interest, it is ordinarily smaller because it includes neither the injured party’s lost profit nor that part of his expenditures in reliance that resulted in no benefit to the other party.” Footnote Ibid. [emphasis added]. The Restatement adds that “in situations in which a court grants such relief as justice requires, the relief may not correspond precisely to any of these interests.”

37 This is not the first time this reconceptualization has been put forward. Izhak Englard reveals how outlines of this same reconceptualization of Aristotle’s work – the core of which constitutes an inversion of values underlying the traditional distinction and their eventual reconciliation – was prefigured in a fragmentary way by a number of renaissance and humanist scholars, including the French jurist and political philosopher Jean Bodin, the German scholastic and theologian Valentin Wudrian and the Italian philosopher and historian Giambattista Vico, Their views are surveyed in Izhak Englard, Corrective and Distributive Justice: From Aristotle to Modern Times (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2009). For references to Bodin see Footnote ibid., pp. 131–133, Wudrian see pp. 133–135, Vico see pp. 156–158.

38 This is evident in the shape of rules concerning court costs. Traditionally, the “English Rule” provides that the party who loses in court pays the other party’s legal costs. The English Rule contrasts with the “American Rule” under which each party is generally responsible for paying its own legal fees. In either case, however, recovery is not 100 percent. See Christopher Hodges, “Settlement and its pitfalls in England and Wales” in Christopher Hodges & Astrid Stadler, Resolving Mass Disputes 106 (Edward Elgar, Cheltenham: 2013); Mark Anderson, “Settlement or Roll the Dice?” 28:1 Litigation 37 (Fall 2001).

39 Hanoch Dagan, “The Distributive Foundation of Corrective Justice” 98 Mich. L. Rev. 138 at 140 (1999) (“the legal choice among … pecuniary remedies is not a matter of legal technicality, but rather requires a choice among varying conceptions of the plaintiff’s entitlement. This choice, in its turn, is a normative choice that implicates the prevailing background ethos of the society at issue and is deeply influenced by the society’s complex conceptions of self and of community.”)

40 Law Commission of Canada, “From Restorative Justice to Transformative Justice: Discussion Paper,” Law Commission of Canada Catalogue No. JL2–6/1999 (1999).

41 EC – Computer Equipment, WT/DS62/AB/R, para. 82 (5 June 1998).

42 [1994] I.C.J. Reports 112 at 121.

43 Footnote Ibid., para. 25 [emphasis added]. Similarly, Robert Jennings and Arthur Watts have concluded “that the decisive factor is still whether the instrument is intended to create international legal rights and obligations between the parties” Robert Jennings & Arthur Watts, Oppenheim’s International Law (9th ed.) 1202 (Longman, Harlow; 1996) [emphasis added].

44 Jutta Brunnée & Stephen Toope, “International Law and Constructivism: Elements of an Interactional Theory of International Law” 39 Colum. J. Transnat’l L. 19 at 31 (2000).

45 The idea of a correspondence between rights and obligations was recognized by early philosophers but developed most insightfully by Wesley Hohfeld, who postulated that there are rights and associated privileges, powers and immunities, and that there are also correspondent obligations and associated no-rights, liabilities and disabilities. When integrated, these form correlative pairs of legal relationships in the form of right-obligation, privilege-no right, power-liability and immunity-disability. See Wesley Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning 36 (1919, rev’d. ed., Lawbook Exchange Ltd., Clark, NJ; 2010). Onora O’Neill has warned about the illusory nature of “manifesto rights,” that is, rights for which there are no associated obligations:

The most questionable effect of putting rights first is that those rights for which no allocation of obligations has been institutionalized may not be taken seriously. When obligations are unallocated it is indeed right that they should be met, but nobody can have an effective right – an enforceable, claimable or waivable right – to their being met. Such abstract rights are not effective entitlements. If the claimants of supposed “rights” to food or development cannot find where to lodge their claims, these are “empty “manifesto” rights.”

(Onora O’Neill, Bounds of Justice 126 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; 2000))

46 Japan – Taxes on Alcoholic Beverages, WT/DS8/AB/R, p. 14 (4 Oct 1996) [emphasis added]. Jeffrey Waincymer notes that:

[s]cholars have sought to distinguish between a contractarian versus constitutional approach to the GATT/WTO system. Contract interpretation tends to look at the intent of the parties at the time of the signing of the agreement. Constitutional lawyers vary their approach. Some would argue that a constitutional document must also be interpreted in its historical context. Others argue that it must be updated for modern times.

(Jeffrey Waincymer, WTO Litigation 400–401 (Cameron May, London; 2002))

47 Generally speaking, countries have found a contractual conception of the treaty appealing and have referred to it on a number of occasions. See, for example, statement by Brazil in EC – Poultry, WT/DS69/AB/R, para. 15 (13 July 1998) (describing the WTO Agreement as “an international treaty laying down contractual obligations and not erga omnes obligations.”); Argentina in WT/DSB/M/42, p. 14 (13 Feb. 1998) (referring to SPS obligations as “contractual international obligations”); China in WT/GC/M/173, para. 6.38 (26 July 2018) (“The WTO Agreement is a set of contracts achieved through negotiations. Within the scope of those contracts, Members abide by the conditions set forth in the contracts. Beyond the scope of those contracts, Members have their own policy space.”). For commentators supportive of this view, see Joost Pauwelyn, “A Typology of Multilateral Treaty Obligations” 14:5 E.J.I.L. 907 (2003) (“Put differently, the values, aspirations and priorities of close to 150 WTO Members remain far too diverse for WTO norms to be streamlined into constitutional-type obligations” Footnote Ibid. at 938). Similarly, Petros Mavroidis has referred to the WTO Agreement as an “incomplete contract.” In his view negotiators were “well aware that various [governmental] policies … might have an impact on trade, and that is why they decided to discipline the exercise of these policies. They did not, however, proceed to enumerate every one of them, nor did they provide specific disciplines for each.” Petros Mavroidis, The General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade: A Commentary 127 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2005).

48 “The constitution sets the pattern for the legal order of the international organization. Further rules develop from the operation of its organs. The power of these organs to take decisions stems from the constitution.” Henry Schermers & Niels Blokker, International Institutional Law (6th ed.) 722 (Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Leiden; 2018). See also WTO Agreement Art. 1 (“The World Trade Organization … is hereby established.”).

49 Gail Evans, Lawmaking under the Trade Constitution 44 (Kluwer Law International, The Hague; 1999). For a range of constitutional views, see John Jackson, The World Trade Organization (Royal Institute of International Affairs, London; 1998); Deborah Cass, The Constitutionalization of the World Trade Organization (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2005). Also Peter Gerhart, “Two Constitutional Visions of the World Trade Organization” 24 U. Pa. J. Int’l Econ. L. 1 (2003).

50 “The validity of each rule [of an international organization] will depend on the constitution [of the organization], the basis of the legal order.” Schermers & Blokker, International Institutional Law 722.

51 See Turkey – Textiles, WT/DS34/R (31 May 1999), at para. 9.178 (“In our view, however, a bilateral agreement between two Members … does not alter the legal nature of the measures at issue or the applicability of the relevant GATT/WTO provisions”); EC – Bananas III, WT/DS27/AB/R (9 Sept. 1997), at paras. 164–170 (the Appellate Body, in examining the Lomé Convention, concluded that unless explicitly authorized by a waiver, provisions of the Convention could not alter rights and obligations of WTO members).

52 See WTO Art. III:2 (contemplating change through future negotiation). The theme of change has also been addressed in WTO dispute settlement. Thus, in Japan – Alcoholic Beverages the Appellate Body observed, “WTO rules are not so rigid or so inflexible as not to leave room for reasoned judgements in confronting the endless and ever-changing ebb and flow of real facts in real cases in the real world.” WT/DS8/AB/R, p. 31 (4 Oct. 1996).

53 J. S. Covington, Jr., The Structure of Legal Argument and Proof 7–8 (John Marshall Pub. Co., Houston, TX; 1993).

54 Footnote Ibid., p. 8.

55 See U.S. – Taxes on Petroleum, 34th B.I.S.D. Supp. 156–157, para. 5.1.7 (17 June 1987).

56 For instance, in Japan – Leather, B.I.S.D. 31st Supp. 94 (15–16 May 1984) “the panel wished to stress that the existence of a quantitative restriction should be presumed to cause nullification or impairment not only because of the effect it had on the volume of trade but also for other reasons e.g., it would lead to increased transaction costs and would create uncertainties which would affect investment plans.” Footnote Ibid., paras. 55–56.

57 “A constitution is framed for ages to come, and is designed to approach immortality as nearly as human institutions can approach it.” Cohens v. Virginia, 19 U.S. (6 Wheaton) 264 at 387 (1821) (Marshall C. J.); “A constitution … is drafted with an eye to the future. Its function is to provide a continuing framework for the legitimate exercise of governmental power …” Hunter v. Southam [1984] 2 S.C.R. 145 at 155 (Dickson J.).

58 Randy Barnett, “A Consent Theory of Contract” 86:2 Columbia L. Rev. 269 at 272 (1986) (“Will theories depend for their moral force upon the notion that contractual duties are binding because they are freely assumed by those who are required to discharge them.”)

59 Philip Allott, The Health of Nations 47 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; 2002) (noting how according to the nineteenth century English legal theorist John Austin “[l]aw … was to be seen as a species of command … [and] [t[he idea-complex of sovereignty, command, sanction and obedience was all the lawyer needed to know about the theory of law.”).

60 On the traditional timeless perspective sought in analytic jurisprudence see Dan Priel, “Analytic Jurisprudence in Time” in Thomas Bustamante & Thiago Lopes Decat (eds), Philosophy of Law as an Integral Part of Philosophy 213 (Hart, Oxford; 2020).

61 Alan Brudner & Jennifer Nadler, The Unity of the Common Law (2nd ed.) 2 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2013).

62 Philip Allott has described the transformation of the international community as follows: “the self-transformation of international society might represent it as a process of processes, a set of highlight charged psychic force-fields, overlapping and interacting in a multiple dialectic of change, negating and re-enforcing and surpassing each other, a revolution of declining expectations within a revolution of rising expectations.” Philip Allott, Eunomia xxv (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 1990).

63 Covington, The Structure of Legal Argument and Proof 3.

65 Philip Allott has observed, “[t]he limits of a right amount to a peripheral duty … not to exceed those limits … [t]he limits of a duty amount to a peripheral right … not to be required to go beyond those limits.” Allott, Eunomia 162.

66 The same oscillation is observed in the law of international organizations generally. Jan Klabbers has noted, for instance, that “[T]his constant oscillation between the organisation and its members has given rise to a rather volatile set of legal rules and principles governing international organisations.” Jan Klabbers, “The Changing Image of International Organizations” in Jean-Marc Coicaud & Veijo Heiskanen (eds), The Legitimacy of International Organizations 227 (United Nations University Press, Tokyo; 2001).

67 A nested opposition “involve[s] a relation of dependence, similarity or containment between … opposed concepts.” Jack Balkin, “Nested Oppositions” 99 Yale L.J. 1669 at 1671 (1990). Nesting also calls upon deconstructionist ideas of “différance” and “trace.” “Différance” was the term of art used by Jacques Derrida to describe the mutual dependence and differentiation of concepts. “Trace” is the retention of absent concepts that remain present in the understanding of other concepts. Balkin, Footnote ibid. at 1676. Balkin also notes that each opposition is traceable to a larger “idea complex” exhibiting its own particular concern and rationality. Balkin terms this a “countervision which is opposed to the dominant vision enforced by the law.” He also notes that “it makes more sense to emphasize that the countervision one proposes is always immanent in the vision one is critiquing.” Footnote Ibid. at 1688.

68 For an attempt to define the criteria of a system, see Donella Meadows, Thinking in Systems (Chelsea Green Publishing, White River Junction, VT; 2008). Indications of these same criteria are discernible in WTO law. In China – Electronic Payment Services, for instance, the panel put forward the view that a “system [is] composed of several elements. Those elements could be considered, individually, as services in their own right.” Footnote Ibid. at para. 7.58. The United States added that “the various elements of the system are integrated and necessary to facilitate a payment card transaction and, as such, constitute a single service. In our view, all elements of the system, together, are necessary for the payment card to materialize. None of the elements of the “system”, individually, would be sufficient to process a payment card transaction. Each of them must be integrated into a whole.” Footnote Ibid. at para. 7.59:

(China – Electronic Payment Services, WT/DS413/R, (16 July 2012) [emphasis added]).

69 John Maxcy Zane, The Story of Law (2nd ed.) 104 (Liberty Fund, Indianapolis, IN; 1927, reprint. 1998). See also Hurtado v. California, 110 U.S. 516 at 535 (1884) (“Law is something more than mere will exerted as an act of power.”). Stephen Smith has observed that today there is “general agreement that a central feature, if not the central feature, of [law’s] self-understanding is law’s claim to authority – the claim or belief that law is morally justified.” Stephen Smith, Contract Theory 15 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2003). Moreover, “a good theory of law ought to show that the law is, in fact, morally justified.” Footnote Ibid., p. 17 [emphasis in original].

70 Brazil – Dessicated Coconut, WT/DS22/AB/R, pp. 11–12 (21 Feb. 1997) [emphasis added].

71 Footnote Ibid., p. 17, quoting Brazil – Dessicated Coconut, WT/DS22/R, para. 246 (17 Oct. 1996).

72 U.S. – Oil Country Tubular Goods Sunset Reviews, WT/DS268/RW, para. 7.129 (30 Nov. 2006).

73 Brazil – Dessicated Coconut, WT/DS22/AB/R, p. 11 (21 Feb. 1997) [emphasis added].

74 Andrei Marmor & Alexander Sarch, “The Nature of Law” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (22 Aug. 2019) (“In the course of the last few centuries, two main rival philosophical traditions have emerged about the nature of legality. The older one, dating back to late medieval Christian scholarship, is called the natural law tradition. Since the early 19th century, natural law theories have been fiercely challenged by the legal positivism tradition.”)

Reduced to its simplest, the distinction between [natural law and positivism] is that natural law theories argue that the status of law depends not simply on the fact that it has been laid down in whatever way or ways are recognised by the legal system of which it is part, but also on some additional factor or factors external to that system. Positivist theories, on the other hand, argue that the status of law attaches to anything which has been laid down (or posited) as law in whatever way or ways is or are recognised by the legal system in question.

(Ian McLeod, Legal Theory 18–19 (Palgrave MacMillan, Basingstoke; 2005) [emphasis in original])

76 Bruno Simma & Andrea Paulus, “The ‘International Community’: Facing the Challenge of Globalization” 9 E.J.I.L. 266 at 269 (1998).

79 Footnote Ibid. at 270.

83 Footnote Ibid. at 271.

85 US – FSC, WT/DS108/AB/R, para. 166 (24 Feb. 2000).

86 See, for example, Chad Bown, Self-Enforcing Trade: Developing Countries and WTO Dispute Settlement (Brookings Institution Press, Washington, DC; 2009).

87 Schermers & Blokker, International Institutional Law 764 (describing a forum organization as “a platform for discussion amongst members, for coordination of policies, and for exchange of views on items of common interest” as opposed to the enforcement of binding rules).

88 Dennis Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (2nd ed.) 2 (Wiley Blackwell, Malden, MA; 2010).

89 John Austin was a noted English legal theorist who influenced Anglo-American law with his analytical approach to jurisprudence and his theory of legal positivism in his major work, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (J. Murray, London; 1832). Austin’s particular theory of law is often called the “command theory of law” because the concept of command lies at its core, resting on three-fold concepts of sovereignty, command, and sanction.

90 Hart’s book The Concept of Law (1994) presents his theory of legal positivism within the framework of analytic philosophy. In The Concept of Law Hart made a distinction between primary and secondary legal rules, where a primary rule governs conduct and a secondary rule allows the creation, alteration or extinction of primary rules.

91 A basic norm (grundnorm) is a concept in Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law (rev’d. ed.) (The Lawbook Exchange, Clark, NJ; 2005). Kelsen used this term to denote the basic norm, order or rule that forms the underlying basis for a legal system. His theory is based on a need to find a point of origin for all law, from which basic law and the constitution can gain their legitimacy.

92 Joseph Raz maintains that legal commands are exclusionary reasons for action and for the “service conception” of authority, according to which those subject to an authority “can benefit by its decisions only if they can establish their existence and content in ways which do not depend on raising the very same issues which the authority is there to settle.” This, in turn, supports Raz’s argument for legal positivism, in particular “the sources thesis,” or “the idea that an adequate test for the existence and content of law must be based only on social facts, and not on moral arguments.” Massimo Renzo & Leslie Green, “Legal Obligation and Authority” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (30 June 2022).

93 Dworkin’s book Law’s Empire posited the hypothetical scenario in which judges interpret the law in terms of consistent moral principles, especially justice and fairness.

94 Paul Rubin, “Why Is the Common Law Efficient?” 6 J. Legal Studies 51 (1977); George Priest, “The Common Law Process and the Selection of Efficient Rules” 6 J. Legal Studies 65 (1977); John Goodman, “An Economic Theory of the Evolution of the Common Law” 7 J. Legal Studies 393 (1978); R. Peter Terrebonne, “A Strictly Evolutionary Model of Common Law” 10 J. Legal Studies 397 (1981).

95 Allen Buchanan & David Golove, “Philosophy of International Law” in Jules Coleman et al., The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (Oxford University Press, Oxford; Jan. 2004) (noting “the traditional view according to which state consent is both necessary and sufficient for the legitimacy of norms within the international legal system.” Footnote Ibid. at 50).

96 David Bederman, The Spirit of International Law 17 (University of Georgia Press, Athens, GA; 2002) (“the naturalist-positivist dualism has been regarded as the crucial dialectic of international law”).

97 Martti Koskenniemi, “International Legal Theory and Doctrine” in Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law, para. 21 (2005).

98 Thus, Stephen Waddams has observed that “Often a legal obligation has been derived not from a single concept but from the interaction of two or more concepts in such a way as to preclude the allocation of the legal issue to a single category.” Stephen Waddams, Dimensions of Private Law 1 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; 2003). See also José Alvarez, The Public International Law Regime Governing International Investment 232 (Hague Academy of International Law, The Hague; 2011) (noting that “strict positivism” does not explain the shape of international investment law).

99 On tendencies in law, see Catherine Valcke, “Contractual Interpretation at Common Law and Civil Law” in Jason Neyers (ed.), Exploring Contract Law 77 at 112 (Hart Publishing, Oxford; 2008).

100 I would like to thank Maureen Irish for suggesting the use of this phrase.

101 See Meinhard Hilf & Tim René Salomon, “Running in Circles: Regionalism in World Trade and How It Will Lead Back to Multilateralism” in Ulrich Fastenrath et al. (eds), From Bilateralism to Community Interest: Essays in Honour of Bruno Simma 257 at 267 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2011) (“after being subject to [fragmentation] for some time, States will consequently start to look for a solution in order to somehow limit the variety of dispute settlement systems to its lowest common denominator.”); Alan Wolff, “WTO 2025: Getting Back to the Negotiating Table” 22-7 Peterson Institute for International Economics Briefing Paper 10 (May 2022) (“Fragmentation of the trading system is not a sustainable long-term trend. There will be a return to multilateralism.”). For broader accounts of this same oscillatory movement between multilateralism and unilateralism detected in international law, see Matthew Craven, “Unity, Diversity and the Fragmentation of International Law” XIV Finnish Yearbook I.L. 3 at 12 (2003) (referring to the fact that “progressive systematization [of international law] appears in tension with that of fragmentation … A system is a system by reason of its ability to unify a diversity of experience – it must be simultaneously homogenous and heterogenous, unified but multipolar.”).

102 Hans Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State 13 (Transaction Publishers, New Brunswick, NJ; 2008).

103 See Ann Marie Clark et al., “The Sovereign Limits of Global Civil Society” 51:1 World Politics 1 (1998) (arguing that the concept of global civil society sets a more demanding standard for the evaluation of transnational political processes than has been applied in prior accounts of transnational activity); Robert O’Brien et al., Contesting Global Governance (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press; 2000) (arguing that there is a transformation in the nature of global economic governance as the result of the multilateral economic institution-global society movement encounter, pluralizing governance structures).

104 Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State 13.

105 “[T]wo features of international law most commonly invoked by those who call into question its legal character are the absence of a centralized system of enforcement and the role of state consent in the formation of rules of international law.” See John Tasioulas & Guglielmo Vendirame, “Philosophy of International Law” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (12 May 2022). Herbert Hart maintained that:

the absence of an international legislature, courts with compulsory jurisdiction, and centrally organized sanctions have inspired misgivings … the absence of these institutions means that the rules for states resemble that form of social structure, consisting of primary rules of obligation … [However] international law not only lacks the secondary rules of change and adjudication which provide for legislature and courts, but also a unifying rule of recognition specifying “sources” of law and providing general criteria for the identification of its rules.

(Hart, The Concept of Law 214 (1994))

106 Pavlos Eleftheriadis differs: “Although the distinction between distributive and corrective justice is old and well understood, it has not, for the most part, been deployed in the debates concerning international justice. It appears that when scholars refer to justice in the international context, they only have in mind distributive claims. If distributive claims cannot be justified, then justice is irrelevant.” Pavlos Eleftheriadis, “Corrective Justice among States” 2 Jus Cogens 7 at 14 (2020). The concern with distributive justice in international affairs is often traced to the work of John Rawls, Michael Blake & Taylor Smith, “International Distributive Justice” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (4 May 2020) (noting that “international justice has been a central research topic only in recent years” and that “modern dialogue about international distributive justice can be largely traced to the initial publication of Rawls’s A Theory of Justice.”).

107 “Taking Rawls at his word, his principles of justice apply to the basic structure [of society]; they do not apply to transactions within that structure, which may be subject to other principles of justice.” Steven Walt, “Eliminating Corrective Justice” 92:7 Virginia. L. Rev. 1311 at 1316 (2006).

108 Steven Heyman, “Aristotle on Political Justice” 77 Iowa L. Rev. 851 at 856 (1992) (“the law that governs corrective justice is not purely ‘private law’, a law that focuses solely on the private interests of the parties. Instead, the law of corrective justice is inherently political, in the sense that it is directed toward the good of the community”); see also Dagan, “The Distributive Foundation of Corrective Justice,” (“the legal choice among … pecuniary remedies is not a matter of legal technicality, but rather requires a choice among varying conceptions of the plaintiff’s entitlement. This choice, in its turn, is a normative choice that implicates the prevailing background ethos of the society at issue and is deeply influenced by the society’s complex conceptions of self and of community.”); Aditi Bagchi, “Distributive Injustice and Private Law” 130 Hastings L.J. 105 (2008) (maintaining that “a background of distributive injustice properly informs our understanding of what constitutes responsible conduct, and thus, the scope of otherwise secure legal entitlements.” Footnote Ibid. at 108).

109 Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 80 (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA; 1995) (“As an autonomous form of justice, corrective justice operates on entitlements without addressing the justice of the underlying distribution.”); Peter Benson, “The Basis of Corrective Justice and Its Relation to Distributive Justice” 77 Iowa L. Rev. 515 at 607 (1992) (“The justification of abstract right and of its principles of acquisition does not depend in the least on the prior satisfaction of any distributive requirements of background justice.”); Stephen Perry, “On the Relationship between Corrective and Distributive Justice” in Jeremy Horder (ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence: Fourth Series 237 at 247 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2000) (“[Corrective justice is] an independent moral principle that operates within the context of distributive justice, but not as part of it.”).

110 “The conceptual distinction between distributive and corrective justice seems clear, but their normative relationship is more difficult to pin down.” David Miller, “Justice” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (6 Aug. 2021).

111 Perry, “On the Relationship between Corrective and Distributive Justice” 247 (“if we accept the premise that distributive justice is best understood dynamically rather than statically, corrective justice should be understood as independent moral principle that operates within the context of distributive justice, but not as part of it.”). Walt, “Eliminating Corrective Justice” 1317 (“[c]orrective justice’s duty of repair is static; it requires compensation for a wrongful harm that has occurred. Distributive justice is dynamic; it is concerned with the distribution of resources and liberties over the entire life of individuals, not at any point within their lives.”).

112 It might be argued that Rawls did account for the wider value of fairness in positing the “maximin” as the rational choice rule under conditions of uncertainty. The concept of maximin:

directs that we play it as safe as possible by choosing the alternative whose worst outcome leaves us better off than the worst outcome of all other alternatives.

(Samuel Freeman, “Original Position” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (3 Apr. 2019))

I thank Petros Mavroidis for this insight.

113 John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA; 1999).

114 For an interpretation of Rawls as a communitarian, see Roberto Alejandro, “Rawls’s Communitariansm” 23:1 Can. J. Phil. 75 (1993). For an attempt to posit a principle of private responsibility complementary to Rawlsian ideas, see Arthur Ripstein, “The Division of Responsibility and the Law of Tort” 72 Fordham L. Rev. 1811 (2004).

115 In these understandings, time is usually understood statically through a series of political regimes, historical figures or particular thinkers or schools of thought, taken to be representative of law at one particular time. See, for instance, Martti Koskenniemi, The Gentle Civilizer of Nations (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; 2001). See however Priel, “Analytic Jurisprudence in Time” 213 (noting the dominant view within analytic jurisprudence which sees it as aiming to provide an account of the nature of law existing beyond time and place and how this is insufficiently appreciated in the discipline).

116 “[I]f from a moral point of view cooperation always entails some kind of effacing of one’s own interests in deference to others or the group, then from a cognitive point of view, cooperative thinking always entails some kind of effacing of one’s own perspective in deference to the more ‘objective’ perspective of others or the group.” Michael Tomasello, A Natural History of Human Thinking 122 (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA; 2014).

117 Carol Ezzell, “Clocking Cultures” in A Matter of Time 27 Scientific American (Special Edition) 48 (Summer 2018) (“the way various cultures keep time reflects their priorities and even the way they view the world”). See also generally Robert Levine, A Geography of Time (Basic Books, New York; 1998).

118 Gabrielle Marceau has observed how much interpretation under international and WTO law according to the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, 8 I.L.M. 679 (1969), is subtly diachronic because of regular reliance on ever-updated dictionary definitions and reference to a wider context that is constantly changing. Gabrielle Marceau, “Evolutive Interpretation by the WTO Adjudicator” 12:4 J.I.E.L. 791 (2018).

119 John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights 9–15 (Oxford University Press, New York; 1980).

120 In 1917 Wesley Hohfeld put forward his well-known arrangement of jural opposites and correlatives as a means of understanding interests in property. Wesley Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning 36 (1919, rev’d. ed., Lawbook Exchange, Clark, NJ; 2010).

121 See Dworkin, Law’s Empire 152 (“Legal rights and duties are a familiar part of our legal scene.”). William Eskridge has pointed to a need for a balance between these concepts, “Individual rights, without more, are a thin way to express or normalize the relationship of the individual to the community. … [the] assumption of responsibility is what separates the full member of the community from the child or the outsider. This conception provides a richer understanding of the relationship between the individual and the community than does liberal theory.” William Eskridge, “The Relationship between Obligations and Rights of Citizens” 69 Fordham L. Rev. 1721 at 1722 (2001).

122 A/RES/375 (6 Dec. 1949).

123 The phrase “rights and obligations” is also found in Art. 14 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, 999 U.N.T.S. 171 (1966) in a way that infers it to be portmanteau term for the totality of legal relations between individuals in domestic legal systems (“All persons shall be equal before the courts and tribunals. In the determination of any criminal charge against him, or of his rights and obligations in a suit at law, everyone shall be entitled to a fair and public hearing by a competent, independent and impartial tribunal established by law.”) The nineteenth-century Chinese constitutional scholar Liang Qichao observed “Defining the rights and obligations of the subjects is an essential part of the constitutions of various countries.” Liang Qichao: Anthology of Works on Law by Liang Qichao (Fan Zhongxin, ed.), p. 9 (1989) [Hein – World Constitutions Illustrated].

124 Julie Maybee, “Hegel’s Dialectics” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fri, 2 Oct. 2020).

125 Roger Martin, The Opposable Mind 15 (Harvard Business School Press, Cambridge, MA; 2007).

126 The “messiness” of the problem is important to ensuring that no features are edited out that “are necessary to the completion of the problem as a whole.” Footnote Ibid., p. 41.

127 Footnote Ibid., p. 42.

128 Footnote Ibid., p. 43.

131 E. Donald Elliott, “Law and Biology: The New Synthesis” 41 St. Louis U. L.J. 595 at 600 (1997).

132 Michael Sinclair, “Evolution in Law” 71 U. Det. Mercy L. Rev. 31 at 32 (1993) (“It is quite commonplace to talk of law as evolving.”). But see Allan Hutchinson, Evolution and the Common Law (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; 2005) (noting that evolution is simply “about change historical change, not normative advancement.” Footnote Ibid. at 34).

133 In general, disputes in the WTO involve allegations that a country has violated an agreement or broken a commitment. But in some situations a government can commence a dispute under WTO dispute settlement even when an agreement has not been violated. This option is termed a “nonviolation complaint.” Non-violation is made out when a government can show that it has been deprived on an expected benefit arising from GATT by action taken by another country outside the treaty. if one government can show that it has been deprived of an expected benefit because of another government’s action, or because of any other situation that exists. See GATT Art. XXIII:1(b).

134 See, for example, Asif Qureshi, Interpreting WTO Agreements (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; 2006); Isabelle Van Damme, Treaty Interpretation by the WTO Appellate Body (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2009).

135 For a review of economic thinking in relation to the WTO Agreement, see Kyle Bagwell & Robert Staiger, The WTO: Theory and Practice, WTO Staff Working Paper ERSD-2009-11 (11 Nov. 2009).

136 Petros Mavroidis, Trade in Goods (1st ed.) 18 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2007) [emphasis in original].

137 Marion Jansen et al. (eds), The Use of Economics in International Trade and Investment Disputes 6 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; 2017).

138 On the legitimacy of WTO law, see Joseph Weiler, “The Rule of Lawyers and the Ethos of Diplomats” 35 J.W.T. 191 (2001); Robert Howse, “Adjudicative Legitimacy and Treaty Interpretation in International Trade Law” in Joseph Weiler (ed.), The EU, the WTO and the NAFTA 35 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2000).

139 Frédéric Mégret also notes, however, that there have been sustained efforts recently to identify justice as a basis for international law. Mégret notes that this consists of trying to identify “an intrinsic justice to at least some forms of law,” or the idea that justice might arise in “international law based on the commutative exchange of obligations over time” or in “attempts to elucidate international law as based or deserving to be based on a form of deontological or consequentialist morality.” Frédéric Mégret, “Justice” in Jean d’Aspremont & Sahib Singh (eds), Concepts for International Law 585 at 600–601 (Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham; 2019).

140 A cosmopolitan account of justice typically holds that every human being has standing as the ultimate unit of moral concern and is entitled to equal consideration of their interests no matter what other affiliations, especially national affiliations, they might have. See Martha Nussbaum, “Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism” in Joshua Cohen (ed.), For Love of Country? 3 (Beacon Press, Boston; 1996) and Thomas Pogge in Thomas Pogge, “Concluding Reflections” in Gillian Brock (ed.), Cosmopolitanism versus Non-Cosmopolitanism 294 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2013).

141 Gabrielle Marceau, “WTO Dispute Settlement and Human Rights” 13:4 E.J.I.L. 753 at 756 (2002).

142 Steven Ratner, The Thin Justice of International Law (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2015) (arguing that the standard of international justice is based largely on principles of promotion of interstate peace and respect for basic human rights, with some room for deontological considerations in limited situations beyond these. The “thin” justice of international law is not as thick as that minimally demanded in domestic politics nor is it the limit for justice that should be striven for in the international realm, “but it is justice deserving of the name – one justifiable from an impartial perspective and, indeed, broadly consistent with a cosmopolitan vision of the world.” Footnote Ibid. at 9).

Justice in society in relation to its constituent members is a concept that can only be determined in the context of their socio-juridical status in that society. At a time when slaves were not regarded as legitimate elements of society, the problem of social justice in relation to slaves was not on the conscience of the people. … In the context of international society, this would mean that the conception of justice in a given situation could vary depending on whether it was viewed primarily in relation to sovereign states as the constituent members of society in the sense of the community of nations, or in relation to individuals (or groups of individuals) as the real component elements of society in the sense of the global community. In the context of the traditional Westphalian legal order where sovereign states are the basic constituent units of society, justice in international public order as an objective to be realized has always been conceived of primarily in relation to the sovereign states.

(Hisashi Owada, “Some Reflections on Justice in a Globalizing World” 97 Am. Soc. Int’l L. Proc. 181 at 188 (2003))

144 There is an entire field of institutional rule-making in the WTO law that often interacts symbiotically with WTO dispute settlement results and which is little referenced here. For a worthy account of WTO rule-making, see Mary Footer, An Institutional and Normative Analysis of the World Trade Organization (Martinus Nijhoff, Leiden; 2006).

145 Ronald Dworkin, Justice in Robes 57 (Belknap Press, Cambridge, MA; 2006).

146 Philip Allott has described theory’s “hegemonic explanatory power”: see Allott, The Health of Nations 143.

147 Edmund Wilson, Letters to a Young Scientist 91 (Liveright Publishing, New York; 2013) (“The conventional wisdom holds that science of the future will be more and more the product of ‘teamthink,’ multiple minds put in close contact. It is certainly the case that fewer and fewer solitary authors publish research articles in premier journals such as Nature and Science.”).

148 See Benedict Kingsbury, “The International Legal Order” in Peter Cane & Mark Tushnet (eds), Oxford Handbook of Legal Studies 271 at 294 (Oxford University Press, Oxford; 2003).

149 Kuhn observed that theories “gain their status because they are more successful than their competitors in solving a few problems that the group of practitioners has come to recognize as acute.” Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 23 (University of Chicago Press, Chicago; 1962) [emphasis added].

Figure 0

Figure 1.1 A communitarian theory outline

Figure 1

Figure 1.2 A theory of community

Figure 2

Figure 1.3 A theory of community and justice

Figure 3

Figure 1.4 The structure of justice

Figure 4

Figure 1.5 A communitarian theory of law (preliminary)

Figure 5

Figure 1.6 A communitarian theory of law

Accessibility standard: Unknown

Accessibility compliance for the HTML of this book is currently unknown and may be updated in the future.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge-org.demo.remotlog.com is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • A Theory of WTO Law
  • Chios Carmody, University of Western Ontario
  • Book: A Communitarian Theory of WTO Law
  • Online publication: 14 December 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9780511843280.002
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • A Theory of WTO Law
  • Chios Carmody, University of Western Ontario
  • Book: A Communitarian Theory of WTO Law
  • Online publication: 14 December 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9780511843280.002
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • A Theory of WTO Law
  • Chios Carmody, University of Western Ontario
  • Book: A Communitarian Theory of WTO Law
  • Online publication: 14 December 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9780511843280.002
Available formats
×